04.06.2014 Views

Volu m e II - Purdue University Calumet

Volu m e II - Purdue University Calumet

Volu m e II - Purdue University Calumet

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

A third possibility could be where choosing needs only an effect and no cause. Sure, it is possible<br />

imagine a world where things manifest into existence causelessly. Imagine where electronics, animals, or<br />

paintings by Salvador Dali pop into and out of existence without consistency or order. These would still be<br />

effects of some sort, being instances of changed states of affairs. But could this be true of our decisions?<br />

How could we be held responsible for a decision appearing in our heads uncaused? Could we blame our<br />

decision on its causeless, unpredictable nature? This seems as problematic as indetermism. There could not<br />

be an explanation for why one thing happened over any other thing. Furthermore, in the known world,<br />

there is not one other example of this type of causation (or should I say non-causation). If this could come<br />

about inside our heads, why doesn’t it appear anywhere else? It seems that events in the universe do not<br />

happen ex nihilo. I would not grant this possibility to decision making.<br />

The fourth and final possibility I will discuss is self-causation, where cause and effect either happen<br />

simultaneously, or they are identical. The problem with self-causation is that it contradicts itself. If<br />

something were to cause itself to exist, it must exist at a time when it does not exist. It is impossible for<br />

something to exist while it does not exist. Self-causation is not a possible explanation.<br />

So far, I have attempted to show decision making governed by determinism, indeterminism, or<br />

non-determinism does not allow for the real possibility of making different choices. In any of the cases<br />

above, the agent cannot do anything other then causal laws govern, and in situations where they do, the<br />

causal laws do not fit our world. So what happens to the problem of intuited freedom? Should we redo our<br />

analysis as van Inwagen suggests? I think the logic expressed above is sound. Instead, we should disregard<br />

the concept of metaphysical freedom.<br />

Let’s look closer. How does van Inwagen come to the conclusion that freedom is intuitively<br />

obvious? He does so by appealing to our sense of choosing between two possibilities, and our belief that we<br />

have the ability to do either choice. Choices seem real to us, but it is possible that they are illusory. Our<br />

perceptions are flawed in many ways; perhaps this is one of them. Consider color for example. It appears<br />

147

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!