11.07.2015 Views

2DkcTXceO

2DkcTXceO

2DkcTXceO

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

260 Conditioning is the issueHaar prior, here simply given by p(θ) = 1. For instance, the optimal conditionalfrequentist estimator of θ under squared error loss would simply be theposterior mean with respect to p(θ) = 1, namely∫ ∏ n θi=1 ˆθ =f(x i − θ)1dθ∫ ∏ ni=1 f(x i − θ)1dθ ,which is also known as Pitman’s estimator.Having a model with a group-invariance structure leaves one in an incrediblypowerful situation, and this happens with many of our most commonstatistical problems (mostly from an estimation perspective). The difficultiesof the conditional frequentist perspective are (i) finding the right strength ofevidence statistic S, and (ii) carrying out the conditional frequentist computation.But, if one has a group-invariant model, these difficulties can be bypassedbecause theory says that the optimal conditional frequentist answer is the answerobtained from the much simpler Bayesian analysis with the right-Haarprior.Note that the conditional frequentist and Bayesian answers will have differentinterpretations. For instance both approaches would produce the same95% confidence set, but the conditional frequentist would say that the frequentistcoverage, conditional on S (and also unconditionally), is 95%, while theBayesian would say the set has probability .95 of actually containing θ. Alsonote that it is not automatically true that analysis conditional on ancillarystatistics is optimal; see, e.g., Brown (1990).23.5.3 Conditional frequentist testingUpon rejection of the H 0 in unconditional Neyman–Pearson testing, one reportsthe same error probability α regardless of where the test statistic is inthe rejection region. This has been viewed as problematical by many, and isone of the main reasons for the popularity of p-values. But as we saw earlier,p-values do not satisfy the frequentist principle, and so are not the conditionalfrequentist answer.AtrueconditionalfrequentistsolutiontotheproblemwasproposedinBerger et al. (1994), with modification (given below) from Sellke et al. (2001)and Wolpert (1996). Suppose that we wish to test that the data X arises fromthe simple (i.e., completely specified) hypotheses H 0 : f = f 0 or H 1 : f = f 1 .The recommended strength of evidence statistic isS = max{p 0 (x),p 1 (x)},where p 0 (x) isthep-value when testing H 0 versus H 1 , and p 1 (x) isthepvaluewhen testing H 1 versus H 0 . It is generally agreed that smaller p-valuescorrespond to more evidence against an hypothesis, so this use of p-valuesin determining the strength of evidence statistic is natural. The frequentist

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!