12.07.2015 Views

Literatur zur Tugendethik Bibliography on Virtue ... - Academic Room

Literatur zur Tugendethik Bibliography on Virtue ... - Academic Room

Literatur zur Tugendethik Bibliography on Virtue ... - Academic Room

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<str<strong>on</strong>g>Literatur</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>zur</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g><str<strong>on</strong>g>Bibliography</str<strong>on</strong>g> <strong>on</strong> <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics (Last Update: 27.01.11)Jörg Schroth (jschrot@gwdg.de)Alphabetische Ordnung / alphabetical order:Chr<strong>on</strong>ologische Ordnung / reverse chr<strong>on</strong>ological order:http://www.ethikseite.de/bib/bvirtue.pdfhttp://www.ethikseite.de/bib/cvirtue.pdf1988 [1] Ackerman, Felicia (1988): A Man by Nothing Is so Well Betrayed as by His Manners?Politeness as a <strong>Virtue</strong>, in Midwest Studies in Philosophy Vol. XIII: Ethical Theory:Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. und HowardK. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 250–58.1988 [2] Adams, Robert M. (1988): Comm<strong>on</strong> Projects and Moral <strong>Virtue</strong>, in Midwest Studies inPhilosophy Vol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A.French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 297–307.2006 [3] Adams, Robert M. (2006): A Theory of <strong>Virtue</strong>. Excellence in Being for the Good, Oxford. 12010 [4] Adams, Robert M. (2010): A Theory of <strong>Virtue</strong>: Introductory Remarks, Philosophical Studies1“The distinguished philosopher Robert M. Adams presents a major work <strong>on</strong> virtue, which is <strong>on</strong>ce again acentral topic in ethical thought. A Theory of <strong>Virtue</strong> is a systematic, comprehensive framework for thinkingabout the moral evaluati<strong>on</strong> of character. Many recent attempts to stake out a place in moral philosophy forthis c<strong>on</strong>cern define virtue in terms of its benefits for the virtuous pers<strong>on</strong> or for human society moregenerally. In Part One of this book Adams presents and defends a c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of virtue as intrinsicexcellence of character, worth prizing for its own sake and not <strong>on</strong>ly for its benefits. In the other two parts headdresses two challenges to the ancient idea of excellence of character. One challenge arises from theimportance of altruism in modern ethical thought, and the questi<strong>on</strong> of what altruism has to do with intrinsicexcellence. Part Two argues that altruistic benevolence does indeed have a crucial place in excellence ofcharacter, but that moral virtue should also be expected to involve excellence in being for other goodsbesides the well-being (and the rights) of other pers<strong>on</strong>s. It explores relati<strong>on</strong>s am<strong>on</strong>g cultural goods, pers<strong>on</strong>alrelati<strong>on</strong>ships, <strong>on</strong>e’s own good, and the good of others, as objects of excellent motives. The other challenge,the subject of Part Three of the book, is typified by doubts about the reality of moral virtue, arising fromexperiments and c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s in social psychology. Adams explores in detail the prospects for an empiricallyrealistic c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of excellence of character as an object of moral aspirati<strong>on</strong>, endeavor, and educati<strong>on</strong>. Heargues that such a c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> will involve renunciati<strong>on</strong> of the ancient thesis of the unity or mutualimplicati<strong>on</strong> of all virtues, and acknowledgment of sufficient ‘moral luck’ in the development of anyindividual’s character to make virtue very largely a gift, rather than an individual achievement, thoughn<strong>on</strong>etheless excellent and admirable for that.C<strong>on</strong>tents: Part One: What Is <strong>Virtue</strong>? 1. Introducti<strong>on</strong> 2. Excellence in Being for the Good 3. Wickedness andVices 4. <strong>Virtue</strong> and its Benefits Part Two: Self and Other 5. Altruism 6. Comm<strong>on</strong> Projects 7. Self-Love andthe Vices of Self-Preference Part Three: Are There Really Any <strong>Virtue</strong>s? 8. Moral Inc<strong>on</strong>sistency 9. MoralFrailty and Moral Luck 10. Do the <strong>Virtue</strong>s All Imply Each Other? 11. Plural and Integrated <strong>Virtue</strong> 12. Can<strong>Virtue</strong> Be Taught?”1


2003 [13] Annas, Julia (2003): The Structure of <strong>Virtue</strong>, in Intellectual <strong>Virtue</strong> – Perspectives from Ethicsand Epistemology, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Micheal DePaul und Linda Zagzebski, Oxford, S. 15–33.2004 [14] Annas, Julia (2004): Being Virtuous and Doing the Right Thing, Proceedings and Addresses ofthe American Philosophical Associati<strong>on</strong> 78 (2), S. 61–75.2005 [15] Annas, Julia (2005): Comments <strong>on</strong> John Doris’s Lack of Character, Philosophy andPhenomenological Research 71, S. 636–42. – Vgl. dazu: [120].2005 [16] Annas, Julia (2005): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics: What Kind of Naturalism?, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Old and New,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Stephen M. Gardiner, Ithaca, S. 11–29.2008 [17] Annas, Julia (2008): The Phenomenology of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences7, S. 21–34. 41958 [18] Anscombe, G. E. M. (1958): Modern Moral Philosophy, Philosophy 33, S. 1–19. Wiederabgedrucktin Anscombe, Collected Philosophical Papers, Vol. 3: Ethics, Religi<strong>on</strong> andPolitics, Oxford 1981, S. 26–42, in Anscombe, Human Life, Acti<strong>on</strong> and Ethics. Essaysby G. E. M. Anscombe, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Mary Geach und Luke Gormally, Exeter 2005, S.169–94 sowie in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp und Michael Slote, Oxford 1997,S. 26–44. – Moderne Moralphilosophie, in Seminar: Sprache und Ethik. ZurEntwicklung der Metaethik, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Günther Grewendorf und Georg Meggle,Frankfurt a. M. 1974, S. 217–43.1992 [19] Anzenbacher, Arno (1992): Einführung in die Ethik, Düsseldorf, S. 135–50 („Tugend“).2008 [20] Appiah, Kwame Anth<strong>on</strong>y (2008): Experiments in Ethics, Cambridge, Mass., S. 33–72 (“TheCase against Character”).2008 [21] Arjo<strong>on</strong>, Surendra (2008): Rec<strong>on</strong>ciling Situati<strong>on</strong>al Social Psychology with <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Inter-4“What is it like to be a good pers<strong>on</strong>? I examine and reject suggesti<strong>on</strong>s that this will involve having thoughtswhich have virtue or being a good pers<strong>on</strong> as part of their c<strong>on</strong>tent, as well as suggesti<strong>on</strong>s that it might be thepresence of feelings distinct from the virtuous pers<strong>on</strong>’s thoughts. Is there, then, anything after all to thephenomenology of virtue? I suggest that an answer is to be found in looking to Aristotle’s suggesti<strong>on</strong> thatvirtuous activity is pleasant to the virtuous pers<strong>on</strong>. I try to do this, using the work of the c<strong>on</strong>temporary socialpsychologist Mihalyi Csikszentmihalyi and his work <strong>on</strong> the ‘flow experience’. Crucial here is the point thatI c<strong>on</strong>sider accounts of virtue which take it to have the structure of a practical expertise or skill. It is whenwe are most engaged in skilful complex activity that the activity is experienced as ‘unimpeded’, inAristotle’s terms, or as ‘flow’. This experience does not, as might at first appear, preclude thoughtfulinvolvement and reflecti<strong>on</strong>. Although we can say what in general the phenomenology of virtue is like, eachof us <strong>on</strong>ly has some more or less dim idea of it from the extent to which we are virtuous – that is, for mostof us, not very much.”3


nati<strong>on</strong>al Journal of Management Reviews 10, S. 221–43. 52005 [22] Arpaly, Nomy (2005): Comments <strong>on</strong> Lack of Character by John Doris, Philosophy and PhenomenologicalResearch 71, S. 643–47. – Vgl. dazu: [120].2000 [23] Athanassoulis, Nafsika (2000): A Resp<strong>on</strong>se to Harman: <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Character Traits, Proceedingsof the Aristotelian Society 100, S. 215–21. – Zu [171]. Vgl. dazu [172].1995 [24] Audi, Robert (1995): Acting from <strong>Virtue</strong>, Mind 104, S. 449–71. Wiederabgedruckt in Audi,Moral Knowledge and Ethical Character, New York, Oxford, S. 174–92.1988 [25] Audi, Robert (1998): A Liberal Theory of Civic <strong>Virtue</strong>, in <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> EllenFrankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr. und Jeffrey Paul, Cambridge, S. 149–70.2009 [26] Audi, Robert (2009): Moral <strong>Virtue</strong> and Reas<strong>on</strong>s for Acti<strong>on</strong>, Philosophical Issues 19, S. 1–20.2010 [27] Axtell, Guy (2010): Agency Ascripti<strong>on</strong>s in Ethics and Epistemology: Or, NavigatingIntersecti<strong>on</strong>s, Narrow and Broad, Metaphilosophy 41, S. 73–94. 62000 [28] Bächli, Andreas/Graeser, Andreas (2000): Tugend, in dies., Grundbegriffe der antiken Philosophie.Ein Lexik<strong>on</strong>, Stuttgart, S. 216–21.1996 [29] Badhwar, Neera K. (1996): The Limited Unity of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Nous 30, S. 306–29.1997 [30] Badhwar, Neera K. (1997): Self-Interest and <strong>Virtue</strong>, Social Philosophy and Policy 14, S. 226–63.56“For the past four decades, debate has occurred in respect of situati<strong>on</strong>al social psychology and virtue ethics.This paper attempts to rec<strong>on</strong>cile this debate. Situati<strong>on</strong>ists propose a fragmentati<strong>on</strong> theory of character (eachpers<strong>on</strong> has a whole range of dispositi<strong>on</strong>s, each of which has a restricted situati<strong>on</strong>al applicati<strong>on</strong>) and do notsubscribe to a regularity theory of character (behaviour is regulated by l<strong>on</strong>g-term dispositi<strong>on</strong>s). In order tosupport this view, they cite a number of experiments. It is proposed that the substantive claims made bysituati<strong>on</strong>ist social psychologists, for the most part, do not undermine or disagree with an Aristotelian virtueethics perspective, but stem from a misunderstanding of c<strong>on</strong>cepts of moral character, faulty c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s andgeneralizati<strong>on</strong>s in respect of experimental results. Situati<strong>on</strong>ists take a narrow view of character andmorality. Evidence from organizati<strong>on</strong>al behaviour and managerial research literature supports the view thatboth situati<strong>on</strong>al (organizati<strong>on</strong>al) features and inner characteristics (including virtues) are powerfulinfluences and determinants of morally upright and morally deviant behaviour. The role of practicaljudgement in bridging these views is discussed. As a way forward in rec<strong>on</strong>ciling situati<strong>on</strong>al socialpsychology with virtue ethics, the paper proposes an Aristotelian–Thomistic framework to overcome someof the problems associated with inadequate regulative ideals in building a normative moral theory.”“In this article, the logic and functi<strong>on</strong>s of character-trait ascripti<strong>on</strong>s in ethics and epistemology is compared,and two major problems, the “generality problem” for virtue epistemologies and the “global trait problem”for virtue ethics, are shown to be far more similar in structure than is comm<strong>on</strong>ly acknowledged. Bey<strong>on</strong>d theaporia of character-trait ascripti<strong>on</strong> and between the Scylla and Charybdis that virtue theories are faced within each field of philosophy, we find our passage by making full and explicit use of the “narrow-broadspectrum of trait ascripti<strong>on</strong>,” and by accounting for the various uses of it in an inquiry-pragmatist account.In virtue theories informed by inquiry pragmatism, the agential habits and abilities deemed salient inexplanati<strong>on</strong>s/evaluati<strong>on</strong>s of agents in particular cases, and the determinati<strong>on</strong> of the relevant domains andc<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s that an agent’s habit or ability is reliably efficacious in, is determined by pragmatic c<strong>on</strong>cernsrelated to our evaluative epistemic practices.”4


2009 [31] Badhwar, Neera K. (2009): The Milgram Experiments, Learned Helplessness, and CharacterTraits, Journal of Ethics 13, S. 257–89. 71992 [32] Baechler, Jean (1992): <strong>Virtue</strong>: Its Nature, Exigency, and Acquisiti<strong>on</strong>, in <strong>Virtue</strong> (Nomos 34),hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> John W. Chapman und William A. Galst<strong>on</strong>, New York, S. 25–48.2007 [33] Baehr, Jas<strong>on</strong> (2007): On the Reliability of Moral and Intellectual <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Metaphilosophy 38, S.456–70. 82010 [34] Baehr, Jas<strong>on</strong> (2010): Epistemic Malevolence, Metaphilosophy 41, S. 189–213. 91992 [35] Baier, Annette (1992): Some <strong>Virtue</strong>s of Resident Alienage, in <strong>Virtue</strong> (Nomos 34), hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> JohnW. Chapman und William A. Galst<strong>on</strong>, New York, S. 291–308.1988 [36] Baier, Kurt (1988): Radical <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Midwest Studies in Philosophy Vol. XIII: EthicalTheory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. undHoward K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 126–35.1998 [37] Barcalow, Emmett (1998): Moral Philosophy. Theories and Issues, Belm<strong>on</strong>t, CA, 2. Auflage, S.98–124 (“The Good Pers<strong>on</strong>: <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice”).1985 [38] Bar<strong>on</strong>, M. (1985): Varieties of Ethics of <strong>Virtue</strong>, American Philosophical Quarterly 22, S. 47–789“The Milgram and other situati<strong>on</strong>ist experiments support the real-life evidence that most of us are highlyakratic and heter<strong>on</strong>omous, and that Aristototelian virtue is not global. Indeed, like global theoreticalknowledge, global virtue is psychologically impossible because it requires too much of finite human beingswith finite powers in a finite life; virtue can <strong>on</strong>ly be domain-specific. But unlike local, situati<strong>on</strong>-specificvirtues, domain-specific virtues entail some general understanding of what matters in life, and arec<strong>on</strong>nected c<strong>on</strong>ceptually and causally to our traits in other domains. The experiments also make us aware ofhow easily unobtrusive situati<strong>on</strong>al factors can tap our susceptibilities to obedience, c<strong>on</strong>formity,irresp<strong>on</strong>sibility, cruelty, or indifference to others’ welfare, thereby empowering us to change ourselves forthe better. Thus, they advance the Socratic project of living the examined life. I note a remarkable parallelbetween the results of the baseline Milgram experiments and the results of the learned helplessnessexperiments by Martin Seligman et al. This provides fresh insight into the psychology and character of theobedient Milgram subjects, and I use this insight to argue that pusillanimity, as Aristotle c<strong>on</strong>ceives of it, ispart of a complete explanati<strong>on</strong> of the behavior of the obedient Milgram subjects.”“I examine here whether reliability is a defining feature of (moral or intellectual) virtues. I argue (1) thatreliability is not a defining feature of a virtue where virtues are c<strong>on</strong>ceived (as they often are) as “pers<strong>on</strong>alexcellences,” but (2) that there is another (also intuitive and familiar) c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of a virtue according towhich reliability is a defining feature. I also argue (3) that even <strong>on</strong> the former c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>, a certain rati<strong>on</strong>albelief pertaining to reliability is essential and (4) that reliability itself, while not a defining feature of avirtue thus c<strong>on</strong>ceived, nevertheless is a c<strong>on</strong>comitant of it.”“Against the background of a great deal of structural symmetry between intellectual and moral virtue andvice, it is a surprising fact that what is arguably the central or paradigm moral vice – that is, moralmalevolence or malevolence proper – has no obvious or well-known counterpart am<strong>on</strong>g the intellectualvices. The noti<strong>on</strong> of “epistemic malevolence” makes no appearance <strong>on</strong> any standard list of intellectualvices; nor is it central to our ordinary ways of thinking about intellectual vice. In this essay, I argue thatthere is such a thing as epistemic malevolence and offer an account of its basic character and structure.Doing so requires a good deal of attenti<strong>on</strong> to malevolence simpliciter. In the final secti<strong>on</strong> of the essay, Ioffer an explanati<strong>on</strong> of our relative unfamiliarity with this trait.”5


53.2010 [39] Battaly, Heather (2010): Introducti<strong>on</strong>: <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, Metaphilosophy 41 (Special Issue:<strong>Virtue</strong> And Vice, Moral And Epistemic), S. 1–21. 102010 [40] Battaly, Heather (2010): Epistemic Self-Indulgence, Metaphilosophy 41, S. 214–34. 111997 [41] Baur, Michael (Hrsg.) (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong>s and <strong>Virtue</strong> Theories, Washingt<strong>on</strong>, D.C: Catholic Univ. ofAmerica Press (Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Associati<strong>on</strong> 71).2007 [42] Baxley, Anne Margaret (2007): The Price of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88, S. 40–23. 121994 [43] Beauchamp, Tom L./Childress, James F. (1994): Principles of Biomedical Ethics, New York,Oxford, 4. Aufl., S. 62–69 (“Character Ethics: <strong>Virtue</strong>-Based Theory”).1975 [44] Becker, Lawrence C. (1975): The Neglect of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Ethics 85, S. 110–22. 1310111213“This introducti<strong>on</strong> to the collecti<strong>on</strong> <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, Moral and Epistemic addresses three main questi<strong>on</strong>s:(1) What is a virtue theory in ethics or epistemology? (2) What is a virtue? and (3) What is a vice? (1) Itsuggests that a virtue theory takes the virtues and vices of agents to be more fundamental than evaluati<strong>on</strong>sof acts or beliefs, and defines right acts or justified beliefs in terms of the virtues. (2) It argues that there aretwo important but different c<strong>on</strong>cepts of virtue: virtues are qualities that attain good ends, and virtues arequalities that involve good motives. (3) Accordingly, vices are qualities that either fail to attain good endsor involve bad motives. Finally, the introducti<strong>on</strong> summarizes the eleven essays in the collecti<strong>on</strong>, which aredivided into four secti<strong>on</strong>s: the Structure of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and <strong>Virtue</strong> Epistemology; <strong>Virtue</strong> and C<strong>on</strong>text;<strong>Virtue</strong> and Emoti<strong>on</strong>; and <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Vices.”“I argue in this essay that there is an epistemic analogue of moral self-indulgence. Secti<strong>on</strong> 1 analyzesAristotle’s noti<strong>on</strong> of moral temperance, and its corresp<strong>on</strong>ding vices of self-indulgence and insensibility.Secti<strong>on</strong> 2 uses Aristotle’s noti<strong>on</strong> of moral self-indulgence as a model for epistemic self-indulgence. I arguethat <strong>on</strong>e is epistemically self-indulgent <strong>on</strong>ly if <strong>on</strong>e either: (ESI1) desires, c<strong>on</strong>sumes, and enjoys appropriateand inappropriate epistemic objects; or (ESI2) desires, c<strong>on</strong>sumes, and enjoys epistemic objects atappropriate and inappropriate times; or (ESI3) desires and enjoys epistemic objects too frequently, or to aninappropriately high degree, or c<strong>on</strong>sumes too much of them. We need not look far to locate theepistemically self-indulgent: philosophers, especially skeptics, are likely candidates.”“Aristotle famously held that there is a crucial difference between the pers<strong>on</strong> who merely acts rightly andthe pers<strong>on</strong> who is wholehearted in what she does. He captures this c<strong>on</strong>trast by insisting <strong>on</strong> a distincti<strong>on</strong>between c<strong>on</strong>tinence and full virtue. One way of accounting for the important difference here is to supposethat, for the genuinely virtuous pers<strong>on</strong>, the requirements of virtue “silence” competing reas<strong>on</strong>s for acti<strong>on</strong>. Iargue that the silencing interpretati<strong>on</strong> is not compelling. As Aristotle rightly saw, virtue can have a cost,and a mark of the wise pers<strong>on</strong> is that she recognizes it.”“Modern moral philosophy has generally neglected the c<strong>on</strong>cept of virtue as <strong>on</strong>e which should be central tomoral theorizing. Some reas<strong>on</strong>s for the neglect are menti<strong>on</strong>ed; some sources of regret for the neglect areexplained; and six illustrati<strong>on</strong>s of the usefulness of the c<strong>on</strong>cept of virtue in moral theorizing are developedin more detail: 1) On defining the good pers<strong>on</strong>; 2) On defining standards of performance; 3) On excuses; 4)On rescue vs preventive acti<strong>on</strong>; 5) On civil disobedience; 6) On torture, terrorism and strategic bombing.The point of the paper is not to argue that the c<strong>on</strong>cept of virtue should supplant the c<strong>on</strong>cepts of duty andvalue, but merely to show that there are good reas<strong>on</strong>s for regretting its neglect, and good reas<strong>on</strong>s forencouraging its development.” (http://www.wm.edu/CAS/PHIL/Becker/lcb-bib.htm)6


Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76, S. 310–32. 162003 [52] Birnbacher, Dieter (2003): Analytische Einführung in die Ethik, Berlin, S. 203–6 („<str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>“).1994 [53] Blum, Lawrence A. (1994): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Community, in ders., Moral Percepti<strong>on</strong> andParticularity, Cambridge, S. 144–69.1996 [54] Blum, Lawrence A. (1996): Community and <strong>Virtue</strong>, in How Should One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the<strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 231–50.1996 [55] B<strong>on</strong>d, E. J. (1996): Ethics and Human Well-being. An Introducti<strong>on</strong> to Moral Philosophy,Oxford, S. 135–64.2001 [56] Borchers, Dagmar (2001): Die neue <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g> – Schritt <str<strong>on</strong>g>zur</str<strong>on</strong>g>ück im Zorn?, Paderborn.2008 [57] Borchers, Dagmar (2008): Moralische Exzellenz – Einführung in die <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, inGrundkurs Ethik. Band 1: Grundlagen, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Johannes S. Ach, Kurt Bayertz undLudwig Siep, Paderborn, S. 33–48.2005 [58] Bradely, Ben (2005): <strong>Virtue</strong> C<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, Utilitas 17, S. 282–98. 172004 [59] Brady, Michael (2004): Against Agent-Based <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Philosophical Papers 33, S. 1–10. 18161718“In recent years, there has been c<strong>on</strong>siderable debate in the literature c<strong>on</strong>cerning the existence of moralcharacter. One less<strong>on</strong> we should take away from these debates is that the c<strong>on</strong>cept of character, and the roleit plays in guiding our acti<strong>on</strong>s, is far more complex than most of us initially took it to be. Just as GilbertHarman, for example, makes a serious mistake in insisting, plain and simply, that there is no such thing ascharacter, defenders of character also make a mistake to the extent that they imply there is no problemraised by the psychological literature for either the c<strong>on</strong>cept of character or the nature of character-basedethics. My hope for this paper is to avoid both of these mistakes by first, exploring exactly what is thec<strong>on</strong>cept of character that is so firmly rooted in our philosophical and everyday thinking; and sec<strong>on</strong>d,exploring the implicati<strong>on</strong>s of the psychological literature for this appropriately understood c<strong>on</strong>cept ofcharacter. In so doing, I will come to a resoluti<strong>on</strong> that vindicates the existence of character, while at thesame time calls attenti<strong>on</strong> to the real and serious problem suggested by the psychological evidence. This, wewill see, is a problem of moral motivati<strong>on</strong>.”“<strong>Virtue</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism has been held by many prominent philosophers, but has never been properlyformulated. I criticize Julia Driver’s formulati<strong>on</strong> of virtue c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism and offer an alternative. Imaintain that according to the best versi<strong>on</strong> of virtue c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, attributi<strong>on</strong>s of virtue are reallydisguised comparis<strong>on</strong>s between two character traits, and the c<strong>on</strong>sequences of a trait in n<strong>on</strong>-actualcircumstances may affect its actual status as a virtue or vice. Such a view best enables the c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist toaccount for moral luck, unexemplified virtues, and virtues and vices involving the preventi<strong>on</strong> of goodnessand badness.”“Agent-based virtue ethics is a unitary normative theory according to which the moral status of acti<strong>on</strong>s isentirely dependent up<strong>on</strong> the moral status of an agent’s motives and character traits. One of the problems anysuch approach faces is to capture the comm<strong>on</strong>-sense distincti<strong>on</strong> between an agent’s doing the right thing,and her doing it for the right (or wr<strong>on</strong>g) reas<strong>on</strong>. In this paper I argue that agent-based virtue ethicsultimately fails to capture this kind of fine-grained distincti<strong>on</strong>, and to this extent ought to be rejected. Ifocus first <strong>on</strong> Michael Slote’s agent-based theory, according to which the moral status of acti<strong>on</strong>s dependsup<strong>on</strong> an agent’s actual motives, and argue that this leads to a paradox. I then c<strong>on</strong>sider whether the8


2005 [60] Brady, Michael S. (2005): The Value of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Philosophical Studies 125, S. 85–114. 192010 [61] Brady, Michael S. (2010): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Emoti<strong>on</strong>, and Attenti<strong>on</strong>, Metaphilosophy 41, S. 115–31. 201981 [62] Brandt, Richard B. (1981): Frankena and <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, M<strong>on</strong>ist 64, S. 271–92.1988 [63] Brandt, Richard B. (1988): The Structure of <strong>Virtue</strong>, in Midwest Studies in Philosophy Vol. XIII:Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling,Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 64–82. – Wiederabgedruckt in Brandt,Morality, Utilitarianism, and Rights, Cambridge 1992, S. 289–311.2011 [64] Cafaro, Philip/Sandler, R<strong>on</strong>ald (Hrsg.) (2011): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and the Envir<strong>on</strong>ment, Berlin, NewYork 2011. 212006 [65] Brännmark, Johan (2006): From <strong>Virtue</strong> to Decency, Metaphilosophy 37, S. 589–604. 2219202122‘counterfactual’ versi<strong>on</strong> of agent-basing favoured by Rosalind Hursthouse and Linda Zagzebski fares anybetter, and c<strong>on</strong>clude that it does not.”“Direct theories of the virtues maintain that an explanati<strong>on</strong> of why some virtuous trait counts as valuableshould ultimately appeal to the value of its characteristic motive or aim. In this paper I argue that, if we takethe idea of a direct approach to virtue theory seriously, we should favour a view according to which virtueinvolves knowledge. I raise problems for recent “agent-based” and “end-based” versi<strong>on</strong>s of the directapproach, show how my account proves preferable to these, and defend it against a number of objecti<strong>on</strong>s.”“The perceptual model of emoti<strong>on</strong>s maintains that emoti<strong>on</strong>s involve, or are at least analogous to,percepti<strong>on</strong>s of value. On this account, emoti<strong>on</strong>s purport to tell us about the evaluative realm, in much thesame way that sensory percepti<strong>on</strong>s inform us about the sensible world. An important development of thispositi<strong>on</strong>, prominent in recent work by Peter Goldie am<strong>on</strong>gst others, c<strong>on</strong>cerns the essential role that virtuoushabits of attenti<strong>on</strong> play in enabling us to gain perceptual and evaluative knowledge. I think that there aregood reas<strong>on</strong>s to be sceptical about this picture of virtue. In this essay I set out these reas<strong>on</strong>s, and explain thec<strong>on</strong>sequences this scepticism has for our understanding of the relati<strong>on</strong> between virtue, emoti<strong>on</strong>, andattenti<strong>on</strong>. In particular, I argue that our primary capacity for recognizing value is in fact a n<strong>on</strong>-emoti<strong>on</strong>alcapacity.”Editorial, Richard P. Haynes. – Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics Special Issue: Introducti<strong>on</strong>, Philip Cafaro. –Envir<strong>on</strong>mentalism and Public <strong>Virtue</strong>, Brian Treanor. – Forgivingness, Pessimism, and Envir<strong>on</strong>mentalCitizenship, Kathryn J. Norlock. – Radical Hope for Living Well in a Warmer World, Allen Thomps<strong>on</strong>. –Species Extincti<strong>on</strong> and the Vice for Learning <strong>Virtue</strong> of Thoughtlessness: The Importance of SpiritualExercises, Jeremy Bendik-Keymer. – The <strong>Virtue</strong> of Simplicity, Joshua Colt Gambrel and Philip Cafaro. –The Epistemic Demands of Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong>, Jas<strong>on</strong> Kawall. – Hume’s Knave and N<strong>on</strong>anthropocentric<strong>Virtue</strong>s, Paul Haught. – Heideggerian Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Christine Swant<strong>on</strong>. – Ethical Theoryand the Problem of Inc<strong>on</strong>sequentialism: Why Envir<strong>on</strong>mental Ethicists Should be <strong>Virtue</strong>-Oriented Ethicists,R<strong>on</strong>ald Sandler. – Patriotism as an Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong>, Philip Cafaro.Previously published in the Journal of Agricultural and Envir<strong>on</strong>mental Ethics 23 (2010).“In her work <strong>on</strong> virtue ethics Rosalind Hursthouse has formulated an Aristotelian criteri<strong>on</strong> of rightness thatunderstands rightness in terms of what the virtuous pers<strong>on</strong> would do. It is argued here that this kind ofcriteri<strong>on</strong> does not allow enough room for the category of the supererogatory and that right and wr<strong>on</strong>g shouldrather be understood in terms of the characteristic behavior of decent pers<strong>on</strong>s. Furthermore, it is suggestedthat this kind of approach has the added advantage of allowing <strong>on</strong>e to make sense of the centrality ofnegative precepts in comm<strong>on</strong>sense morality.”9


1997 [66] Brickhouse, Thomas C./Smith, Nicholas D. (1997): Socrates and the Unity of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s,Journal of Ethics 1, S. 311–24.2004 [67] Brown, Stephen R. (2004): Naturalized <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and the Epistemological Gap, Journal ofMoral Philosophy 1, S. 197–209.2008 [68] Brown, Stephen R. (2008): Moral <strong>Virtue</strong> and Nature: A Defense of Ethical Naturalism,L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>. 232002 [69] Brumlik, Micha (2002): Bildung und Glück. Versuch einer Theorie der Tugenden, Berlin,Wien. 242005 [70] Cafaro, Philip/Sandler, R<strong>on</strong>ald (Hrsg.) (2005): Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Lanham. 252007 [71] Calder, Todd (2007): Against C<strong>on</strong>sequentialist Theories of <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, Utilitas 19, S. 201–19. 26232425Table of C<strong>on</strong>tents: Acknowledgements. 1. Ethical Naturalism. 2. Natural Teleology. 3. Good HumanBeings. 4. Facts and values. 5. Moral <strong>Virtue</strong> and Nature. Works Cited.“What makes some<strong>on</strong>e a good human being? Is there an objective answer to this questi<strong>on</strong>, an answer thatcan be given in naturalistic terms? For ages philosophers have attempted to develop some sort of naturalisticethics. Against ethical naturalism, however, notable philosophers have c<strong>on</strong>tended that such projects areimpossible, due to the existence of some sort of ‘gap’ between facts and values. Others have suggested thatteleology, up<strong>on</strong> which many forms of ethical naturalism depend, is an outdated metaphysical c<strong>on</strong>cept.This book argues that a good human being is <strong>on</strong>e who has those traits the possessi<strong>on</strong> of which enablessome<strong>on</strong>e to achieve those ends natural to beings like us. Thus, the answer to the questi<strong>on</strong> of what makes agood human being is given in terms both objective and naturalistic. The author shows that neither ‘is-ought’gaps, nor objecti<strong>on</strong>s c<strong>on</strong>cerning teleology pose insurmountable problems for naturalistic virtue ethics. Thiswork is a much needed c<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong> to the <strong>on</strong>going debate about ethical theory and ethical virtue.”Inhalt: Vorbemerkung 7 Einleitung: Moralische Gefühle und Die Leichtigkeit des Seins 9 I. MenschlicheNatur und <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g> 29 II. Skizze einer Theorie des Lasters 57 III.Vertrauen und Scham – Grundzügeeiner Theorie moralischer Gefühle 65 IV. Evoluti<strong>on</strong>, Altruismus und Moral 82 V. Die Leidenschaft derPädagogik 102 VI. Glück und Lebenslauf 115 VII. Human<strong>on</strong>togenese und der Sinn des Lebens 128 VIII.Tugend und Charakter 143 IX. Die Tugenden 149 Gerechtigkeit 151 Mut 156 Mäßigung und Bes<strong>on</strong>nenheit167 Hoffnung 181 Glaube 197 Liebe 204 X. Freundschaft 241 XI. Tugend und demokratischer Charakter258 XII. Toleranz – Tugend der Citoyens? 281 Bibliographische Notiz 287 Anmerkungen.C<strong>on</strong>tents: Part One: Recognizing Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics: Introducti<strong>on</strong>: Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics(R<strong>on</strong>ald Sandler), The Emergence of Ecological <strong>Virtue</strong> Language (Louke van Wensveen), Thoreau,Leopold, and Cars<strong>on</strong>: Toward an Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics (Philip Cafaro). Part Two: Envir<strong>on</strong>mental<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics Theory: Ideals of Human Excellence and Preserving Natural Envir<strong>on</strong>ments (Thomas Hill, Jr.),Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics: Half the Truth but Dangerous as a Whole (Holmes Rolst<strong>on</strong>, III), <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethicsas Foundati<strong>on</strong>al for a Global Ethic (Laura Westra), A <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics Approach to Aldo Leopold's Land Ethic(Bill Shaw), <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Repugnant C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s (David Schmidtz and Matt Zwolinski), Part Three:Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong>s And Vices: Benevolence as an Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong> (Geoffrey Frasz), Glutt<strong>on</strong>y,Arrogance, Greed and Apathy: An Explorati<strong>on</strong> of Envir<strong>on</strong>mental Vice (Philip Cafaro), Religi<strong>on</strong> andEnvir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong> (Charles Taliaferro), Cardinal Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong>s (Louke van Wensveen), PartFour: The Applicati<strong>on</strong> Of Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong>: Synergistic Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong>s: C<strong>on</strong>sumerism andHuman Flourishing (Peter Wenz), A <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics Perspective <strong>on</strong> Genetically Modified Crops (R<strong>on</strong>aldSandler)10


2008 [72] Calhoun, Cheshire (2008): Reflecti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the Metavirtue of Sensitivity to Suffering, Hypatia 23,S. 182–88. – Zu [440].1994 [73] Callan, E. (1994): Impartiality and <strong>Virtue</strong>, Journal of Value Inquiry 28, S. 401–14.2004 [74] Card, Robert F. (2004): Pure Aretaic Ethics and Character, Journal of Value Inquiry 38, S. 473–84.1985 [75] Carr, David (1985): Two Kinds of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 85 (1984–5),S. 47–61.2003 [76] Carr, David (2003): Character and Moral Choice in the Cultivati<strong>on</strong> of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Philosophy 78, S.219–32. 272009 [77] Carr, David (2009): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Mixed Emoti<strong>on</strong>s and Moral Ambivalence, Philosophy 84, S. 31–46. 281999 [78] Carr, David/Steutel, Jan (Hrsg.) (1999): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Moral Educati<strong>on</strong>, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>.1990 [79] Casey, John (1990): Pagan <strong>Virtue</strong>. An Essay in Ethics, Oxford.1997 [80] Cates, Diana Fritz (1997): Choosing to Feel: <strong>Virtue</strong>, Friendship, and Compassi<strong>on</strong> for Friends,Notre Dame, Ind.2006 [81] Chappell, Timothy (2006): The Variety of Life and the Unity of Practical Wisdom, in Valuesand <strong>Virtue</strong>s: Aristotelianism in C<strong>on</strong>temporary Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Timothy Chappell,262728“C<strong>on</strong>sequentialist theories of virtue and vice, such as the theories of Jeremy Bentham and Julia Driver,characterize virtue and vice in terms of the c<strong>on</strong>sequential, or instrumental, properties of these charactertraits. There are two problems with theories of this sort. First they imply that, under the right circumstances,paradigmatic virtues, such as benevolence, are vices and paradigmatic vices, such as maliciousness, arevirtues. This is c<strong>on</strong>ceptually problematic. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, they say nothing about the intrinsic nature of the virtuesand vices, which is less than we could hope for from a theory of virtue and vice. Thus, we have reas<strong>on</strong> toreject c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist theories in favour of theories that characterize virtue and vice in terms of theintrinsic properties of these character traits. Aristotle and Thomas Hurka have theories this sort.”“It is central to virtue ethics both that morally sound acti<strong>on</strong> follows from virtuous character, and thatvirtuous character is itself the product of habitual right judgement and choice: that, in short, we choose ourmoral characters. However, any such view may appear to encounter difficulty in those cases of moralc<strong>on</strong>flict where an agent cannot simultaneously act (say) both h<strong>on</strong>estly and sympathetically, and in which thechoices of agents seem to favour the c<strong>on</strong>structi<strong>on</strong> of different moral characters. This paper argues, againstpossible counter-arguments, for a view of virtue ethics which embraces the diversity of moral character.”“Aristotelian virtue ethics invests emoti<strong>on</strong>s and feelings with much moral significance. However, the moraland other c<strong>on</strong>flicts that inevitably beset human life often give rise to states of emoti<strong>on</strong>al divisi<strong>on</strong> andambivalence with problematic implicati<strong>on</strong>s for any understanding of virtue as complete psychic unity ofcharacter and c<strong>on</strong>duct. For <strong>on</strong>e thing, any admissi<strong>on</strong> that the virtuous are prey to c<strong>on</strong>flicting passi<strong>on</strong>s anddesires may seem to threaten the crucial virtue ethical distincti<strong>on</strong> between the virtuous and the c<strong>on</strong>tinent.One recent attempt to sustain this distincti<strong>on</strong> – c<strong>on</strong>sidered in this paper – maintains that the c<strong>on</strong>trary-tovirtueemoti<strong>on</strong>s and desires of the virtuous (by c<strong>on</strong>trast with those of the c<strong>on</strong>tinent) must relinquish theirmotive power as reas<strong>on</strong>s for acti<strong>on</strong>. Following some attenti<strong>on</strong> to the psychological status of feelings andemoti<strong>on</strong>s – in particular their complex relati<strong>on</strong>s with cogniti<strong>on</strong> and reas<strong>on</strong> – this paper rejects this soluti<strong>on</strong>in favour of a more c<strong>on</strong>structive view of emoti<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>flict.”11


Oxford, S. 136–57.2009 [82] Chappell, Timothy (2009): Ethics and Experience. Life Bey<strong>on</strong>d Moral Theory, M<strong>on</strong>treal, S. 97–124 (“<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics”).2006 [83] Chappell, Timothy (Hrsg.) (2006): Values and <strong>Virtue</strong>s: Aristotelianism in C<strong>on</strong>temporary Ethics,Oxford. 291992 [84] Chapman, John W./Galst<strong>on</strong>, William A. (Hrsg.) (1992): <strong>Virtue</strong> (Nomos 34), New York.2009 [85] Christensen, Anne-Marie S. (2009): Getting It Right in Ethical Experience: John McDowell and<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Journal of Value Inquiry 43, S. 493–506.1998 [86] Churchland, Paul M. (1998): Toward a Cognitive Neurobiology of the Moral <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Topoi 17,S. 83–96.2010 [87] Clarke, Bridget (2010): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Disagreement, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13, S.273–91. 301990 [88] Clowney, D. (1990): <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Rules and the Foundati<strong>on</strong>s of Ethics, Philosophia 20, S. 49–68.1995 [89] Comte-Sp<strong>on</strong>ville, André (1995): Ermutigung zum unzeitgemäßen Leben. Ein kleines Brevier derTugenden und Werte, Reinbek bei Hamburg 1998.1988 [90] C<strong>on</strong>ly, Sarah (1988): Flourishing and the Failure of the Ethics of <strong>Virtue</strong>, in Midwest Studies inPhilosophy Vol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A.French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 83–96.2006 [91] Coope, Christopher Miles (2006): Modern <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Values and <strong>Virtue</strong>s: Aristotelianismin C<strong>on</strong>temporary Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Timothy Chappell, Oxford, S. 20–52.1975 [92] Cooper, John M. (1975): Reas<strong>on</strong> and Human Good in Aristotle, Indianapolis 1986.2930C<strong>on</strong>tents: Introducti<strong>on</strong>, Timothy Chappell. 1. Modern virtue ethics, Christopher Coope. 2. The admirablelife and the desirable life, Linda Zagzebski. 3. <strong>Virtue</strong> and rights in Aristotle’s best regime, Fred Miller. 4.The virtues and vices of virtue jurisprudence, Ant<strong>on</strong>y Duff. 5. Habituati<strong>on</strong> as mimêsis, Hallvard Fossheim.6. Moral incompetence, Adam Mort<strong>on</strong>. 7. The variety of life and the unity of practical wisdom, TimothyChappell. 8. Moral sense and virtue in Hume’s ethics , Paul Russell. 9. Can Nietzsche be both a virtueethicist and an existentialist?, Christine Swant<strong>on</strong>. 10. Manners, morals, and practical wisdom, Karen Stohr.11. The hardboiled detective as moralist, Sandrine Berges. 12. ‘Like the Bloom <strong>on</strong> Youths’: How pleasurecompletes our lives, Johan Braennmark. 13. Mixed determinates: pleasure, good, and truth, TheodoreScaltsas. 14. Three dogmas of desire, Talbot Brewer.“One of the most prominent strands in c<strong>on</strong>temporary work <strong>on</strong> the virtues c<strong>on</strong>sists in the attempt to developa distinctive – and compelling – account of practical reas<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> the basis of Aristotle’s ethics. In resp<strong>on</strong>se tothis project, several eminent critics have argued that the Aristotelian account encourages a dismissiveattitude toward moral disagreement. Given the importance of developing a mature resp<strong>on</strong>se todisagreement, the criticism is devastating if true. I examine this line of criticism closely, first elucidatingthe features of the Aristotelian account that motivate it, and then identifying two further features of theaccount that the criticism overlooks. These further features show the criticism to be entirely unwarranted.Once these features are acknowledged, a more promising line of criticism suggests itself – namely, that theAristotelian account does too little to help us to resolve disputes – but that line of objecti<strong>on</strong> will have to becarried out <strong>on</strong> quite different grounds.”12


1998 [93] Cooper, John M. (1998): The Unity of <strong>Virtue</strong>, in <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Ellen Frankel Paul,Fred D. Miller, Jr. und Jeffrey Paul, Cambridge, S. 233–74.2010 [94] Coplan, Amy (2010): Feeling Without Thinking: Less<strong>on</strong>s from the Ancients <strong>on</strong> Emoti<strong>on</strong> and<strong>Virtue</strong>-Acquisiti<strong>on</strong>, Metaphilosophy 41, S. 132–51. 311994 [95] Cordner, Christopher (1994): Aristotelian <strong>Virtue</strong> and its Limitati<strong>on</strong>s, Philosophy 69, 291–316.1991 [96] Cottingham, John (1991): The Ethics of Self-C<strong>on</strong>cern, Ethics 101, S. 798–817.1996 [97] Cottingham, John (1996): Partiality and the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, in How Should One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the<strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 57–76.2006 [98] Cox, Damian (2006): Agent-based Theories of Right Acti<strong>on</strong>, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice9, S. 505–15. 321992 [99] Crisp, Roger (1992): Utilitarianism and the Life of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Philosophical Quarterly 42, S. 139–60.1996 [100] Crisp, Roger (1996): Modern Moral Philosophy and the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, in How Should One Live?Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 1–18.1998 [101] Crisp, Roger (1998): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> EdwardCraig, Vol. 9, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, S. 622–26.2010 [102] Crisp, Roger (2010): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and <strong>Virtue</strong> Epistemology, Metaphilosophy 41, S. 22–40. 331996 [103] Crisp, Roger (Hrsg.) (1996): How Should One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Oxford.313233“By briefly sketching some important ancient accounts of the c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>s between psychology and moraleducati<strong>on</strong>, I hope to illuminate the significance of the c<strong>on</strong>temporary debate <strong>on</strong> the nature of emoti<strong>on</strong> and toreveal its stakes. I begin the essay with a brief discussi<strong>on</strong> of intellectualism in Socrates and the Stoics, andPlato’s and Posid<strong>on</strong>ius’s respective attacks against it. Next, I examine the two current leadingphilosophical accounts of emoti<strong>on</strong>: the cognitive theory and the n<strong>on</strong>cognitive theory. I maintain that then<strong>on</strong>cognitive theory better explains human behavior and experience and has more empirical support thanthe cognitive theory. In the third secti<strong>on</strong> of the essay I argue that recent empirical research <strong>on</strong> emoti<strong>on</strong>alc<strong>on</strong>tagi<strong>on</strong> and mirroring processes provides important new evidence for the n<strong>on</strong>cognitive theory. In thefinal secti<strong>on</strong>, I draw some preliminary c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>s about moral educati<strong>on</strong> and the acquisiti<strong>on</strong> of virtue.”“In this paper, I develop an objecti<strong>on</strong> to agent-based accounts of right acti<strong>on</strong>. Agent-based accounts of rightacti<strong>on</strong> attempt to derive moral judgment of acti<strong>on</strong>s from judgment of the inner quality of virtuous agentsand virtuous agency. A moral theory ought to be something that moral agents can permissibly use in moraldeliberati<strong>on</strong>. I argue for a principle that captures this intuiti<strong>on</strong> and show that, for a broad range of otherdirectedvirtues and motives, agent-based accounts of right acti<strong>on</strong> fail to satisfy this principle.”“The aim of this essay is to test the claim that epistemologists – virtue epistemologists in particular – havemuch to learn from virtue ethics. The essay begins with an outline of virtue ethics itself. This secti<strong>on</strong>c<strong>on</strong>cludes that a pure form of virtue ethics is likely to be unattractive, so the virtue epistemologist shouldexamine the "impure" views of real philosophers. Aristotle is usually held up as the paradigm virtueethicist. His doctrine of the mean is described, and it is explained how that doctrine can provide aframework for an account of epistemic virtue. The c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> of the essay is that a virtue epistemologybased <strong>on</strong> analogies with virtue ethics, though well worth developing and c<strong>on</strong>sidering, will face severalchallenges in fulfilling the significant promises that have been made <strong>on</strong> its behalf.”13


1997 [104] Crisp, Roger/Slote, Michael (Hrsg.) (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Oxford.1999 [105] Cullity, Garrett (1999): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Theory, and Warrant, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice2, S. 277–94.1994 [106] Darwall, Stephen (1994): From Morality to <strong>Virtue</strong> and Back?, Philosophy andPhenomenological Research 54, S. 695–701. (Zu M. Slote, From Morality to <strong>Virtue</strong>)2002 [107] Darwall, Stephen (Hrsg.) (2002): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Oxford.2003 [108] Das, Ram<strong>on</strong> (2003): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Right Acti<strong>on</strong>, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81, S.324–39. 341988 [109] Davis, Michael (1988): Civic <strong>Virtue</strong>, Corrupti<strong>on</strong>, and the Structure of Moral Theories, inMidwest Studies in Philosophy Vol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg.v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame,S. 352–66.1994 [110] DeMarco, Joseph P. (1994): A Coherence Theory in Ethics, Amsterdam, Atlanta, S. 54–60.1996 [111] DeMarco, Joseph P. (1996): Moral Theory. A C<strong>on</strong>temporary Overview, Bost<strong>on</strong>, S. 93–106.1975 [112] Dent, N. J. H. (1975): The Moral Psychology of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Cambridge.1991 [113] Den Uyl, Douglas J. (1991): The <strong>Virtue</strong> of Prudence, New York.2000 [114] DePaul, Michael (2000): Character Traits, <strong>Virtue</strong>s, and Vices: Are There N<strong>on</strong>e?, in Proceedingsof the Twentieth World C<strong>on</strong>gress of Philosophy, Vol. 9: Philosophy of Mind, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>Bernard Elevitch, Bowling Green.2003 [115] DePaul, Michael/Zagzebski, Linda (Hrsg.) (2003): Intellectual <strong>Virtue</strong> – Perspectives fromEthics and Epistemology, Oxford.2002 [116] Devettere, Raym<strong>on</strong>d J. (2002): Introducti<strong>on</strong> to <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. Insights of the Ancient Greeks,Washingt<strong>on</strong>, D. C.1998 [117] Doris, John M. (1998): Pers<strong>on</strong>s, Situati<strong>on</strong>s, and <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Nous 32, S. 504–30. – Vgl. dazu[399], [475].2002 [118] Doris, John M. (2002): Lack of Character. Pers<strong>on</strong>ality and Moral Behavior, Cambridge. – Vgl.dazu [15], [22], [278], [343], [397], [461], [476].2005 [119] Doris, John M. (2005): Précis of Lack of Character, Philosophy and PhenomenologicalResearch 71, S. 632–35.34“In this paper I evaluate some recent virtue-ethical accounts of right acti<strong>on</strong> [Hursthouse 1999; Slote 2001;Swant<strong>on</strong> 2001]. I argue that all are vulnerable to what I call the insularity objecti<strong>on</strong>: evaluating acti<strong>on</strong>requires attenti<strong>on</strong> to worldly c<strong>on</strong>sequences external to the agent, whereas virtue ethics is primarilyc<strong>on</strong>cerned with evaluating an agent’s inner states. More specifically, I argue that insofar as these accountsare successful in meeting the insularity objecti<strong>on</strong> they invite the circularity objecti<strong>on</strong>: they end up relyingup<strong>on</strong> putatively virtue-ethical c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s that themselves depend <strong>on</strong> unexplained judgments ofrightness. Such accounts thus face a dilemma that is characteristic of virtue-ethical accounts of right acti<strong>on</strong>.They avoid the insularity objecti<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong>ly at the cost of inviting the circularity objecti<strong>on</strong>: they becomeintuitively plausible roughly to the extent that they lose their distinctively virtue-ethical character.”14


2005 [120] Doris, John M. (2005): Replies: Evidence and Sensibility, Philosophy and PhenomenologicalResearch 71, S. 656–77.2010 [121] Doris, John M. (2010): Heated Agreement: Lack of Character as Being for the Good,Philosophical Studies 148, S. 135–46. – Zu [3]. Dazu: [5].2009 [122] Doviak, Daniel (2009): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Satisfacti<strong>on</strong> and Welfare Enhancement, Utilitas 21, S. 59–71. 351989 [123] Driver, Julia (1989): The <strong>Virtue</strong>s of Ignorance, Journal of Philosophy 86, S. 373–84.1994 [124] Driver, Julia (1994): A Critical Study of Michael Slote’s “From Morality to <strong>Virtue</strong>”, Nous 28, S.505–14.1995 [125] Driver, Julia (1995): M<strong>on</strong>keying with Motives: Agent-Basing <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Utilitas 7, S. 281–85.1996 [126] Driver, Julia (1996): The <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Human Nature, in How Should One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the<strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 111–29.2001 [127] Driver, Julia (2001): Uneasy <strong>Virtue</strong>, Cambridge. – Vgl. dazu: [305], [385].2002 [128] Driver, Julia (2002): Review of On <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics by Rosalind Hursthouse, Philosophical Review111, S. 122–27. – Zu2004 [129] Driver, Julia (2004): Resp<strong>on</strong>se to my Critics, Utilitas 16, S. 33–41. 36 – Zu [305], [385].2006 [130] Driver, Julia (2006): Ethics. The Fundamentals, Oxford, S. 136–53 (“<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics”).2006 [131] Driver, Julia (2006): <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory, in C<strong>on</strong>temporary Debates in Moral Theory, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>James Dreier, Oxford, S. 113–23.1993 [132] Elliot, David (1993): The Nature of <strong>Virtue</strong> and the Questi<strong>on</strong> of Its Primacy, Journal of Value Inquiry27, S. 317–30.2004 [133] Esser, Andrea Marlen (2004): Eine Ethik für Endliche. Kants Tugendlehre in der Gegenwart,Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt.3536“In ‘Is <strong>Virtue</strong> Its Own Reward?’ Wayne Sumner argues that (1) as a matter of necessity, virtue isintrinsically prudentially rewarding, and (2) if all else is equal, the virtuous will fare better than the n<strong>on</strong>virtuous.In this article, I reproduce and criticize those arguments. I offer several objecti<strong>on</strong>s to the argumentfor the first thesis; each objecti<strong>on</strong> makes the same basic point: c<strong>on</strong>trary to what Sumner assumes, certainc<strong>on</strong>tingent facts over and above a pers<strong>on</strong>’s being virtuous have to obtain if virtue is to issue in anyprudential reward. I object to Sumner’s sec<strong>on</strong>d thesis by arguing that moral neutrality can be at least aswelfare-enhancing as moral virtuosity. Finally, I argue that even if virtue were intrinsically rewarding in theway Sumner envisi<strong>on</strong>s, it would still be impossible to determine a priori whether adopting a virtuouslifestyle would be prudentially rati<strong>on</strong>al.”“This essay is a rejoinder to comments <strong>on</strong> Uneasy <strong>Virtue</strong> made by Onora O'Neill, John Skorupski, andMichael Slote in this issue. In Uneasy <strong>Virtue</strong> I presented criticisms of traditi<strong>on</strong>al virtue theory. I alsopresented an alternative - a c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist account of virtue, <strong>on</strong>e which is a form of ‘pure evaluati<strong>on</strong>alexternalism’. This type of theory holds that the moral quality of character traits is determined by factorsexternal to agency (e.g. c<strong>on</strong>sequences). All three commentators took excepti<strong>on</strong> to this account. Therefore,the bulk of my resp<strong>on</strong>se focuses <strong>on</strong> defending the externalist account of virtue presented in the finalchapters of Uneasy <strong>Virtue</strong>.”15


2007 [134] Everitt, Nicholas (2007): Some Problems with <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory, Philosophy 82, S. 275–99. 372009 [135] Eyl<strong>on</strong>, Yuval (2009): <strong>Virtue</strong> and C<strong>on</strong>tinence, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12, S. 137–51. 381980 [136] Fleming, Arthur (1980): Reviewing the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Ethics 90, S. 587–95.2006 [137] Fleming, Diana (2006): The Character of <strong>Virtue</strong>: Answering the Situati<strong>on</strong>ist Challenge to<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Ratio 19, S. 24–42. 39373839“<strong>Virtue</strong> ethics (VE for short) is currently so widely embraced that different versi<strong>on</strong>s of the theory can nowbe distinguished. Some of these are mapped out in Statman’s useful introducti<strong>on</strong> to his collecti<strong>on</strong>. There areenough of these versi<strong>on</strong>s to c<strong>on</strong>stitute a family, and c<strong>on</strong>sequently what they share is a family resemblancerather than agreement to a defining set of necessary and sufficient c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s. What I propose to do,therefore, is to criticise <strong>on</strong>e of the main versi<strong>on</strong>s of VE. Rosalind Hursthouse is the main prop<strong>on</strong>ent of theversi<strong>on</strong> which I will criticise. I choose her as a spokespers<strong>on</strong>, not because her versi<strong>on</strong> of VE is especiallyweak. On the c<strong>on</strong>trary, it is because she is <strong>on</strong>e of the leading protag<strong>on</strong>ists of VE, and because her writingsprovide a lucid, powerful and elegant expositi<strong>on</strong> of VE that her versi<strong>on</strong> of the theory is an appropriate objectof scrutiny.”“John McDowell argued that the virtuous pers<strong>on</strong> (VP) knows no temptati<strong>on</strong>: her percepti<strong>on</strong> of a situati<strong>on</strong>silences all competing motivati<strong>on</strong>s – be it fear in the face of danger or a str<strong>on</strong>g desire. The VP cannotrecognize any reas<strong>on</strong> to act n<strong>on</strong>-virtuously as a reas<strong>on</strong>, and is never inclined to act n<strong>on</strong>-virtuously. Thisview rests <strong>on</strong> the requirement that the VP rati<strong>on</strong>ally resp<strong>on</strong>d, and not merely react, to the envir<strong>on</strong>ment – itrests <strong>on</strong> the requirement that the relati<strong>on</strong> between the VP and the world (ethical requirements) must rule outthe possibility that the VP is a brain in a vat. I will argue that the opposite is true: virtue requires asensitivity to temptati<strong>on</strong>. The VP, as such, must be able to recognize reas<strong>on</strong>s for performing n<strong>on</strong>-virtuousacti<strong>on</strong>s as reas<strong>on</strong>s, and be inclined to perform them. She must find nothing human alien. This is so becausethe VP must possess the ability to understand n<strong>on</strong>-virtuous agents, and understanding necessarily involvesvulnerability to temptati<strong>on</strong>. Otherwise, it will be argued, the VP views the acti<strong>on</strong>s of others as determinedfrom outside the space of reas<strong>on</strong>s. But the VP, like any other pers<strong>on</strong>, must have the ability to view theacti<strong>on</strong>s of others as rati<strong>on</strong>al resp<strong>on</strong>ses to the envir<strong>on</strong>ment, not <strong>on</strong>ly as reacti<strong>on</strong>s to it. Put differently, theVP’s view of others must rule out the possibility that they are brains in a vat – the possibility that theiracti<strong>on</strong>s are merely caused, rather than justified, by the facts. Finally, it will be suggested that an amendedc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the VP can meet both requirements: view others as rati<strong>on</strong>ally resp<strong>on</strong>sive to the world, withoutrelinquishing its relati<strong>on</strong> to the facts.”“Neo-Aristotelian virtue ethics makes essential reference to the noti<strong>on</strong> of a stable, robust character-trait. Italso claims to be c<strong>on</strong>strained by at least a minimal degree of psychological realism. Recent developments inempirical psychology have drawn into questi<strong>on</strong> the evidence for the existence of such robust traits, arguingthat it rests <strong>on</strong> what has been called a ‘undamental attributi<strong>on</strong> error’. <strong>Virtue</strong> ethics has thus seemingly beenmade vulnerable to criticisms that it is essentially dependent <strong>on</strong> an err<strong>on</strong>eous, folk-psychological, noti<strong>on</strong> ofcharacter and, so, must either aband<strong>on</strong> their characteristic noti<strong>on</strong> of virtue or forego any pretensi<strong>on</strong>s topsychological realism.I develop a two-pr<strong>on</strong>ged resp<strong>on</strong>se to this objecti<strong>on</strong>. First, I argue that there is reas<strong>on</strong> to questi<strong>on</strong> much of theempirical evidence and that such evidence as does exist can easily be accommodated by virtue ethics. Next, Iargue that even if we allow that neo-Aristotelian virtue ethical theories does sometimes presuppose astr<strong>on</strong>ger c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of character-traits than is warranted by the evidence, this does not significantlyundermine the virtue ethicist’s project.”16


1978 [138] Foot, Philippa (1978): <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Vices, in dies., <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Vices and Other Essays in MoralPhilosophy, Oxford, S. 1–18. Wiederabgedruckt in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crispund Michael Slote, Oxford 1997, S. 163–77. Tugenden und Laster, in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Klaus Peter Rippe und Peter Schaber, Stuttgart, S. 69–91.1989 [139] Foot, Philippa (1989): V<strong>on</strong> Wright <strong>on</strong> <strong>Virtue</strong>, in The Philosophy of Georg Henrik v<strong>on</strong> Wright,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Paul A. Schilpp, La Salle, Ill. Wiederabgedruckt in Foot, Moral Dilemmasand Other Topics in Moral Philosophy, Oxford 2002, S. 105–116.1994 [140] Foot, Philippa (1994): Rati<strong>on</strong>ality and <strong>Virtue</strong>, in Norms, Values, and Society, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> HerlindePauer-Studer, Amsterdam, S. 205–16. Wiederabgedruckt in Foot, Moral Dilemmas andOther Topics in Moral Philosophy, Oxford 2002, S. 159–74.1994 [141] Foot, Philippa (1994): Tugend und Glück, in dies., Die Wirklichkeit des Guten.Moralphilosophische Aufsätze, hrsg. und eingeleitet v<strong>on</strong> Ursula Wolf und Ant<strong>on</strong> Leist,Frankfurt a. M., S. 214–25.2001 [142] Foot, Philippa (2001): Natural Goodness, Oxford. – Die Natur des Guten, Frankfurt a. M. 2004.1970 [143] Frankena, William K. (1970): Prichard and the Ethics of <strong>Virtue</strong>: Notes <strong>on</strong> a Footnote, M<strong>on</strong>ist54, S. 1–17.1973 [144] Frankena, William K. (1973): Ethics, Sec<strong>on</strong>d Editi<strong>on</strong>, Englewood Cliffs, N. J., S. 62–67.1988 [145] French, P./Uehling, T./Wettstein, H. (Hrsg.) (1988): Midwest Studies in Philosophy Vol. XIII:Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, South Bend, Ind.2008 [146] Friedman, Marilyn (2008): <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Oppressi<strong>on</strong>: A Complicated Relati<strong>on</strong>ship, Hypatia 23, S.189–96. 40 – Zu [440].2009 [147] Friedman, Marilyn (2009): Feminist <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Happiness, and Moral Luck, Hypatia 24, S.29–40. 411991 [148] Galst<strong>on</strong>, William A. (1991): Liberal Purposes. Goods, <strong>Virtue</strong>s, and Diversity in the LiberalState, Cambridge, S. 213–37 (“Liberal <strong>Virtue</strong>s”).1989 [149] Garcia, J. L. A. (1989): On ‘High-Mindedness’: Towards a C<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of Duty for <strong>Virtue</strong>-BasedMoral Theories, Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Associati<strong>on</strong> 63,S. 98–107.1990 [150] Garcia, J. L. A. (1990): The Primacy of the Virtuous, Philosophia 20, S. 69–91.4041“This paper raises some minor questi<strong>on</strong>s about Lisa Tessman’s book, Burdened <strong>Virtue</strong>s. Friedman’squesti<strong>on</strong>s pertain, am<strong>on</strong>g other things, to the adequacy of a virtue ethical focus <strong>on</strong> character, the apparentimplicati<strong>on</strong> of virtue ethics that oppressors suffer damaged characters and are not any better off than theoppressed, the importance of whether privileged pers<strong>on</strong>s may have earned their privileges, and theoppositi<strong>on</strong>al anger that movement feminists sometimes direct against each other.”“Can men who dominate women nevertheless be happy or lead flourishing lives? Building <strong>on</strong> ClaudiaCard's explorati<strong>on</strong> of moral luck, this paper c<strong>on</strong>siders the belief that male dominators cannot be happy. Thediscussi<strong>on</strong> ranges over both virtue theory and empirical research into the “belief in a just world.” I c<strong>on</strong>cludethat there are reas<strong>on</strong>s to avoid believing that male dominators cannot be happy or flourish, and thatfeminism does not need that belief.”17


1997 [151] Garcia, J. L. A. (1997): Interpers<strong>on</strong>al <strong>Virtue</strong>s. Whose Interests Do They Serve?, Proceedings ofthe American Catholic Philosophical Associati<strong>on</strong> 71, S. 31–60.2005 [152] Gardiner, Stephen M. (2005): Seneca’s Virtuous Moral Rules, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Old and New,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Stephen M. Gardiner, Ithaca, S. 30–59.2005 [153] Gardiner, Stephen M. (Hrsg.) (2005): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Old and New, Ithaca.2000 [154] Garrard, Eve (2000): Slote <strong>on</strong> <strong>Virtue</strong>, Analysis 60, S. 280–84.1997 [155] Gauthier, Jeffrey A. (1997): Schiller’s Critique of Kant’s Moral Psychology: Rec<strong>on</strong>cilingPractical Reas<strong>on</strong> and an Ethics of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 27, S. 513–544.1977 [156] Geach, Peter (1977): The <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Cambridge.1998 [157] Gert, Bernard (1998): Morality. Its Nature and Justificati<strong>on</strong>, New York, S. 277–309 (“<strong>Virtue</strong>sand Vices”).1985 [158] Gewirth, Alan (1985): Rights and <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Review of Metaphysics 38, S. 739–62.2005 [159] Gill, Christopher (Hrsg.) (2005): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Norms, and Objectivity. Issues in Ancient and ModernEthics, Oxford.2008 [160] Goldie, Peter (2008): <strong>Virtue</strong>s of Art and Human Well-Being, Proceedings of the AristotelianSociety Supplementary Volume 82, S. 179–95. 422008 [161] Gowans, Christopher W. (2008): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Nature, Social Philosophy and Policy 25, S. 28–55.2011 [162] Gowans, Christopher W. (2011): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Moral Relativism, in A Compani<strong>on</strong> to Relativism,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Steven D. Hales, Oxford, S. 391–410.1999 [163] Graeser, Andreas (1999): Philosophie und Ethik, Düsseldorf, S. 144–49.2004 [164] Graham, Gord<strong>on</strong> (2004): Eight Theories of Ethics, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, S. 53–70 (“Naturalism and <strong>Virtue</strong>Theory”).1994 [165] Greenspan, Patricia S. (1994): Guilt and <strong>Virtue</strong>, Journal of Philosophy 91, S. 57–70. 434243“What is the point of art, and why does it matter to us human beings? The answer that I will give in thispaper, following <strong>on</strong> from an earlier paper <strong>on</strong> the same subject, is that art matters because our being activelyengaged with art, either in its producti<strong>on</strong> or in its appreciati<strong>on</strong>, is part of what it is to live well. The focus inthe paper will be <strong>on</strong> the dispositi<strong>on</strong>s—the virtues of art producti<strong>on</strong> and of art appreciati<strong>on</strong>—that arenecessary for this kind of active engagement with art. To begin with, I will argue that these dispositi<strong>on</strong>sreally are virtues and not mere skills. Then I will show how the virtues of art, and their exercise in artisticactivity, interweave with the other kinds of virtue which are exercised in ethical and c<strong>on</strong>templative activity.And finally, I will argue that artistic activity affords, in a special way, a certain kind of emoti<strong>on</strong>al sharingthat binds us together with other human beings.”“Feelings of guilt have a role to play in moral philosophy as a link between the ethics of virtue and duty.They allow for a noti<strong>on</strong> of imperfect virtue as something still achievable despite serious moral lapses in thepast. They also would seem to be required by perfect virtue in resp<strong>on</strong>se to a moral dilemma. The defense ofguilt in a case of dilemma has implicati<strong>on</strong>s for virtue ethics insofar as it yields a distincti<strong>on</strong> between anagent’s character and his record of moral acti<strong>on</strong>--and an asymmetrical justificatory treatment of guilt versusother-directed variants of emoti<strong>on</strong>al blame.”18


1996 [166] Griffin, James (1996): Value Judgement. Improving Our Ethical Beliefs, Oxford, S. 112–16(“<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics”).1998 [167] Griffin, James (1998): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Envir<strong>on</strong>s, in <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Ellen FrankelPaul, Fred D. Miller, Jr. und Jeffrey Paul, Cambridge, S. 56–70.2007 [168] Hacker-Wright, John (2007): Moral Status in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Philosophy 82, S. 449–73. 442010 [169] Hacker-Wright, John (2010): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics without Right Acti<strong>on</strong>: Anscombe, Foot, and C<strong>on</strong>temporary<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Journal of Value Inquiry 44, S. 209–24.2005 [170] Hanafin, John/Coady, C. A. (Hrsg.) (2005): Unity, Separateness and C<strong>on</strong>flict in the <strong>Virtue</strong>s,Aldershot.1999 [171] Harman, Gilbert (1999): Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology. <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and theFundamental Attributi<strong>on</strong> Error, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 99, S. 315–31.Wiederabgedruckt in Harman, Explaining Value and Other Essays in MoralPhilosophy, Oxford 2000, S. 165–78. – Vgl. dazu [23], [243], [399].2000 [172] Harman, Gilbert (2000): The N<strong>on</strong>existence of Character Traits, Proceedings of the AristotelianSociety 100, S. 223–26. – Zu [23].2003 [173] Harman, Gilbert (2003): No Character or Pers<strong>on</strong>ality, Business Ethics Quarterly 13, S. 87–94. –Zu [395].2009 [174] Harman, Gilbert (2009): Skepticism about Character Traits, Journal of Ethics 13, S. 235–42. 452005 [175] Harris, George W. (2005): The <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Perfecti<strong>on</strong>ist Goods, and Pessimism, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics,Old and New, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Stephen M. Gardiner, Ithaca, S. 193–210.1995 [176] Harris<strong>on</strong>, J<strong>on</strong>athan (1995): Is <strong>Virtue</strong> in the Interest of the Str<strong>on</strong>ger? or the Prevaricati<strong>on</strong>s ofPlato, in ders., Ethical Essays Vol. III: New Essays, Aldershot, S. 220–44.4445(http://romulus.umd.edu/ARHU/Depts/Philosophy/Faculty/PGreenspan/Res/g&vabs.html)“My c<strong>on</strong>tenti<strong>on</strong> is that virtue ethics offers an important critique of traditi<strong>on</strong>al philosophical c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s ofmoral status as well as an alternative view of important moral issues held to depend <strong>on</strong> moral status. I arguethat the scope of entities that deserve c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> depends <strong>on</strong> our c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the demands of virtueslike justice; which entities deserve c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong> emerges from a moral view of a world shaped by thatc<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>. The deepest disputes about moral status depend <strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>flicting c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s of justice. I advocatea c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the virtue of justice that can account for the cases that pose problems for the legalistic viewsof moral status and discuss what ideal moral debate looks like <strong>on</strong> this view.”“The first part of this article discusses recent skepticism about character traits. The sec<strong>on</strong>d describes variousforms of virtue ethics as reacti<strong>on</strong>s to such skepticism. The philosopher J.-P. Sartre argued in the 1940s thatcharacter traits are pretenses, a view that the sociologist E. Goffman elaborated in the 1950s. Since thensocial psychologists have shown that attributi<strong>on</strong>s of character traits tend to be inaccurate through theignoring of situati<strong>on</strong>al factors. (Pers<strong>on</strong>ality psychology has tended to c<strong>on</strong>centrate <strong>on</strong> people’s c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s ofpers<strong>on</strong>ality and character rather than <strong>on</strong> the accuracy of these c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>s). Similarly, the political theoristR. Hardin has argued for situati<strong>on</strong>al explanati<strong>on</strong>s of bloody social disputes in the former Yugoslavia and inAfrica, rather than explanati<strong>on</strong>s in terms of ethnic hatred for example. A versi<strong>on</strong> of virtue ethics mightidentify virtues as characteristics of acts rather than character traits, as traits c<strong>on</strong>sisting in actual regularitiesin behavior, or as robust dispositi<strong>on</strong>s that would manifest themselves also in counterfactual situati<strong>on</strong>s.”19


1926 [177] Hartmann, Nicolai (1926): Ethik, Berlin 1962, S. 416–544.1999 [178] Hayd<strong>on</strong>, Graham (1999): Values, <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Violence: Educati<strong>on</strong> and the PublicUnderstanding of Morality, Oxford.1985 [179] Heil, John (1985): Thoughts <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Journal of Value Inquiry 19, S. 27–34.2008 [180] Hennig, Boris (2008): Tugenden und Absichten. Versuch, Anscombe einen Tugendbegriff zuentnehmen, Philosophisches Jahrbuch der Görres-Gesellschaft 115, S. 165–83.2008 [181] Herdt, Jennifer A. (2008): Putting <strong>on</strong> <strong>Virtue</strong>. The Legacy of the Splendid Vices, Chicago. 462005 [182] Higgins, Kathleen Marie (2005): Negative <strong>Virtue</strong>s: Zhuangzi’s Wuwei, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Old andNew, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Stephen M. Gardiner, Ithaca, S. 125–41.1998 [183] Hinman, Lawrence M. (1998): Ethics. A Pluralistic Approach to Moral Theory, Sec<strong>on</strong>d Editi<strong>on</strong>,Fort Worth, S. 321–64 (“The Ethics of Character: Aristotle and Our C<strong>on</strong>temporaries”).1998 [184] Höffe, Otfried (1998): Aristoteles’ universalistische <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>Klaus Peter Rippe und Peter Schaber, Stuttgart, S. 42–68.1998 [185] Holmes, Robert L. (1998): Basic Moral Philosophy, Belm<strong>on</strong>t, CA, 2. Auflage, S. 31–61 (“TheEthics of <strong>Virtue</strong>”).1997 [186] Homiak, Marcia L. (1997): Aristotle <strong>on</strong> the Soul’s C<strong>on</strong>flicts: Toward an Understanding of<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Reclaiming the History of Ethics. Essays for John Rawls, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>Andrews Reath, Barbara Herman und Christine M. Korsgaard, Cambridge, S. 7–35.1998 [187] H<strong>on</strong>ecker, Martin (1998): Schwierigkeiten mit dem Begriff der Tugend. Die Zweideutigkeit derTugend, in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Klaus Peter Rippe und Peter Schaber, Stuttgart, S.46Preface. Introducti<strong>on</strong>. Part I: Splendid Vices and Imperfect <strong>Virtue</strong>s. 1 Aristotle and the Puzzles ofHabituati<strong>on</strong>. 2 Augustine: Disordered Loves and the Problem of Pride. 3 Aquinas: Making Space for Pagan<strong>Virtue</strong>. Part II: Mimetic <strong>Virtue</strong>. 4 Erasmus: Putting On Christ. 5 The Jesuit Theatrical Traditi<strong>on</strong>: ActingVirtuous. Part III: The Exodus from <strong>Virtue</strong>. 6 Luther: Saved Hypocrites. 7 Bunyan and Puritan Life-Writing: The <strong>Virtue</strong> of Self-Examinati<strong>on</strong>. Part IV: The Anatomy of <strong>Virtue</strong>. 8 Jesuits and Jansenists:Gracián and Pascal. 9 Emancipating Worldly <strong>Virtue</strong>: Nicole, La Rochefoucauld, and Mandeville. Part V:Pagan <strong>Virtue</strong> and Modern Moral Philosophy. 10 Rousseau and the <strong>Virtue</strong> of Authenticity. 11 Hume and theBourgeois Rehabilitati<strong>on</strong> of Pride. 12 Kant and the Pursuit of Noumenal Purity. C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>. Notes. Index.“Augustine famously claimed that the virtues of pagan Rome were nothing more than splendid vices. Thiscritique has reinvented itself as a suspici<strong>on</strong> of acquired virtue as such, and true Christian virtue has, eversince, been set against a false, hypocritical virtue alleged merely to c<strong>on</strong>ceal pride. Putting On <strong>Virtue</strong> revealshow a distrust of learned and habituated virtue shaped both early modern Christian moral reflecti<strong>on</strong> andsecular forms of ethical thought.Jennifer Herdt develops her claims through an argument of broad historical sweep, which brings togetherthe Aristotelian traditi<strong>on</strong> as taken up by Thomas Aquinas with the early modern thinkers who shapedmodern liberalism. In chapters <strong>on</strong> Luther, Bunyan, the Jansenists, Mandeville, Hume, Rousseau, and Kant,she argues that efforts to guard a radical distincti<strong>on</strong> between true Christian virtue and its tainted imitati<strong>on</strong>sir<strong>on</strong>ically fostered the emergence of an aut<strong>on</strong>omous natural ethics that valorized pride and authenticity,while rendering graced human agency increasingly unintelligible. Ultimately, Putting On <strong>Virtue</strong> traces apath from suspici<strong>on</strong> of virtue to its secular inversi<strong>on</strong>, from c<strong>on</strong>fessi<strong>on</strong> of dependence to asserti<strong>on</strong> ofindependence.” (Publisher’s descripti<strong>on</strong>)20


166–84.1996 [188] Hooker, Brad (1996): Does Moral <strong>Virtue</strong> C<strong>on</strong>stitute a Benefit to the Agent?, in How Should OneLive? Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 141–55.2002 [189] Hooker, Brad (2002): The Collapse of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Utilitas 14, S. 22–40. – Vgl. dazu [207].2008 [190] Horn, Christoph (2008): Glück und Tugend, in Grundpositi<strong>on</strong>en und Anwendungsprobleme derEthik (Kolleg Praktische Philosophie Band 2), hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Volker Steenblock, Stuttgart,S. 23–54. 471986 [191] Huds<strong>on</strong>, Stephen D. (1986): Human Character and Morality. Reflecti<strong>on</strong>s from the History ofIdeas, Bost<strong>on</strong>.1980 [192] Hunt, Lester H. (1980): Courage and Principle, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 10, S. 281–93.1997 [193] Hunt, Lester H. (1997): Character and Culture, Lanham.1992 [194] Hurka, Thomas (1992): <strong>Virtue</strong> as Loving the Good, in The Good Life and the Human Good,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr. und Jeffrey Paul, Cambridge, S. 149–68.1997 [195] Hurka, Thomas (1997): Self-Interest, Altruism, and <strong>Virtue</strong>, Social Philosophy and Policy 14, S.286–307.1998 [196] Hurka, Thomas (1998): How Great a Good is <strong>Virtue</strong>?, Journal of Philosophy 95, S. 181ff.2001 [197] Hurka, Thomas (2001): The Comm<strong>on</strong> Structure of <strong>Virtue</strong> and Desert, Ethics 112, S. 6–31.2001 [198] Hurka, Thomas (2001): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Vice, and Value, Oxford.2001 [199] Hurka, Thomas (2001): Vices as Higher-level Evils, Utilitas 13, S. 195–212.2006 [200] Hurka, Thomas (2006): Virtuous Act, Virtuous Dispositi<strong>on</strong>s, Analysis 66, S. 69–76.2010 [201] Hurka, Thomas (2010): Right Act, Virtuous Motive, Metaphilosophy 41, S. 58–72. 481991 [202] Hursthouse, Rosalind (1991): <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory and Aborti<strong>on</strong>, Philosophy and Public Affairs 20, S.223–46. Wiederabgedruckt in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp und Michael Slote,Oxford 1997, S. 217–38 sowie in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> DanielStatman, Edinburgh 1997, S. 227–44.4748„1. Begriffliche Voraussetzungen: „Glück“ und „Tugend“ im antiken und modernen Wortverständnis. 2.Das vormoderne Modell einer eudäm<strong>on</strong>istischen <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>. 3. Aktuelle Diskussi<strong>on</strong>en über Glück undgelingendes Leben. 4. Zeitgenössische <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>en. 5. <str<strong>on</strong>g>Literatur</str<strong>on</strong>g>hinweise.““The c<strong>on</strong>cepts of virtue and right acti<strong>on</strong> are closely c<strong>on</strong>nected, in that we expect people with virtuousmotives to at least often act rightly. Two well-known views explain this c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong> by defining <strong>on</strong>e of thec<strong>on</strong>cepts in terms of the other. Instrumentalists about virtue identify virtuous motives as those that lead toright acts; virtue-ethicists identify right acts as those that are or would be d<strong>on</strong>e from virtuous motives. Thisessay outlines a rival explanati<strong>on</strong>, based <strong>on</strong> the “higher-level” account of virtue defended in the author’s<strong>Virtue</strong>, Vice, and Value. On this account rightness and virtue go together because each is defined by a(different) relati<strong>on</strong> to some other, more basic moral c<strong>on</strong>cept. Their frequent coincidence is therefore like acorrelati<strong>on</strong> between A and B based not <strong>on</strong> either’s causing the other but <strong>on</strong> their being joint effects of asingle comm<strong>on</strong> cause.”21


1995 [203] Hursthouse, Rosalind (1995): Applying <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Reas<strong>on</strong>s. Philippa Footand Moral Theory. Essays in H<strong>on</strong>our of Philippa Foot, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Rosalind Hursthouse,Gavin Lawrence und Warren Quinn, Oxford, S. 57–75.1996 [204] Hursthouse, Rosalind (1996): Normative <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in How Should One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the<strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 19–36.1997 [205] Hursthouse, Rosalind (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and the Emoti<strong>on</strong>s, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A CriticalReader, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Daniel Statman, Edinburgh, S. 99–117.1999 [206] Hursthouse, Rosalind (1999): On <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Oxford. – Vgl. dazu [128], [328].2002 [207] Hursthouse, Rosalind (2002): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics vs. Rule-C<strong>on</strong>sequentialism: A Reply to BradHooker, Utilitas 14, S. 41–53. – Zu [189].2003 [208] Hursthouse, Rosalind (2003): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>Edward Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-virtue/.2004 [209] Hursthouse, Rosalind (2004): On the Grounding of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s in Human Nature, in Was ist dasfür den Menschen Gute? Menschliche Natur und Güterlehre. / What Is Good for aHuman Being? Human Nature and Values, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Jan Szaif und Matthias Lutz-Bachmann, Berlin, S. 263–75.2006 [210] Hursthouse, Rosalind (2006): Are <strong>Virtue</strong>s the Proper Starting Point for Morality?, in C<strong>on</strong>temporaryDebates in Moral Theory, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> James Dreier, Oxford, S. 99–112.1994 [211] Irwin, T. H. (1994): Happiness, <strong>Virtue</strong>, and Morality, Ethics 105, S. 153–177.1996 [212] Irwin, T. H. (1996): The <strong>Virtue</strong>s: Theory and Comm<strong>on</strong> Sense in Greek Philosophy, in HowShould One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 37–55.2005 [213] Irwin, T. H. (2005): Do <strong>Virtue</strong>s C<strong>on</strong>flict? Aquinas’s Answer, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Old and New,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Stephen M. Gardiner, Ithaca, S. 60–77.1995 [214] Jacobs, J<strong>on</strong>athan (1995): Why is <strong>Virtue</strong> Naturally Pleasing?, Review of Metaphysics 49, S. 21–48.1995 [215] Jacobs, J<strong>on</strong>athan (2001): Choosing Character. Resp<strong>on</strong>sibility for <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, Ithaca.2005 [216] Jacobs<strong>on</strong>, Daniel (2005): Seeing by Feeling: <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Skills, and Moral Percepti<strong>on</strong>, Ethical22


Theory and Moral Practice 8, S. 387–409. 492000 [217] Jansen, Lynn A. (2000): The <strong>Virtue</strong>s in Their Place: <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics in Medicine, TheoreticalMedicine 21, S. 261–76.1998 [218] Jeffries, Vincent (1998): <strong>Virtue</strong> and the Altruistic Pers<strong>on</strong>ality, Sociological Perspectives 41, S.151–166.1997 [219] Jensen, Steven J. (1997): Goods of C<strong>on</strong>sequences and Goods of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Proceedings of theAmerican Catholic Philosophical Associati<strong>on</strong> 71, S. 179–87.2003 [220] Johns<strong>on</strong>, Robert N. (2003): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Right, Ethics 113, S. 810–34. – Dazu: [269], [442].1998 [221] Kagan, Shelly (1998): Normative Ethics, Boulder, S. 204–12 (“<strong>Virtue</strong>s”).2004 [222] Kamtekar, Rachana (2004): Situati<strong>on</strong>ism and <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics <strong>on</strong> the C<strong>on</strong>tent of Our Character,Ethics 114, S. 458–91.2010 [223] Kamtekar, Rachana (2010): Comments <strong>on</strong> Robert Adams, A Theory of <strong>Virtue</strong>: Excellence inbeing for the Good, Philosophical Studies 148, S. 147–58. – Zu [3]. Dazu: [5].2002 [224] Kawall, Jas<strong>on</strong> (2002): <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory and Ideal Observers, Philosophical Studies 109, S. 197–222. 502009 [225] Kawall, Jas<strong>on</strong> (2009): In Defense of the Primacy of <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Journal of Ethics and SocialPhilosophy 3, Nr. 2, S. 1–21, http://www.jesp.org/. 51495051“Champi<strong>on</strong>s of virtue ethics frequently appeal to moral percepti<strong>on</strong>: the noti<strong>on</strong> that virtuous people can “see”what to do. According to a traditi<strong>on</strong>al account of virtue, the cultivati<strong>on</strong> of proper feeling through imitati<strong>on</strong>and habituati<strong>on</strong> issues in a sensitivity to reas<strong>on</strong>s to act. Thus, we learn to see what to do by coming to feelthe demands of courage, kindness, and the like. But virtue ethics also claims superiority over other theoriesthat adopt a perceptual moral epistemology, such as intuiti<strong>on</strong>ism - which John McDowell criticizes forillicitly “borrow[ing] the epistemological credentials” of percepti<strong>on</strong>. In this paper, I suggest that the mostpromising way for virtue ethics to use perceptual metaphors innocuously is by adopting a skill model ofvirtue, <strong>on</strong> which the virtues are modeled <strong>on</strong> forms of practical know-how. Yet I c<strong>on</strong>tend that this model isdouble-edged for virtue ethics. The skill model belies some central ambiti<strong>on</strong>s and dogmas of the traditi<strong>on</strong>alview, especially its most idealized claims about virtue and the virtuous. While this may be a cost that itschampi<strong>on</strong>s are unprepared to pay, I suggest that virtue ethics would do well to embrace a more realisticmoral psychology and a corresp<strong>on</strong>dingly less sublime c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of virtue.”“<strong>Virtue</strong> theorists in ethics often embrace the following characterizati<strong>on</strong> of right acti<strong>on</strong>: An acti<strong>on</strong> is right iffa virtuous agent would perform that acti<strong>on</strong> in like circumstances. Zagzebski offers a parallel virtue-basedaccount of epistemically justified belief. Such proposals are severely flawed because virtuous agents inadverse circumstances, or through lack of knowledge can perform poorly. I propose an alternative virtuebasedaccount according to which an acti<strong>on</strong> is right (a belief is justified) for an agent in a given situati<strong>on</strong> iffan unimpaired, fully-informed virtuous observer would deem the acti<strong>on</strong> to be right (the belief to bejustified).”“In this paper I resp<strong>on</strong>d to a set of basic objecti<strong>on</strong>s often raised against those virtue theories in ethics whichmaintain that moral properties such rightness and goodness (and their corresp<strong>on</strong>ding c<strong>on</strong>cepts) are to beexplained and understood in terms of the virtues or the virtuous. The objecti<strong>on</strong>s all rest <strong>on</strong> a str<strong>on</strong>gly-heldintuiti<strong>on</strong> that the virtues (and the virtuous) simply must be derivative in some way from either right acti<strong>on</strong>sor good states of affairs. My goal is to articulate several distinct, though related, objecti<strong>on</strong>s grounded in this23


2009 [226] Kawall, Jas<strong>on</strong> (2009): <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory, Ideal Observers, and the Supererogatory, PhilosophicalStudies 146, S. 179–96. 521996 [227] Keefer, Matthew Wilks (1996): The Inseparability of Morality and Well-being: The Duty/<strong>Virtue</strong>Debate Revisited, Journal of Moral Educati<strong>on</strong> 25, S. 277–90.2007 [228] Keller, Sim<strong>on</strong> (2007): <strong>Virtue</strong> ethics is self-effacing, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 85, S.221–31. 531997 [229] Kelly, Eugene (1997): Revisiting Max Scheler’s Formalism in Ethics: <strong>Virtue</strong>-Based Ethics andMoral Rules in the N<strong>on</strong>-Formal Ethics of Value, Journal of Value Inquiry 31, S. 381–97.2002 [230] Kersting, Wolfgang (2002): Kritik der Gleichheit. Über die Grenzen der Gerechtigkeit und derMoral, Weilerswist, S. 217–54 („Zur Geschichte der Tugend“).2000 [231] Kihlbom, Ulrik (2000): Guidance and Justificati<strong>on</strong> in Particularistic Ethics, Bioethics 14, S.287–309. 541983 [232] Kilcullen, John (1983): Utilitarianism and <strong>Virtue</strong>, Ethics 93, S. 451–66.1997 [233] Koehn, Daryl (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in The Blackwell Encyclopedic Dicti<strong>on</strong>ary of Business525354intuiti<strong>on</strong>, and to argue that virtue ethicists have ample resources to resp<strong>on</strong>d to these worries. Theexplanatory primacy of the virtuous over the right or the good emerges as a distinct and viable positi<strong>on</strong>.”“I argue that recent virtue theories (including those of Hursthouse, Slote, and Swant<strong>on</strong>) face importantinitial difficulties in accommodating the supererogatory. In particular, I c<strong>on</strong>sider several potentialcharacterizati<strong>on</strong>s of the supererogatory modeled up<strong>on</strong> these familiar virtue theories (and their accounts ofrightness) and argue that they fail to provide an adequate account of supererogati<strong>on</strong>. In the sec<strong>on</strong>d half ofthe paper I sketch an alternative virtue-based characterizati<strong>on</strong> of supererogati<strong>on</strong>, <strong>on</strong>e that is grounded in theattitudes of virtuous ideal observers, and that avoids the c<strong>on</strong>cerns raised in the first part of the paper.”“An ethical theory is self-effacing if it tells us that sometimes, we should not be motivated by thec<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s that justify our acts. In his influential paper ‘The Schizophrenia of Modern Ethical Theories’[1976], Michael Stocker argues that c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist and de<strong>on</strong>tological ethical theories must be selfeffacing,if they are to be at all plausible. Stocker’s argument is often taken to provide a reas<strong>on</strong> to give upc<strong>on</strong>sequentialism and de<strong>on</strong>tology in favour of virtue ethics. I argue that this assessment is a mistake. <strong>Virtue</strong>ethics is self-effacing in just the same way as are the theories that Stocker attacks. Or, at the very least: ifthere is a way for virtue ethics to avoid self-effacement then there are ways for its rivals to avoid selfeffacementtoo. Therefore, c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s of self-effacement provide no reas<strong>on</strong> to prefer virtue ethics to itsmajor rivals.”“This paper argues that, c<strong>on</strong>trary to a comm<strong>on</strong> line of criticism followed by scholars such as Helga Kuhse, aparticularistic versi<strong>on</strong> of virtue ethics properly elaborated, can provide sound moral guidance and asatisfactory account for moral justificati<strong>on</strong> of our opini<strong>on</strong>s regarding, for instance, health care practice. Inthe first part of the paper, three criteria for comparing normative theories with respect to acti<strong>on</strong>-guidingpower are outlined, and it is argued that the presented particularistic versi<strong>on</strong> of virtue ethics actually canprovide more guidance than the universalistic theories favoured by Kuhse and others. In the sec<strong>on</strong>d part ofthe paper it is claimed that universalist normative theories have serious problems accounting for the rolethat moral principles are supposed to play in the justificati<strong>on</strong>, of moral opini<strong>on</strong>s, whereas the presentversi<strong>on</strong> of virtue ethics accommodates a plausible alternative idea of justificati<strong>on</strong> without invoking moralprinciples or eschewing objectivity.”24


Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Patricia H. Werhane und R. Edward Freeman, Oxford, S. 647–50.2008 [234] Koggel, Christine (2008): Burdening the Burdened <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Hypatia 23, S. 197–204. – Zu [440].2008 [235] Kristjánss<strong>on</strong>, Kristján (2008): An Aristotelian Critique of Situati<strong>on</strong>ism, Philosophy 83, S. 55–76. 551987 [236] Kruschwitz, R./Roberts R. (Hrsg.) (1987): The <strong>Virtue</strong>s. C<strong>on</strong>temporary Essays <strong>on</strong> MoralCharacter, Belm<strong>on</strong>t, Cal.1998 [237] Kultgen, John (1998): The Vicissitudes of Comm<strong>on</strong>-Sense <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Part I: From Aristotleto Slote, Journal of Value Inquiry 32, S. 325–41.1998 [238] Kultgen, John (1998): The Vicissitudes of Comm<strong>on</strong>-Sense <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Part II: The HeuristicUse of Comm<strong>on</strong> Sense, Journal of Value Inquiry 32, S. 465–78.1999 [239] Kupfer, Joseph (1999): Visi<strong>on</strong>s of <strong>Virtue</strong> in Popular Film, Boulder. 562007 [240] Kupfer, Joseph H. (2007): Prostitutes, Musicians, and Self-Respect: <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Vices ofPers<strong>on</strong>al Life, Lanham. 571988 [241] Kupperman, Joel J. (1988): Character and Ethical Theory, in Midwest Studies in PhilosophyVol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French, TheodoreE. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 115–25.1991 [242] Kupperman, Joel J. (1991): Character, New York, S. 90–114 (“Justice and the <strong>Virtue</strong>s”).2001 [243] Kupperman, Joel J. (2001): The Indispensability of Character, Philosophy 76, S. 239–50. – Zu[171].2006 [244] Kupperman, Joel J. (2006): Six Myths About the Good Life: Thinking About What Has Value,Indianapolis, S. 82–109 (“Myth Five – There Is No Real C<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>, At Least in ThisLife, Between True <strong>Virtue</strong> and a Desirable Kind of Life”), S. 110–27 (“Myth Six – True555657“Aristotle says that no human achievement has the stability of activities that express virtue. Ethicalsituati<strong>on</strong>ists c<strong>on</strong>sider this claim to be refutable by empirical evidence. If that is true, not <strong>on</strong>lyAristotelianism, but folk psychology, c<strong>on</strong>temporary virtue ethics and character educati<strong>on</strong> have all beenseriously infirmed. The aim of this paper is threefold: (1) to offer a systematic classificati<strong>on</strong> of the existingobjecti<strong>on</strong>s against situati<strong>on</strong>ism under four main headings: ‘the methodological objecti<strong>on</strong>’, ‘the moraldilemma objecti<strong>on</strong>’, ‘the bullet-biting objecti<strong>on</strong>’ and ‘the anti-behaviouristic objecti<strong>on</strong>’; (2) to resuscitate amore powerful Aristotelian versi<strong>on</strong> of the ‘anti-behaviouristic objecti<strong>on</strong>’ than advanced by previous critics;and (3) to explore some of the implicati<strong>on</strong>s of such resuscitati<strong>on</strong> for our understanding of the salience ofcharacter and for future studies of its nature.”“Synopsis: Out of the interplay between film criticism and a philosophical view of virtue, Joseph Kupferargues that film ficti<strong>on</strong>s can be integral to moral reflecti<strong>on</strong>, and thus by examining the narrative andcinematic aspects of popular films, we can derive important moral truths about people and their behaviour.Taking as his base a classical c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of virtue and vice, Kupfer offers an in-depth examinati<strong>on</strong> of“Groundhog Day”, “The African Queen”, “Parenthood”, “Rob Roy”, “Fresh”, “Jaws” and “Aliens” in orderto investigate the value of virtue within ever-widening social c<strong>on</strong>texts.” (Amaz<strong>on</strong>.co.uk)“Introducti<strong>on</strong>. Chapter 1. The Moral Perspective of Humility. Chapter 2. Sentimentalizing Emoti<strong>on</strong>.Chapter 3. Generosity of Spirit. Chapter 4. Overcoming Envy. Chapter 5. When Waiting is Weightless: The<strong>Virtue</strong> of Patience. Chapter 6. No Regrets, No Debts: The <strong>Virtue</strong> of Gratitude. Chapter 7. Romantic Loveand Moral Growth. Chapter 8. Prostitutes, Musicians, and Self-Respect. C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>.”25


<strong>Virtue</strong> Is Impeccable”).2007 [245] Kupperman, Joel J. (2007): Ethics and Qualities of Life, Oxford, S. 183–90 (“Appendix: <strong>Virtue</strong>Ethics”).2009 [246] Kupperman, Joel J. (2009): <strong>Virtue</strong> in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Journal of Ethics 13, S. 243–55. 581946 [247] Laird, J. (1946): Act-Ethics and Agent-Ethics, Mind 55, S. 113–32.2008 [248] Lara, Amy (2008): <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory and Moral Facts, Journal of Value Inquiry 42, S. 331–52.2009 [249] LeBar, Mark (2009): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and De<strong>on</strong>tic C<strong>on</strong>straints, Ethics 119, S. 642–71.1994 [250] Lemos, John (1994): The Unity of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Its Recent Defenses, Southern Journal ofPhilosophy 32, S. 85–106.2007 [251] Lemos, John (2007): Foot and Aristotle <strong>on</strong> <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Flourishing, Philosophia 37, S. 43–62. 591997 [252] Little, Margaret O. (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong> as Knowledge: Objecti<strong>on</strong>s from the Philosophy of Mind, Nous31, S. 59–79.1993 [253] Littlejohn, R<strong>on</strong>nie L. (1993): Ethics. Studying the Art of Moral Appraisal, Lanham, S. 115–27(“Resp<strong>on</strong>sibility Descripti<strong>on</strong>s Using <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice C<strong>on</strong>cepts”).1999 [254] Liszka, James Jakób (1999): Moral Competence. An Integrated Approach to the Study of Ethics,Upper Saddle River, NJ., S. 114–94 (“<strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice”).1984 [255] Louden, Robert B. (1984): On Some Vices of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, American Philosophical Quarterly21, S. 227–36. Wiederabgedruckt in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp und MichaelSlote, Oxford 1997, S. 201–16 sowie in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>Daniel Statman, Edinburgh 1997, S. 180–93. – Einige Laster <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Klaus Peter Rippe und Peter Schaber, Stuttgart, S. 185–212.1986 [256] Louden, Robert B. (1986): Kant’s <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Philosophy 61, S. 473–89. Wiederabgedruckt in<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Daniel Statman, Edinburgh 1997, S. 286–99.1990 [257] Louden, Robert B. (1990): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Anti-Theory, Philosophia 20, S. 93–114.2005 [258] Lovib<strong>on</strong>d, Sabina (2005): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Nature, and Providence, in <strong>Virtue</strong>, Norms, and Objectivity.Issues in Ancient and Modern Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Christopher Gill, Oxford, S. 99–112.2002 [259] Luckner, Andreas (2002): Handlungen und Haltungen. Zur Renaissance der <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>,5859“This paper represents two polemics. One is against suggesti<strong>on</strong>s (made by Harman and others) that recentpsychological research counts against any claim that there is such a thing as genuine virtue (Cf. Harman,in: Byrne, Stalnaker, Wedgwood (eds.) Fact and value, pp 117–127, 2001). The other is against the viewthat virtue ethics should be seen as competing against such theories as Kantian ethics or c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism,particularly in the specificati<strong>on</strong> of decisi<strong>on</strong> procedures.”“This article compares the views of Foot and Aristotle <strong>on</strong> virtues and flourishing. It is argued that the viewput forward in Philippa Foot’s recent book, Natural Goodness, suffers from a certain sort of vagueness andit is open to other criticisms which the Aristotelian view can avoid. Foot’s views have been subjected tocriticism in the recent literature by David Copp and David Sobel. These criticisms are given c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>in the article and it is argued that the more traditi<strong>on</strong>al Aristotelian view advocated by the author will havethe means to answer some of these criticisms whereas Foot’s view will not.”26


Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 50, S. 779–96.2007 [260] McAleer, Sean (2007): An Aristotelian Account of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics: An Essay in Moral Tax<strong>on</strong>omy,Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88, S. 208–25. 601979 [261] McDowell, John (1979): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Reas<strong>on</strong>, M<strong>on</strong>ist 62, S. 331–50. Wiederabgedruckt inMcDowell, Mind, Value, and Reality, Cambridge, Mass. 1998, S. 50–73.1990 [262] Macedo, Stephen (1990): Liberal <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Oxford.1992 [263] Macedo, Stephen (1992): Charting Liberal <strong>Virtue</strong>s, in <strong>Virtue</strong> (Nomos 34), hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> John W.Chapman und William A. Galst<strong>on</strong>, New York, S. 204–32.1998 [264] Machan, Tibor R. (1998): Generosity: <strong>Virtue</strong> in the Civil Society, Washingt<strong>on</strong>. 611981 [265] MacIntyre, Alasdair (1981): After <strong>Virtue</strong>. A Study in Moral Theory, Notre Dame (2 nd editi<strong>on</strong>:Notre Dame 1984). – Der Verlust der Tugend. Zur moralischen Krise der Gegenwart,Frankfurt a. M. 1987.1988 [266] MacIntyre, Alasdair (1988): Sōphrosunē: How a <strong>Virtue</strong> Can Become Socially Disruptive, inMidwest Studies in Philosophy Vol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg.v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame,S. 1–11.1992 [267] MacIntyre, Alasdair (1992): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Encyclopedia of Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Lawrence C.Becker und Charlotte B. Becker, New York, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, Vol. II, S. 1276–82.1999 [268] MacIntyre, Alasdair (1999): Dependent Rati<strong>on</strong>al Animals. Why Human Beings Need the <strong>Virtue</strong>s,Chicago.2010 [269] McAleer, Sean (2010): Four Soluti<strong>on</strong>s the the Alleged Incompleteness of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Journalof Ethics and Social Philosophy 4 (3), S. 1–20. http://jesp.org/articles/view.php?id=47.– Zu [220].1977 [270] Mackie, John Leslie (1977): Ethics. Inventing Right and Wr<strong>on</strong>g, Harm<strong>on</strong>dsworth, S. 186–89(“<strong>Virtue</strong>”). – Ethik. Die Erfindung des moralisch Richtigen und Falschen, durchge-6061“I argue that a virtue ethics takes virtue to be more basic than rightness and at least as basic as goodness.My account is Aristotelian because it avoids the excessive inclusivity of Martha Nussbaum's account and thedeficient inclusivity of Gary Wats<strong>on</strong>'s account. I defend the account against the objecti<strong>on</strong> that Aristotle doesnot have a virtue ethics by its lights, and c<strong>on</strong>clude with some remarks <strong>on</strong> moral tax<strong>on</strong>omy.”The author, Machan@Chapman.edu, 1 October, 1997: “The virtue of generosity is a sp<strong>on</strong>taneous, thoughrati<strong>on</strong>ally cultivated, dispositi<strong>on</strong> of pers<strong>on</strong>s to extend their help to others who can use and deserve it. Aswith other virtues, generosity presupposes that pers<strong>on</strong>s can make free choices as to how they will act. Its fullflourishing in a community requires, furthermore, that the rights to liberty of acti<strong>on</strong> are fully respected andprotected. C<strong>on</strong>tending, as some do, that generous c<strong>on</strong>duct may be elicited by coercive measures orprohibiti<strong>on</strong>s laid down against trade – e.g., so as to encourage blood d<strong>on</strong>ati<strong>on</strong>s – is wr<strong>on</strong>gheaded. Coerced“generosity” is not virtous and removing the opti<strong>on</strong> to trade also does violence to the c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s required forvirtous generosity. In their eagerness to provide for the needy, some thinkers make public policy proposalsthat destory the human capacity for virtous generosity. Only if men and women are left free – that is, if theylive in civil society – can they be expected to act as they should, including generously, when that isappropriate.” (Amaz<strong>on</strong>.co.uk)27


sehene und verbesserte Ausgabe, Stuttgart 1983, S. 237–42 („Tugend“).1999 [271] McKinn<strong>on</strong>, Christine (1999): Character, <strong>Virtue</strong> Theories, and the Vices, Peterborough.1996 [272] Mas<strong>on</strong>, Andrew (1996): MacIntyre <strong>on</strong> Modernity and How It Has Marginalized the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, inHow Should One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 191–209.2002 [273] Mayer, Verena (2002): Tugend und Gefühl, in Die Moralität der Gefühle, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Sabine A.Döring und Verena Mayer, Berlin, S. 125–50.2009 [274] Mayer, Verena (2009): Tugend aus negativer Freiheit. Eine universelle Begründungsstruktur fürmoralische Normen, in Moralischer Relativismus, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Gerhard Ernst, Paderborn,S. 213–29.1984 [275] Meilaender, Gilbert (1984): The Theory and Practice of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Notre Dame, Ind.2000 [276] Merritt, Maria (2000): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Situati<strong>on</strong>ist Pers<strong>on</strong>ality Psychology, Ethical Theoryand Moral Practice 3, S. 365–83.2009 [277] Merritt, Maria W. (2009): Aristotelean <strong>Virtue</strong> and the Interpers<strong>on</strong>al Aspect of EthicalCharacter, Journal of Moral Philosophy 6, S. 23–49. 622003 [278] Miller, Christian B. (2003): Social Psychology and <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Journal of Ethics 7, S. 365–92. 632009 [279] Miller, Christian B. (2009): Empathy, Social Psychology, and Global Helping Traits,Philosophical Studies 142, S. 247–75. 64626364“I examine the Aristotelean c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of virtuous character as firm and unchangeable, a normative idealendorsed in the currently influential, broadly Aristotelean school of thought known as ‘virtue ethics’.Drawing <strong>on</strong> central c<strong>on</strong>cepts of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, I offer an account of how this ideal issupposed to be realized psychologically. I then c<strong>on</strong>sider present-day empirical findings about relevantpsychological processes, with special attenti<strong>on</strong> to interpers<strong>on</strong>al processes. The empirical evidence suggeststhat over time, the same interpers<strong>on</strong>al processes that sometimes help to sustain character may also disrupt it,even am<strong>on</strong>g agents who have the right values in principle. Fortunately, the evidence also suggests someremedial measures. An important philosophical measure, I c<strong>on</strong>clude, is for advocates of virtue ethics toaddress agents’ psychological need for a systematic decisi<strong>on</strong> procedure that will focus attenti<strong>on</strong> primarily <strong>on</strong>substantive ethical c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s, rather than characterological assessment.”“Several philosophers have recently claimed to have discovered a new and rather significant problem withvirtue ethics. According to them, virtue ethics generates certain expectati<strong>on</strong>s about the behavior of humanbeings which are subject to empirical testing. But when the relevant experimental work is d<strong>on</strong>e in socialpsychology, the results fall remarkably short of meeting those expectati<strong>on</strong>s. So, these philosophers think,despite its recent success, virtue ethics has far less to offer to c<strong>on</strong>temporary ethical theory than might havebeen initially thought. I argue that there are plausible ways in which virtue ethicists can resist argumentsbased <strong>on</strong> empirical work in social psychology. In the first three secti<strong>on</strong>s of the paper, I rec<strong>on</strong>struct the lineof reas<strong>on</strong>ing being used against virtue ethics by looking at the recent work of Gilbert Harman and JohnDoris. The remainder of the paper is then devoted both to resp<strong>on</strong>ding to their challenge as well as to brieflysketching a positive account of character trait possessi<strong>on</strong>.”“The central virtue at issue in recent philosophical discussi<strong>on</strong>s of the empirical adequacy of virtue ethics hasbeen the virtue of compassi<strong>on</strong>. Opp<strong>on</strong>ents of virtue ethics such as Gilbert Harman and John Doris argue that28


2009 [280] Miller, Christian (2009): Social Psychology, Mood, and Helping: Mixed Results for <strong>Virtue</strong>Ethics, Journal of Ethics 13, S. 145–73. 652005 [281] Millgram, Elijah (2005): Reas<strong>on</strong>ably Virtuous, in Millgram, Ethics D<strong>on</strong>e Right. PracticalReas<strong>on</strong>ing as a Foundati<strong>on</strong> for Moral Theory, Cambridge, S. 133–67.1998 [282] Milo, R<strong>on</strong>ald D. (1998): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Knowledge, and Wickedness, in <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr. und Jeffrey Paul, Cambridge, S. 196–232.1992 [283] M<strong>on</strong>tague, Phillip (1992): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics: A Qualified Success Story, American PhilosophicalQuarterly 29. Wiederabgedruckt in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> DanielStatman, Edinburgh 1997, S. 194–204.1998 [284] M<strong>on</strong>tmarquet, James A. (1998): An Asymmetry C<strong>on</strong>cerning <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, Canadian Journalof Philosophy 28, S. 149–59.2008 [285] M<strong>on</strong>tmarquet, James A. (2008): The Voluntariness of <strong>Virtue</strong> – and Belief, Philosophy 83, S.373–90. 661990 [286] Moravcsik, Julius M. (1990): The Role of <strong>Virtue</strong> in Alternatives to Kantian and UtilitarianEthics, Philosophia 20, S. 33–48.1998 [287] Müller, Anselm Winfried (1998): Was taugt die Tugend? Elemente einer Ethik des gutenLebens. Mit einem Gespräch mit August Everding, Stuttgart: Kohlhammer.1996 [288] Nida-Rümelin, Julian (1996): Theoretische und Angewandte Ethik: Paradigmen,Begründungen, Bereiche, in Angewandte Ethik. Die Bereichsethiken und ihretheoretische Fundierung. Ein Handbuch, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Julian Nida-Rümelin, Stuttgart, S.2–85: S. 31–37 („Das tugendethische Paradigma (<str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>)“).1984 [289] Nielsen, Kai (1984): Critique of Pure <strong>Virtue</strong>. Animadversi<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> a <strong>Virtue</strong>-Based Ethic, in <strong>Virtue</strong>and Medicine, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> E. E. Shelp, Dordrecht, S. 133–49. Wiederabgedruckt in6566experimental results from social psychology c<strong>on</strong>cerning helping behavior are best explained not byappealing to so-called ‘global’ character traits like compassi<strong>on</strong>, but rather by appealing to externalsituati<strong>on</strong>al forces or, at best, to highly individualized ‘local’ character traits. In resp<strong>on</strong>se, a number ofphilosophers have argued that virtue ethics can accommodate the empirical results in questi<strong>on</strong>. My ownview is that neither side of this debate is looking in the right directi<strong>on</strong>. For there is an impressive array ofevidence from the social psychology literature which suggests that many people do possess <strong>on</strong>e or morerobust global character traits pertaining to helping others in need. But at the same time, such traits arenoticeably different from a traditi<strong>on</strong>al virtue like compassi<strong>on</strong>.”“I first summarize the central issues in the debate about the empirical adequacy of virtue ethics, and thenexamine the role that social psychologists claim positive and negative mood have in influencingcompassi<strong>on</strong>ate helping behavior. I argue that this psychological research is compatible with the claim thatmany people might instantiate certain character traits after all which allow them to help others in a widevariety of circumstances. Unfortunately for the virtue ethicist, however, it turns out that these helping traitsfall well short of exhibiting certain central features of compassi<strong>on</strong>.”“This paper examines the relative voluntariness of three types of virtue: ‘epistemic’ virtues like openmindedness;‘motivati<strong>on</strong>al’ virtues like courage, and more robustly ‘moral’ virtues like justice. A somewhatnovel c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of the voluntariness of belief is offered in terms of the limited, but quite real, voluntarinessof certain epistemic virtues.”29


Nielsen, Why Be Moral?, Buffalo, New York 1989, S. 228–44. [Zu MacIntyre, After<strong>Virtue</strong>]1998 [290] Norman, Richard (1998): The Moral Philosophers. An Introducti<strong>on</strong> to Ethics, 2. Aufl., Oxford,S. 197–200 (“<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics”).1991 [291] Nort<strong>on</strong>, David L. (1991): Democracy and Moral Development: A Politics of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Berkeley.1993 [292] Nussbaum, Martha (1993): N<strong>on</strong>-Relative <strong>Virtue</strong>s: An Aristotelian Approach, in The Quality ofLife, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Martha C. Nussbaum und Amartya Sen, Oxford, S. 242–70. – NichtrelativeTugenden: Ein aristotelischer Ansatz, in <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Klaus PeterRippe und Peter Schaber, Stuttgart 1998, S. 114–65. – Vgl. dazu: Hurley, Susan L.(1993): Commentary <strong>on</strong> Martha Nussbaum, “N<strong>on</strong>-Relative <strong>Virtue</strong>s: An AristotelianApproach”, in The Quality of Life, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Martha C. Nussbaum und Amartya Sen,Oxford, S. 270–76.1999 [293] Nussbaum, Martha (1999): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics: A Misleading Category?, Journal of Ethics 3, S. 163–201. 671996 [294] Oakley, Justin (1996): Varieties of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Ratio (New Series) 9, S. 128–52.1998 [295] Oakley, Justin (1998): A <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics Approach, in A Compani<strong>on</strong> to Bioethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> HelgaKuhse und Peter Singer, Oxford, S. 86–97.2001 [296] Oakley, Justin/Cocking, Dean (2001): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Professi<strong>on</strong>al Roles, Cambridge.1988 [297] O’C<strong>on</strong>nor, David (1988): Aristotelian Justice as a Pers<strong>on</strong>al <strong>Virtue</strong>, in Midwest Studies inPhilosophy Vol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A.French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 417–27.1999 [298] Oderberg, David S. (1999): On the Cardinality of the Cardinal <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Internati<strong>on</strong>al Journal ofPhilosophical Studies 7, S. 305–22. 6867“<strong>Virtue</strong> ethics is standardly taught and discussed as a distinctive approach to the major questi<strong>on</strong>s of ethics, athird major positi<strong>on</strong> al<strong>on</strong>gside Utilitarian and Kantian ethics. I argue that this tax<strong>on</strong>omy is a c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong>.Both Utilitarianism and Kantianism c<strong>on</strong>-tain treatments of virtue, so virtue ethics cannot possibly be aseparate approach c<strong>on</strong>trasted with those approaches. There are, to be sure, quite a few c<strong>on</strong>temporaryphilosophical writers about virtue who are neither Utilitarians nor Kantians; many of these find inspirati<strong>on</strong>in ancient Greek theories of virtue. But even here there is little unity. Although certain c<strong>on</strong>cerns do unitethis disparate group (a c<strong>on</strong>cern for the role of motives and passi<strong>on</strong>s in good choice, a c<strong>on</strong>cern for character,and a c<strong>on</strong>cern for the whole course of an agent’s life), there are equally profound disagreements, especiallyc<strong>on</strong>cerning the role that reas<strong>on</strong> should play in ethics. One group of modern virtue-theorists, I argue, areprimarily anti-Utilitarians, c<strong>on</strong>cerned with the plurality of value and the susceptibility of passi<strong>on</strong>s to socialcultivati<strong>on</strong>. These theorists want to enlarge the place of reas<strong>on</strong> in ethics. They hold that reas<strong>on</strong> candeliberate about ends as well as means, and that reas<strong>on</strong> can modify the passi<strong>on</strong>s themselves. Another groupof virtue theorists are primarily anti-Kantians. They believe that reas<strong>on</strong> plays too dominant a role in mostphilosophical accounts of ethics, and that a larger place should be given to sentiments and passi<strong>on</strong>s – whichthey typically c<strong>on</strong>strue in a less reas<strong>on</strong>-based way than does the first group. The paper investigates thesedifferences, c<strong>on</strong>cluding that it is not helpful to speak of “virtue ethics,” and that we wouldbe better offcharacterizing the substantive views of each thinker – and then figuring out what we ourselves want to say.”30


2000 [299] Oderberg, David S. (2000): Moral Theory. A N<strong>on</strong>-C<strong>on</strong>sequentialist Approach, Oxford, S. 45–53(“<strong>Virtue</strong>“).2002 [300] Oderberg, David (2002): Review of Hursthouse, On <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Philosophical Books 43 , S.159–63.1996 [301] Okin, Susan Moller (1996): Feminism, Moral Development, and the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, in How ShouldOne Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 211–29.1993 [302] O’Neill, Onora (1993): Duties and <strong>Virtue</strong>s, in Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> A.Phillips Griffiths, Cambridge, S. 107–20.1996 [303] O’Neill, Onora (1996): Kant’s <strong>Virtue</strong>s, in How Should One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg.v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 77–97.1996 [304] O’Neill, Onora (1996): Towards Justice and <strong>Virtue</strong>. A C<strong>on</strong>structive Account of PracticalReas<strong>on</strong>ing, Cambridge. – Tugend und Gerechtigkeit: eine k<strong>on</strong>struktive Darstellung despraktischen Denkens, Berlin 1996.2004 [305] O’Neill, Onora (2004): C<strong>on</strong>sequences for N<strong>on</strong>-c<strong>on</strong>sequentialists, Utilitas 16, S. 1–11. 69 – Zu[127].1998 [306] Paul, Ellen Frankel/Miller, Jr., Fred D./Paul, Jeffrey (Hrsg.) (1998): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice,Cambridge.1984 [307] Pence, Greg (1984): Recent Work <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, American Philosophical Quarterly 21, S. 281–97.1991 [308] Pence, Greg (1991): <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory, in A Compani<strong>on</strong> to Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter Singer, Oxford,S. 249–58.1992 [309] Perry, Michael J. (1992): <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Relativism, in <strong>Virtue</strong>, Nomos 34, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> John W.Chapman und William A. Galst<strong>on</strong>, New York, S. 117–31.6869“This paper is a detailed study of what are traditi<strong>on</strong>ally called the cardinal virtues: prudence, justice,temperance and fortitude. I defend what I call the Cardinality Thesis, that the traditi<strong>on</strong>al four and no othersare cardinal. I define cardinality in terms of three sub-theses, the first being that the cardinal virtues arejointly necessary for the possessi<strong>on</strong> of every other virtue, the sec<strong>on</strong>d that each of the other virtues is aspecies of <strong>on</strong>e of the four cardinals, and the third that many of the other virtues are also auxiliaries of <strong>on</strong>e ormore cardinals. I provide abstract arguments for each sub-thesis, followed by illustrati<strong>on</strong> from c<strong>on</strong>cretecases. I then use these results to shed light <strong>on</strong> the two fundamental problems of the acquisiti<strong>on</strong> of the virtuesand their unity, proving some further theses in the latter case.”“Both c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist and n<strong>on</strong>-c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist ethical reas<strong>on</strong>ing have difficulties in accounting for thevalue of c<strong>on</strong>sequences. Taken neat, c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism is too fierce in its emphasis <strong>on</strong> success and disregardof luck, while n<strong>on</strong>-c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism seemingly over-values inner states and undervalues actual results. InUneasy <strong>Virtue</strong> Julia Driver proposes a form of objective c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism which claims that characters aregood if they typically (but not invariably) produce good results. This positi<strong>on</strong> addresses the problems moralluck raises for c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, but requires some form of realism about traits of character. However, if ourknowledge of mental states is ascriptive, this form of objective c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism may make excessivedemands. N<strong>on</strong>-c<strong>on</strong>sequentialists may gain in so far as the theories of acti<strong>on</strong> to which they are typicallycommitted are less demanding, and are built to take account of the typical or systematic c<strong>on</strong>necti<strong>on</strong>sbetween states of character and results of acti<strong>on</strong>.”31


1971 [310] Pincoffs, Edmund L. (1971): Quandary Ethics, Mind 80, S. 552–71. Wiederabgedruckt inEthical Theory, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> James Rachels, Oxford 1998, S. 435–53.1986 [311] Pincoffs, Edmund L. (1986): Quandaries and <strong>Virtue</strong>s. Against Reductivism in Ethics, Lawrence.1992 [312] Pincoffs, Edmund L. (1992): <strong>Virtue</strong>s, in Encyclopedia of Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Lawrence C. Beckerund Charlotte B. Becker, New York, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, Vol. II, S. 1283–1288.1990 [313] Pojman, Louis P. (1990): Ethics. Discovering Right and Wr<strong>on</strong>g, Belm<strong>on</strong>t, Cal., S. 114–35(“<strong>Virtue</strong>-Based Ethical Systems”).2003 [314] Pollard, Bill (2003): Can Virtuous Acti<strong>on</strong>s be Both Habitual and Rati<strong>on</strong>al?, Ethical Theory andMoral Practice 6, S. 411–25. 701991 [315] Poole, Ross (1991): Morality and Modernity, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, S. 56–64.1997 [316] Preußner, Andreas (1997): Die Komplexität der Tugend: eine historisch-systematische Untersuchung,Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann (Epistemata: Reihe Philosophie 199,Zugl.: Wuppertal, Univ., Diss., 1995)2009 [317] Prinz, Jesse (2009): The Normativity Challenge: Cultural Psychology Provides the Real Threatto <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Journal of Ethics 13, S. 117–44. 711991 [318] Prior, William J. (1991): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Knowledge. An Introducti<strong>on</strong> to Ancient Greek Ethics,L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>.1987 [319] Putman, Daniel (1987): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Self-Decepti<strong>on</strong>, Southern Journal of Philosophy 25, S. 549–57.1991 [320] Putman, Daniel (1991): Relati<strong>on</strong>al Ethics and <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory, Metaphilosophy 22, S. 231–38.1992 [321] Putman, Daniel (1992): Egoism and <strong>Virtue</strong>, Journal of Value Inquiry 26, S. 117–24.1995 [322] Putman, Daniel (1995): The Primacy of <strong>Virtue</strong> in Children’s Moral Development, Journal of7071“Virtuous acti<strong>on</strong>s seem to be both habitual and rati<strong>on</strong>al. But if we combine an intuitive understanding ofhabituality with the currently predominant paradigm of rati<strong>on</strong>al acti<strong>on</strong>, these two features of virtuousacti<strong>on</strong>s are hard to rec<strong>on</strong>cile. Intuitively, acting habitually is acting as <strong>on</strong>e has before in similar c<strong>on</strong>texts,and automatically, that is, without thinking about it. Meanwhile, c<strong>on</strong>temporary philosophers tend to assumethe truth of what I call “the reas<strong>on</strong>s theory of rati<strong>on</strong>al acti<strong>on</strong>”, which states that all rati<strong>on</strong>al acti<strong>on</strong>s are“acti<strong>on</strong>s for reas<strong>on</strong>s”. Whilst interpretati<strong>on</strong>s of this phrase are disputed, I argue that neither of the twoleading views – which I call “reas<strong>on</strong>s internalism” and “reas<strong>on</strong>s externalism” – makes room for habitualacti<strong>on</strong>s to count as acti<strong>on</strong>s for reas<strong>on</strong>s; by the reas<strong>on</strong>s theory, they cannot be rati<strong>on</strong>al either. I suggest <strong>on</strong>eway of effecting the rec<strong>on</strong>ciliati<strong>on</strong> which, whilst it allows us to keep the reas<strong>on</strong>s theory, requires us toc<strong>on</strong>ceive of reas<strong>on</strong>s as even more radically external than current externalists believe them to be.”“Situati<strong>on</strong>ists argue that virtue ethics is empirically untenable, since traditi<strong>on</strong>al virtue ethicists postulatebroad, efficacious character traits, and social psychology suggests that such traits do not exist. I argue thatprominent philosophical replies to this challenge do not succeed. But cross-cultural research gives reas<strong>on</strong> topostulate character traits, and this undermines the situati<strong>on</strong>ist critique. There is, however, another empiricalchallenge to virtue ethics that is harder to escape. Character traits are culturally informed, as are our idealsof what traits are virtuous, and our ideals of what qualifies as well-being. If virtues and well-being areculturally c<strong>on</strong>structed ideals, then the standard strategy for grounding the normativity of virtue ethics inhuman nature is undermined.”32


Moral Educati<strong>on</strong> 24, S. 175–184.1997 [323] Putman, Daniel (1997): The Intellectual Bias of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Philosophy 72, S. 303–11.1998 [324] Putman, Daniel (1998): Human Excellence. Dialogues <strong>on</strong> <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory, Lanham.1988 [325] Putnam, Ruth Anna (1988): Reciprocity and <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Ethics 98, S. 379–89.1993 [326] Rachels, James (1993): The Elements of Moral Philosophy, New York, 2. Aufl., S. 159–79(“The Ethics of <strong>Virtue</strong>”).1998 [327] Ramsay, Hayden (1998): Natural <strong>Virtue</strong>, Dialogue 37, S. 341–60.2001 [328] Read, Rupert (2001): Review of Rosalind Hursthouse, On <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, PhilosophicalInvestigati<strong>on</strong>s 24, S. 274–82.2000 [329] Reader, Soran (2000): New Directi<strong>on</strong>s in Ethics: Naturalisms, Reas<strong>on</strong>s and <strong>Virtue</strong>, EthicalTheory and Moral Practice 3, S. 341–64.1997 [330] Reese-Schäfer, Walter (1997): Grenzgötter der Moral. Der neuere europäisch-amerikanischeDiskurs <str<strong>on</strong>g>zur</str<strong>on</strong>g> politischen Ethik, Frankfurt a. M., S. 309–61 („DemokratischeTugendlehre“).1988 [331] Regan, S.J., Richard J. (1988): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Religi<strong>on</strong>, and Civic Culture, in Midwest Studies inPhilosophy Vol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A.French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 342–51.2001 [332] Rh<strong>on</strong>heimer, Martin (2001): Die Perspektive der Moral. Philosophische Grundlagen der<str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, Berlin.1999 [333] Richter, Duncan (1999): <strong>Virtue</strong> Without Theory, Journal of Value Inquiry 33, S. 353–69.1994 [334] Richards<strong>on</strong>, Henry S. (1994): Rescuing Ethical Theory, Philosophy and PhenomenologicalResearch 54, S. 703–8. (Zu M. Slote, From Morality to <strong>Virtue</strong>)1998 [335] Rippe, Klaus Peter/Schaber, Peter (1998): Einleitung, in dies. (Hrsg.), <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, Stuttgart, S.7–18.1998 [336] Rippe, Klaus Peter/Schaber, Peter (Hrsg.) (1998): <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, Stuttgart.1991 [337] Roberts, Robert C. (1991): <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Rules, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51,S. 325–43.1988 [338] Rorty, Amelie Oksenberg (1988): <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Their Vicissitudes, in Midwest Studies in PhilosophyVol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French,Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 136–48.1996 [339] Roughley, Neil (1996): Tugend, in Enzyklopädie Philosophie und Wissenschaftstheorie Bd. 4,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Jürgen Mittelstraß, Stuttgart, S. 344–50.2008 [340] Russell, Daniel C. (2008): Agent-Based <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and the Fundamentality of <strong>Virtue</strong>,American Philosophical Quarterly 45, S. 329–48.2008 [341] Russell, Daniel C. (2008): That “Ought” Does Not Imply “Right”: Why It Matters for <strong>Virtue</strong>Ethics, Southern Journal of Philosophy 46, S. 299–315.33


2009 [342] Russell, Daniel C. (2009): Practical Intelligence and the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Oxford. 722005 [343] Sabini, John/Silver, Maury (2005): Lack of Character? Situati<strong>on</strong>ism Critiqued, Ethics 115, S.535–62.2005 [344] Sandler, R<strong>on</strong>ald (2005): What Makes a Character Trait a <strong>Virtue</strong>?, Journal of Value Inquiry 39,S. 383–97.1993 [345] Santas, Gerasimos X. (1993): Does Aristotle Have a <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics?, Philosophical Inquiry 15.Wiederabgedruckt (in revidierter Versi<strong>on</strong>) in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg.v<strong>on</strong> Daniel Statman, Edinburgh 1997, S. 260–85.1990 [346] Schaller, Walter E. (1990): Are <strong>Virtue</strong>s No More Than Dispositi<strong>on</strong>s to Obey Moral Rules?,Philosophia 20, S. 195–207.1990 [347] Schneewind, J. B. (1990): The Misfortunes of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Ethics 101, S. 42–63. Wiederabgedrucktin <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp und Michael Slote, Oxford 1997, S. 178–200.1997 [348] Schuster, Josef (1997): Moralisches Können. Studien <str<strong>on</strong>g>zur</str<strong>on</strong>g> <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, Würzburg.2004 [349] Schuster, Josef (2004): Gefühle und ethische Tugenden, in Abwägende Vernunft. PraktischeRati<strong>on</strong>alität in historischer, systematischer und religi<strong>on</strong>sphilosophischer Perspektive,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Franz-Josef Bormann und Christian Schröer, Berlin, S. 361–80.1974 [350] Seeskin, Kenneth (1974): Courage and Knowledge: A Perspective <strong>on</strong> the Socratic Paradox,72Publisher’s Descripti<strong>on</strong>: “One of the most important developments in modern moral philosophy is theresurgence of interest in the virtues. In this new book, Daniel Russell explores two important hopes for suchan approach to moral thought: that starting from the virtues should cast light <strong>on</strong> what makes an acti<strong>on</strong>right, and that noti<strong>on</strong>s like character, virtue, and vice should yield a plausible picture of human psychology.Russell argues that the key to each of these hopes is an understanding of the cognitive and deliberative skillsinvolved in the virtues. If right acti<strong>on</strong> is defined in terms of acting generously or kindly, then these virtuesmust involve skills for determining what the kind or generous thing to do would be <strong>on</strong> a given occasi<strong>on</strong>.Likewise, Russell argues that understanding virtuous acti<strong>on</strong> as the intelligent pursuit of virtuous goals yieldsa promising picture of the psychology of virtue. This book develops an Aristotelian account of the virtue ofpractical intelligence or ‘phr<strong>on</strong>esis’ – an excellence of deliberating and making choices – which Russellargues is a necessary part of every virtue. This emphasis <strong>on</strong> the roots of the virtues in the practical intellectc<strong>on</strong>trasts with ambivalence about the practical intellect in much recent work <strong>on</strong> the virtues – a trend Russellargues is ultimately perilous for virtue theory. This book also takes a penetrating look at issues like the unityof the virtues, resp<strong>on</strong>sibility for character, and that elusive figure, ‘the virtuous pers<strong>on</strong>’. Written in a clearand careful manner, Practical Intelligence and the <strong>Virtue</strong>s will appeal to philosophers and students alike inmoral philosophy and moral psychology.”C<strong>on</strong>tents: 1. Practical Intelligence and the <strong>Virtue</strong>s: An Aristotelian Approach. Part 1. Phr<strong>on</strong>esis, <strong>Virtue</strong>,and Right Acti<strong>on</strong>. 2. Right Acti<strong>on</strong> for <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. 3. Right Acti<strong>on</strong> and Virtuous Motives. 4. Right Acti<strong>on</strong>and ‘the Virtuous Pers<strong>on</strong>’. Part 2. The Enumerati<strong>on</strong> Problem. 5. The Enumerati<strong>on</strong> Problem. 6.Individuating the <strong>Virtue</strong>s. 7. Magnificence, Generosity, and Subordinati<strong>on</strong>. Part 3. Situati<strong>on</strong>s,Dispositi<strong>on</strong>s, and <strong>Virtue</strong>s. 8. Situati<strong>on</strong>s and Broad-Based Dispositi<strong>on</strong>s. 9. Situati<strong>on</strong>s and Dispositi<strong>on</strong>s:Examining the Evidence. 10. From Situati<strong>on</strong>ism to <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory. Part 4. Defending Hard <strong>Virtue</strong>Theory. 11. Phr<strong>on</strong>esis and the Unity of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s. 12. Resp<strong>on</strong>sibility for Character. Works Cited. IndexLocorum. General Index.34


Southern Journal of Philosophy 14, S. 511–21.2007 [351] Setiya, Kieran (2007): Reas<strong>on</strong>s without Rati<strong>on</strong>alism, Princet<strong>on</strong>. 731991 [352] Seung, T. K. (Hrsg.) (1991): The Nature of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics: its Political Relevance. A C<strong>on</strong>ferenceH<strong>on</strong>oring Edmund L. Pincoffs, Social Theory and Practice 17 (2), S. 137–344.1999 [353] Shaw, William H. (1999): C<strong>on</strong>temporary Ethics. Taking Account of Utilitarianism, Oxford, S.252–61.1992 [354] Sher, George (1992): Knowing about <strong>Virtue</strong>, in <strong>Virtue</strong> (Nomos 34), hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> John W.Chapman und William A. Galst<strong>on</strong>, New York, S. 91–116.1988 [355] Sherman, Nancy (1988): Comm<strong>on</strong> Sense and Uncomm<strong>on</strong> <strong>Virtue</strong>, in Midwest Studies inPhilosophy Vol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A.French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 97–114.1989 [356] Sherman, Nancy (1989): The Fabric of Character. Aristotle’s Theory of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Oxford.1993 [357] Sherman, Nancy (1993): The <strong>Virtue</strong>s of Comm<strong>on</strong> Pursuit, Philosophy and PhenomenologicalResearch 53, S. 277–99.1997 [358] Sherman, Nancy (1997): Kantian <strong>Virtue</strong>: Priggish or Passi<strong>on</strong>al?, in Reclaiming the History ofEthics. Essays for John Rawls, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Andrews Reath, Barbara Herman undChristine M. Korsgaard, Cambridge, S. 270–96.1997 [359] Sherman, Nancy (1997): Making a Necessity of <strong>Virtue</strong>. Aristotle and Kant <strong>on</strong> <strong>Virtue</strong>,Cambridge.1997 [360] Sherman, Nancy (2005): The Look and Feel of <strong>Virtue</strong>, in <strong>Virtue</strong>, Norms, and Objectivity. Issuesin Ancient and Modern Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Christopher Gill, Oxford, S. 59–82.73“Modern philosophy has been vexed by the questi<strong>on</strong> “Why should I be moral?” and by doubts about therati<strong>on</strong>al authority of moral virtue. In Reas<strong>on</strong>s without Rati<strong>on</strong>alism, Kieran Setiya shows that these doubtsrest <strong>on</strong> a mistake. The “should” of practical reas<strong>on</strong> cannot be understood apart from the virtues of character,including such moral virtues as justice and benevolence, and the c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s to which the virtues make<strong>on</strong>e sensitive thereby count as reas<strong>on</strong>s to act. Proposing a new framework for debates about practical reas<strong>on</strong>,Setiya argues that the <strong>on</strong>ly alternative to this “virtue theory” is a form of ethical rati<strong>on</strong>alism in whichreas<strong>on</strong>s derive from the nature of intenti<strong>on</strong>al acti<strong>on</strong>. Despite its recent popularity, however, ethicalrati<strong>on</strong>alism is false. It wr<strong>on</strong>gly assumes that we act “under the guise of the good,” or it relies <strong>on</strong> dubiousviews about intenti<strong>on</strong> and motivati<strong>on</strong>. It follows from the failure of rati<strong>on</strong>alism that the virtue theory is true:we cannot be fully good without the perfecti<strong>on</strong> of practical reas<strong>on</strong>, or have that perfecti<strong>on</strong> without beinggood. Addressing such topics as the psychology of virtue and the explanati<strong>on</strong> of acti<strong>on</strong>, "Reas<strong>on</strong>s withoutRati<strong>on</strong>alism" is essential reading for philosophers interested in ethics, rati<strong>on</strong>ality, or the philosophy ofmind.”C<strong>on</strong>tents: Preface ix – Introducti<strong>on</strong> 1 – 1. “Squeezing the Good into the Right through the Tubes ofImperfecti<strong>on</strong>” 7 – 2. The Relevance of Acti<strong>on</strong> Theory 14 – PART ONE: Explaining Acti<strong>on</strong> 21 – 1. A Puzzleabout Intenti<strong>on</strong> 23 – 2. The Belief-Desire Model 28 – 3. Acting for Reas<strong>on</strong>s 39 – 4. Solving the Puzzle 48 –5. A Causal Theory of Acti<strong>on</strong>? 56 – 6. Against the Guise of the Good 59 – PART TWO: Why <strong>Virtue</strong>Matters to the Study of Practical Reas<strong>on</strong> 68 – 1. Character and Practical Thought 70 – 2. An Argument forthe <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory 79 – 3. Practical Reas<strong>on</strong> and the Guise of the Good 86 – 4. Motivati<strong>on</strong> and Desire 99 – 5.Self-Knowledge as the Aim of Acti<strong>on</strong> 107 – C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> 116 – <str<strong>on</strong>g>Bibliography</str<strong>on</strong>g> 121 – Index 129.35


2003 [361] Sherman, Nancy/White, Heath (2003): Intellectual <strong>Virtue</strong>: Emoti<strong>on</strong>s, Luck, and the Ancients, inIntellectual <strong>Virtue</strong> – Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> MichealDePaul und Linda Zagzebski, Oxford, S. 34–54.1992 [362] Shklar, Judith N. (1992): Justice without <strong>Virtue</strong>, in <strong>Virtue</strong> (Nomos 34), hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> John W.Chapman und William A. Galst<strong>on</strong>, New York, S. 283–88.2004 [363] Siep, Ludwig (2004): Vernunft und Tugend, in Abwägende Vernunft. Praktische Rati<strong>on</strong>alität inhistorischer, systematischer und religi<strong>on</strong>sphilosophischer Perspektive, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Franz-Josef Bormann und Christian Schröer, Berlin, S. 344–60.2005 [364] Siep, Ludwig (2005): <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Values, and Moral Objectivity, in <strong>Virtue</strong>, Norms, and Objectivity.Issues in Ancient and Modern Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Christopher Gill, Oxford, S. 83–98.1992 [365] Simps<strong>on</strong>, Peter (1992): C<strong>on</strong>temporary <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Aristotle, Review of Metaphysics, 46,S. 503–24. Wiederabgedruckt in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> DanielStatman, Edinburgh 1997, S. 245–59.1997 [366] Skillen, T<strong>on</strong>y (1997): Can <strong>Virtue</strong> be Taught – Especially these Days?, Journal of Philosophy ofEducati<strong>on</strong> 31, S. 375–394.1982 [367] Slote, Michael (1982): Is <strong>Virtue</strong> Possible?, Analysis 42, S. 70–76.1983 [368] Slote, Michael (1983): Goods and <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Oxford 1989 (mit neuem Vorwort 1989).1988 [369] Slote, Michael (1988): Utilitarian <strong>Virtue</strong>, in Midwest Studies in Philosophy Vol. XIII: EthicalTheory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. undHoward K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 384–97.1990 [370] Slote, Michael (1990): Some Advantages of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Identity, Character, and Morality.Essays in Moral Psychology, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Owen Flanagan und Amélie Oksenberg Rorty,Cambridge, Mass., S. 429–48.1992 [371] Slote, Michael (1992): From Morality to <strong>Virtue</strong>, New York, Oxford.1993 [372] Slote, Michael (1993): <strong>Virtue</strong>, in A Compani<strong>on</strong> to C<strong>on</strong>temporary Political Philosophy, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>Robert E. Goodin und Philip Pettit, Oxford, S. 645–50.1993 [373] Slote, Michael (1993): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Democratic Values, Journal of Social Philosophy 24,S. 5–37.1994 [374] Slote, Michael (1994): Precis of “From Morality to <strong>Virtue</strong>”, Philosophy and PhenomenologicalResearch 54, S. 683–87.1994 [375] Slote, Michael (1994): Reply to Commentators, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 54,S. 709–19.1995 [376] Slote, Michael (1995): Law in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Law and Philosophy 14, S. 91–114.1996 [377] Slote, Michael (1996): Agent-Based <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Midwest Studies in Philosophy Vol. XX:Moral C<strong>on</strong>cepts, S. 83–101. Wiederabgedruckt in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crispund Michael Slote, Oxford 1997, S. 239–62.1996 [378] Slote, Michael (1996): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Utilitarianism, and Symmetry, in How Should One Live?Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 99–110.36


1997 [379] Slote, Michael (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Marcia W. Bar<strong>on</strong>, Philip Pettit, Michael Slote, ThreeMethods of Ethics: A Debate, Oxford, S. 175–238.1997 [380] Slote, Michael (1997): The <strong>Virtue</strong> in Self-Interest, Social Philosophy and Policy 14, S. 264–285.1998 [381] Slote, Michael (1998): The Justice of Caring, in <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Ellen Frankel Paul,Fred D. Miller, Jr. und Jeffrey Paul, Cambridge, S. 171–95.2000 [382] Slote, Michael (2000): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> HughLaFollette, Oxford, S. 325–47.2001 [383] Slote, Michael (2001): Morals from Motives, Oxford.2003 [384] Slote, Michael (2003): Sentimentalist <strong>Virtue</strong> and Moral Judgement: Outline of a Project,Metaphilosophy 34, S. 131–143. 742004 [385] Slote, Michael (2004): Driver’s <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Utilitas 16, S. 22–32. 75 – Zu [127].1992 [386] Smith, Rogers M. (1992): On the Good of Knowing <strong>Virtue</strong>, in <strong>Virtue</strong> (Nomos 34), hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>John W. Chapman und William A. Galst<strong>on</strong>, New York, S. 132–42.2003 [387] Smith, R. Scott (2003): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Moral Knowledge. Philosophy of Language afterMacIntyre and Hauerwas, Aldershot.1999 [388] Smith, Tara (1999): Justice as a Pers<strong>on</strong>al <strong>Virtue</strong>, Social Theory and Practice 25, S. 361–84.2008 [389] Snow, Nancy (2008): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Flourishing, Journal of Social Philosophy 39, S. 225–45.1988 [390] Solom<strong>on</strong>, David (1988): Internal Objecti<strong>on</strong>s to <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Midwest Studies in PhilosophyVol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, Notre Dame, S. 428–41. Wiederabgedrucktin <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Daniel Statman, Edinburgh 1997,7475“Ethical rati<strong>on</strong>alism has recently dominated the philosophical landscape, but sentimentalist forms ofnormative ethics (such as the ethics of caring) and of metaethics (such as Blackburn’s projectivism andvarious ideal-observer and resp<strong>on</strong>se-dependent views) have also been prominent. But n<strong>on</strong>e of this has beensystematic in the manner of Hume and Hutches<strong>on</strong>. Hume based both ethics and metaethics in his noti<strong>on</strong> ofsympathy, but the project sketched here focuses rather <strong>on</strong> the (related) noti<strong>on</strong> of empathy. I argue thatempathy is essential to the development of morally required caring about others and also to de<strong>on</strong>tologicallimits or restricti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> self-c<strong>on</strong>cern and other-c<strong>on</strong>cern. But empathy also plays a grounding role in moraljudgement. Moral approval and disapproval can be n<strong>on</strong>-circularly understood as empathic reflecti<strong>on</strong>s of thec<strong>on</strong>cern or lack of c<strong>on</strong>cern that agents show towards other people; and moral utterances can plausibly beseen not as projecti<strong>on</strong>s, expressi<strong>on</strong>s, or descripti<strong>on</strong>s of sentiment but as “objective” and “n<strong>on</strong>-relative”judgements whose reference and c<strong>on</strong>tent are fixed by sentiments of approval and disapproval.”“Julia Driver’s Uneasy <strong>Virtue</strong> offers a theory of virtue and the virtues without being an instance of virtueethics. It presents a c<strong>on</strong>sequentialist challenge to recent virtue ethics, but its positive views – and especiallyits interesting examples – have great significance in their own right. Driver’s defence of ‘virtues ofignorance’ has force despite all the challenges to it that have been mounted over the years. But there arealso examples differing from those Driver has menti<strong>on</strong>ed that favour the idea of such virtues. Perhapscertain virtues of religious faith and the virtue necessary for dealing as best <strong>on</strong>e can with moral dilemmasboth require ignorance. However, some of the examples Driver does discuss raise the questi<strong>on</strong> whethervirtue status is based solely <strong>on</strong> c<strong>on</strong>sequences, rather than perhaps having (in additi<strong>on</strong>) a motivati<strong>on</strong>alcomp<strong>on</strong>ent.”37


S. 165–79.2003 [391] Solom<strong>on</strong>, David (2003): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics: Radical or Routine? in Intellectual <strong>Virtue</strong> – Perspectivesfrom Ethics and Epistemology, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Micheal DePaul und Linda Zagzebski,Oxford, S. 57–80.1988 [392] Solom<strong>on</strong>, Robert C. (1988): The <strong>Virtue</strong> of Love, in Midwest Studies in Philosophy Vol. XIII:Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French, Theodore E. Uehling,Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 12–31.1992 [393] Solom<strong>on</strong>, Robert C. (1992): Corporate Roles, Pers<strong>on</strong>al <strong>Virtue</strong>s: An Aristotelian Approach toBusiness Ethics, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Daniel Statman,Edinburgh 1997, S. 205–26.1998 [394] Solom<strong>on</strong>, Robert C. (1998): The <strong>Virtue</strong>s of a Passi<strong>on</strong>ate Life: Erotic Love and “the Will toPower”, in <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller, Jr. undJeffrey Paul, Cambridge, S. 91–118.2003 [395] Solom<strong>on</strong>, Robert C. (2003): Victims of Circumstances? A Defense of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics in Business,Business Ethics Quarterly 13, S. 43–62. – Dazu: [173].2005 [396] Solom<strong>on</strong>, Robert C. (2005): Erotic Love as a Moral <strong>Virtue</strong>, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Old and New, hrsg.v<strong>on</strong> Stephen M. Gardiner, Ithaca, S. 81–100.2005 [397] Solom<strong>on</strong>, Robert C. (2005): “What’s Character Got to Do with It?”, Philosophy andPhenomenological Research 71, S. 648–55. – Zu [118]. Vgl. dazu: [120].1992 [398] Spohn, William C. (1992): The Return of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Theological Studies 53, S. 60–75.2002 [399] Sreenivasan, Gopal (2002): Errors about Errors: <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory and Trait Attributi<strong>on</strong>, Mind 111,S. 47–68. 76 – Zu [117], [171]. Vgl. dazu: [475].2008 [400] Sreenivasan, Gopal (2008): Character and C<strong>on</strong>sistency: Still More Errors, Mind 117, S. 603–12. 77 – Zu [475].7677“This paper examines the implicati<strong>on</strong>s of certain social psychological experiments for moral theory –specifically, for virtue theory. Gilbert Harman and John Doris have recently argued that the empiricalevidence offered by ‘situati<strong>on</strong>ism’ dem<strong>on</strong>strates that there is no such thing as a character trait. I dispute thisc<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>. My discussi<strong>on</strong> focuses <strong>on</strong> the proper interpretati<strong>on</strong> of the experimental data – the datathemselves I grant for the sake of argument. I develop three criticisms of the anti-trait positi<strong>on</strong>. Of these, thecentral criticism c<strong>on</strong>cerns three respects in which the experimental situati<strong>on</strong>s employed to test some<strong>on</strong>e’scharacter trait are inadequate to the task. First, they do not take account of the subject’s own c<strong>on</strong>strual of thesituati<strong>on</strong>. Sec<strong>on</strong>d, they include behaviour that is <strong>on</strong>ly marginally relevant to the trait in questi<strong>on</strong>. Third,they disregard the normative character of the resp<strong>on</strong>ses in which virtue theory is interested. Given theseinadequacies in situati<strong>on</strong>ism’s operati<strong>on</strong>alized c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of a ‘character trait’, I argue that situati<strong>on</strong>ismdoes not really address the propositi<strong>on</strong> that people have ‘character traits’, properly understood. A fortiori,the social psychological evidence does not refute that propositi<strong>on</strong>. I also adduce some limited experimentalevidence in favour of character traits and distil two less<strong>on</strong>s we can nevertheless learn from situati<strong>on</strong>ism.”“This paper c<strong>on</strong>tinues a debate am<strong>on</strong>g philosophers c<strong>on</strong>cerning the implicati<strong>on</strong>s of situati<strong>on</strong>ist experimentsin social psychology for the theory of virtue. In a previous paper (2002), I argued am<strong>on</strong>g other things thatthe sort of character trait problematized by Hartshorne and May’s (1928) famous study of h<strong>on</strong>esty is not theright sort to trouble the theory of virtue. Webber (2006) criticizes my argument, alleging that it founders <strong>on</strong>38


2009 [401] Sreenivasan, Gopal (2009): Disunity of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Journal of Ethics 13, S. 195–212. 782008 [402] Stangl, Rebecca (2008): A Dilemma for Particularist <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Philosophical Quarterly 58,S. 665–78. 792001 [403] Stark, Susan (2001): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Emoti<strong>on</strong>, Nous 35, S. 440–55.2004 [404] Stark, Susan (2004): A Change of Heart: Moral Emoti<strong>on</strong>s, Transformati<strong>on</strong>, and Moral <strong>Virtue</strong>,Journal of Moral Philosophy 1, S. 31–50. 801995 [405] Statman, Daniel (1995): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Psychology, Internati<strong>on</strong>al Journal of AppliedPhilosophy 9, S. 43–50.1997 [406] Statman, Daniel (1997): Introducti<strong>on</strong> to <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg.v<strong>on</strong> Daniel Statman, Edinburgh, S. 1–41.1997 [407] Statman, Daniel (Hrsg.) (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, Edinburgh.1998 [408] Stemmer, P./Schönberger, R./Höffe, O./Rapp, Ch. (1998): Tugend, in Historisches Wörterbuchder Philosophie, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Joachim Ritter und Karlfried Gründer, Basel, Bd. 10, S.1532–70.787980an ambiguity in ‘cross-situati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>sistency’ and that Milgram’s (1974) obedience experiment is immuneto the objecti<strong>on</strong>s I levelled against Hartshorne and May. Here I resp<strong>on</strong>d to his criticisms. The most importanterror in Webber's argument is that it overlooks a distincti<strong>on</strong> between ‘<strong>on</strong>e time performance’ experimentsand ‘iterated trial’ experiments. I explain whythe former cannot begin to trouble the theory of virtue.”“This paper argues against the unity of the virtues, while trying to salvage some of its attractive aspects. Ifocus <strong>on</strong> the str<strong>on</strong>gest argument for the unity thesis, which begins from the premise that true virtue cannotlead its possessor morally astray. I suggest that this premise presupposes the possibility of completelyinsulating an agent’s set of virtues from any liability to moral error. I then distinguish three c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s thatseparately foreclose this possibility, c<strong>on</strong>centrating <strong>on</strong> the propositi<strong>on</strong> that there is more to morality thanvirtue al<strong>on</strong>e—that is, not all moral c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s are <strong>on</strong>es to which some virtue is characteristicallysensitive. If the virtues are not unified, the situati<strong>on</strong>ist critique of virtue ethics also turns out to be moredifficult to establish than some have supposed.”“There is an obvious affinity between virtue ethics and particularism. Both stress the complexity of themoral life, the inadequacy of rule-following as a guide to moral deliberati<strong>on</strong>, and the importance ofjudgement in discerning the morally relevant features of particular situati<strong>on</strong>s. Yet it remains an openquesti<strong>on</strong> how deep the affinity goes. I argue that the radical form of particularism defended by J<strong>on</strong>athanDancy has surprisingly str<strong>on</strong>g implicati<strong>on</strong>s for virtue ethics. Adopting such a view would require the virtuetheorist either to adopt an unattractive model of moral motivati<strong>on</strong> or to embrace a fairly str<strong>on</strong>g versi<strong>on</strong> ofthe unity of the virtues.”“Inspired in part by a renewed attenti<strong>on</strong> to Aristotle ’s moral philosophy, philosophers have acknowledgedthe important role of the emoti<strong>on</strong>s in morality. N<strong>on</strong>etheless, precisely how emoti<strong>on</strong>s matter to morality hasremained c<strong>on</strong>tentious. Aristotelians claim that moral virtue is c<strong>on</strong>stituted by correct acti<strong>on</strong> and correctemoti<strong>on</strong>. But Kantians seem to require solely that agents do morally correct acti<strong>on</strong>s out of respect for themoral law. There is a crucial philosophical disagreement between the Aristotelian and Kantian moraloutlooks: namely, is feeling the correct emoti<strong>on</strong>s necessary to virtue or is it an opti<strong>on</strong>al extra, which ispermitted but not required. I argue that there are good reas<strong>on</strong>s for siding with the Aristotelians: virtuousagents must experience the emoti<strong>on</strong>s appropriate to their situati<strong>on</strong>s. Moral virtue requires a change ofheart.”39


2007 [409] Stichter, Matt (2007): Ethical Expertise: The Skill Model of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Ethical Theory and MoralPractice 10, S. 183–94. 811979 [410] Stocker, Michael (1979): Good Intenti<strong>on</strong>s in Greek and Modern Moral <strong>Virtue</strong>, AustralasianJournal of Philosophy 57, S. 220–4.1994 [411] Stocker, Michael (1994): Self-Other Asymmetries and <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory, Philosophy and PhenomenologicalResearch 54, S. 689–94. (Zu M. Slote, From Morality to <strong>Virtue</strong>)1996 [412] Stocker, Michael (1996): How Emoti<strong>on</strong>s Reveal Value and Help Cure the Schizophrenia ofModern Ethical Theories, in How Should One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 173–90.1997 [413] Stocker, Michael (1997): Emoti<strong>on</strong>al Identificati<strong>on</strong>, Closeness and Size: Some C<strong>on</strong>tributi<strong>on</strong>s to<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Daniel Statman,Edinburgh, S. 118–27.2003 [414] Stohr, Karen E. (2003): Moral Cacoph<strong>on</strong>y: When C<strong>on</strong>tinence is a <strong>Virtue</strong>, Journal of Ethics 7, S.339–63. 822006 [415] Stohr, Karen E. (2006): C<strong>on</strong>temporary <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Philosophy Compass 1, S. 22–7.8182“Julia Annas is <strong>on</strong>e of the few modern writers <strong>on</strong> virtue that has attempted to recover the ancient idea thatvirtues are similar to skills. In doing so, she is arguing for a particular account of virtue, <strong>on</strong>e in which theintellectual structure of virtue is analogous to the intellectual structure of practical skills. The main benefitof this skill model of virtue is that it can ground a plausible account of the moral epistemology of virtue.This benefit, though, is <strong>on</strong>ly available to some accounts of virtue. Annas claims that Aristotle rejects thisskill model of virtue, and so the model of virtues as a skill that Annas endorses for the modern virtue theoryis Socratic. This paper argues that while Aristotle rejects the Socratic model of virtue as a skill, he does notreject the model of virtue as a skill altogether. Annas has mischaracterized Aristotle’s positi<strong>on</strong> <strong>on</strong> the skillmodel, because she has not recognized that Aristotle endorses a different account of the structure of skillthan the <strong>on</strong>e put forth by Socrates. In additi<strong>on</strong>, recent research <strong>on</strong> expertise provides an account of skillsvery much at odds with the descripti<strong>on</strong> of skills offered by Annas, but similar to the account endorsed byAristotle.C<strong>on</strong>trary to Annas, not <strong>on</strong>ly is the skill model of virtue compatible with a neo-Aristotelian accountof virtue, but it also appears that basing a skill model of virtue <strong>on</strong> a Socratic account of virtue is likely toprove unsuccessful.”“C<strong>on</strong>temporary virtue ethicists widely accept the thesis that a virtuous agent’s feelings should be inharm<strong>on</strong>y with her judgments about what she should do and that she should find virtuous acti<strong>on</strong> easy andpleasant. C<strong>on</strong>flict between an agent’s feelings and her acti<strong>on</strong>s, by c<strong>on</strong>trast, is thought to indicate merec<strong>on</strong>tinence – a moral deficiency. This “harm<strong>on</strong>y thesis” is generally taken to be a fundamental element ofAristotelian virtue ethics. I argue that the harm<strong>on</strong>y thesis, understood this way, is mistaken, because thereare occasi<strong>on</strong>s where a virtuous agent will find right acti<strong>on</strong> painful and difficult. What this means is that thegenerally accepted distincti<strong>on</strong> between c<strong>on</strong>tinence and virtue is unsupportable. This c<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong> affectsseveral well-known accounts of virtuous acti<strong>on</strong>, including those of Philippa Foot and John McDowell. Acloser look at Aristotle, however, provides another way of distinguishing between c<strong>on</strong>tinence and virtue,based in his categorizati<strong>on</strong> of goods as noble or base. I argue that virtue is exhibited when an agent’sfeelings harm<strong>on</strong>ize with his correct judgments of value, while discrepancies between feelings and correctjudgments of value indicate c<strong>on</strong>tinence. This understanding of c<strong>on</strong>tinence and virtue enables us toaccommodate the problem cases I raise.”40


2010 [416] Stohr, Karen E. (2010): Teaching & Learning Guide for: C<strong>on</strong>temporary <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics,Philosophy Compass 5, S. 102–7.1992 [417] Strauss, David A. (1992): The Liberal <strong>Virtue</strong>s, in <strong>Virtue</strong> (Nomos 34), hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> John W.Chapman und William A. Galst<strong>on</strong>, New York, S. 197–203.1998 [418] Sumner, L. W. (1998): Is <strong>Virtue</strong> Its Own Reward?, in <strong>Virtue</strong> and Vice, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Ellen FrankelPaul, Fred D. Miller, Jr. und Jeffrey Paul, Cambridge, S. 18–36.2010 [419] Svenss<strong>on</strong>, Frans (2010): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and the Search for an Account of Right Acti<strong>on</strong>, EthicalTheory and Moral Practice 13, S. 255–71. 831993 [420] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (1993): Commentary <strong>on</strong> Michael Slote’s “<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and DemocraticValue”, Journal of Social Philosophy 24, S. 38–49.1993 [421] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (1993): Satisficing and <strong>Virtue</strong>, Journal of Philosophy 90, S. 33–48.1995 [422] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (1995): Profiles of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76, S. 47–72.1997 [423] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Satisficing Rati<strong>on</strong>ality, <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A CriticalReader, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Daniel Statman, Edinburgh 1997, S. 82–98. (Revidierte Versi<strong>on</strong> v<strong>on</strong>“Satisficing and <strong>Virtue</strong>” (1993))1997 [424] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (1997): The Supposed Tensi<strong>on</strong> Between ‘Strength’ and ‘Gentleness’ C<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>sof the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 75, S. 497–510.1997 [425] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and the Problem of Indirecti<strong>on</strong>: A Pluralistic Value-Centered Approach, Utilitas 9, S. 167–81.2001 [426] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (2001): A <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethical Account of Right Acti<strong>on</strong>, Ethics 112, S. 32–52.2001 [427] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (2001): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Value-centredness, and C<strong>on</strong>sequentialism, Utilitas13, S. 213–35.2003 [428] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (2003): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Pluralistic View, Oxford.2004 [429] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (2004): Satisficing and Perfecti<strong>on</strong>ism in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Satisficing andMaximizing: Moral Theorists <strong>on</strong> Practical Reas<strong>on</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Michael Byr<strong>on</strong>, Cambridge,S. 176–89.83“C<strong>on</strong>ceived of as a c<strong>on</strong>tender to other theories in substantive ethics, virtue ethics is often associated with, inessence, the following account or criteri<strong>on</strong> of right acti<strong>on</strong>: VR: An acti<strong>on</strong> A is right for S in circumstancesC if and <strong>on</strong>ly if a fully virtuous agent would characteristically do A in C. There are serious objecti<strong>on</strong>s to VR,which take the form of counter-examples. They present us with different scenarios in which less than fullyvirtuous pers<strong>on</strong>s would be acting rightly in doing what no fully virtuous agent would characteristically do inthe circumstances. In this paper, various proposals for how to revise VR in order to avoid these counterexamplesare c<strong>on</strong>sidered. I will argue that in so far as the revised accounts really do manage to steer clear ofthe counter-examples to VR, something which it turns out is not quite true for all of them, they instead fallprey to other damaging objecti<strong>on</strong>s. I end by discussing the future of virtue ethics, given what has come tolight in the previous secti<strong>on</strong>s of the paper. In particular, I sketch the outlines of a virtue ethical account ofrightness that is structurally different from VR. This account also faces important problems. Still, I suggestthat further scrutiny is required before we are in a positi<strong>on</strong> to make a definitive decisi<strong>on</strong> about its fate.”41


2005 [430] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (2005): Nietzschean <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Old and New, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong>Stephen M. Gardiner, Ithaca, S. 179–92.2010 [431] Swant<strong>on</strong>, Christine (2010): A Challenge to Intellectual <strong>Virtue</strong> from Moral <strong>Virtue</strong>: The Case ofUniversal Love, Metaphilosophy 41, S. 152–71. 842001 [432] Tännsjö, Torbjörn (2001): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, in Exploring Practical Philosophy: From Acti<strong>on</strong> toValues, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Dan Eg<strong>on</strong>ss<strong>on</strong>, J<strong>on</strong>as Josefss<strong>on</strong>, Björn Peterss<strong>on</strong> und T<strong>on</strong>i Rönnow-Rasmussen, Aldershot, S. 167–85.2002 [433] Tännsjö, Torbjörn (2002): Understanding Ethics. An Introducti<strong>on</strong> to Moral Theory, Edinburgh,S. 91–105 (“<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics”).1988 [434] Taylor, Gabriele (1988): Envy and Jealousy: Emoti<strong>on</strong>s and Vices, in Midwest Studies inPhilosophy Vol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A.French, Theodore E. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 233–49.1996 [435] Taylor, Gabriele (1996): Deadly Vices?, in How Should One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg.v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 157–72.1968 [436] Taylor, Gabriele/Wolfram, Sybil (1968): The Self-Regarding and Other-Regarding <strong>Virtue</strong>s,Philosophical Quarterly 18, S. 238–50.1971 [437] Taylor, Gabriele/Wolfram, Sybil (1971): <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Passi<strong>on</strong>s, Analysis, S. 76–83.1988 [438] Taylor, Richard (1988): Ancient Wisdom and Modern Folly, in Midwest Studies in PhilosophyVol. XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French, TheodoreE. Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 54–63.1994 [439] Terzis, George N. (1994): Human Flourishings: A Psychological Critique of <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics,American Philosophical Quarterly 31, S. 333–342.2005 [440] Tessman, Lisa (2005): Burdened <strong>Virtue</strong>s. <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics for Liberatory Struggles, Oxford. 85 –Vgl. dazu (aus dem “Symposium <strong>on</strong> Lisa Tessman’s Burdened <strong>Virtue</strong>s” in Hypatia 23(2008), S. 182–216): [72], [146], [234].8485“On the Aristotelian picture of virtue, moral virtue has at its core intellectual virtue. An interestingchallenge for this orthodoxy is provided by the case of universal love and its associated virtues, such as thedispositi<strong>on</strong>s to exhibit grace, or to forgive, where appropriate. It is difficult to find a property in the objectof such love, in virtue of which grace, for example, ought to be bestowed. Perhaps, then, love in general,including universal love, is not necessarily exhibited for reas<strong>on</strong>s. This is the view that, with the help ofHeidegger's noti<strong>on</strong> of a fundamental emoti<strong>on</strong>al attunement (Grundstimmung), I defend. The problem is toshow how universal love, and its manifestati<strong>on</strong> in the virtues of universal love, can then be seen as rati<strong>on</strong>al.Showing this is the task of the essay.”C<strong>on</strong>tents: Introducti<strong>on</strong>: Moral Trouble (3) – 1. Regretting the Self One Is (11) – 2. The Damage of MoralDamage (33) – 3. The Ordinary Vices of Dominati<strong>on</strong> (53) – 4. Between Indifference and Anguish (81) – 5.The Burden of Political Resistance (107) – 6. Dangerous Loyalties (133) – C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>: Eudaim<strong>on</strong>istic<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics under Adversity (159) – Works Cited (169) – Index (179).Descripti<strong>on</strong>: “Lisa Tessman’s Burdened <strong>Virtue</strong>s is a deeply original and provocative work that engagesquesti<strong>on</strong>s central to feminist theory and practice, from the perspective of Aristotelian ethics. Focusedprimarily <strong>on</strong> selves who endure and resist oppressi<strong>on</strong>, she addresses the ways in which devastatingc<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s c<strong>on</strong>fr<strong>on</strong>ted by these selves both limit and burden their moral goodness, and affect their42


2008 [441] Tessman, Lisa (2008): Reply to Critics, Hypatia 23, S. 205–16. 86 – Zu [72], [146], [234].2006 [442] Tiberius, Valerie (2006): How to Think About <strong>Virtue</strong> and Right, Philosophical Papers 35, S.247–265. 87 – Zu [220].1994 [443] Tierney, Nathan L. (1994): Imaginati<strong>on</strong> and Ethical Ideals. Prospects for Unified Philosophicaland Psychological Understanding, Albany, S. 129–35 (“<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics Rec<strong>on</strong>sidered”).2002 [444] Timm<strong>on</strong>s, Mark (2002): Moral Theory. An Introducti<strong>on</strong>, Lanham, S. 211–43 (“<strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics”).2006 [445] T<strong>on</strong>er, Christopher (2006): The Self-Centredness Objecti<strong>on</strong> to <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Philosophy 81, S.595–618. 881986 [446] Trianosky, Gregory (1986): Supererogati<strong>on</strong>, Wr<strong>on</strong>gdoing, and Vice: On the Aut<strong>on</strong>omy of theEthics of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Journal of Philosophy 83, S. 26–40. Wiederabgedruckt in EthicalTheory, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> James Rachels, Oxford 1998, S. 454–69.1988 [447] Trianosky, Gregory (1988): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Acti<strong>on</strong> and the Good Life: A Theory of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Pacific868788possibilities of flourishing. She describes two different forms of “moral trouble” prevalent under oppressi<strong>on</strong>.The first is that the oppressed self may be morally damaged, prevented from developing or exercising someof the virtues; the sec<strong>on</strong>d is that the very c<strong>on</strong>diti<strong>on</strong>s of oppressi<strong>on</strong> require the oppressed to develop a set ofvirtues that carry a moral cost to those who practice them – traits that Tessman refers to as “burdenedvirtues.” These virtues have the unusual feature of being disjoined from their bearer’s own well being.Tessman’s work focuses <strong>on</strong> issues that have been missed by many feminist moral theories, and her use ofthe virtue ethics framework brings feminist c<strong>on</strong>cerns more closely into c<strong>on</strong>tact with mainstream ethicaltheory. This book will appeal to feminist theorists in philosophy and women’s studies, but also morebroadly, ethicists and social theorists.”“Tessman resp<strong>on</strong>ds to her three critics’ comments <strong>on</strong> Burdened <strong>Virtue</strong>s, focusing <strong>on</strong> their c<strong>on</strong>cerns with herstipulati<strong>on</strong> of an “inclusivity requirement,” according to which <strong>on</strong>e cannot be said to flourish withoutc<strong>on</strong>tributing to the flourishing of an inclusive collectivity. Tessman identifies a naturalized approach toethics – which she distinguishes from the naturalism she implicitly endorsed in Burdened <strong>Virtue</strong>s – thatilluminates how a c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of flourishing that meets the inclusivity requirement could carry moralauthority.”“Robert Johns<strong>on</strong> argues that virtue ethical accounts of right acti<strong>on</strong> fail because they cannot take account ofthe fact that there are things we ought to do precisely because we do not possess virtuous character traits.Self-improving acti<strong>on</strong>s are his paradigm case and it would indeed be a problem if virtue ethics could notmake sense of the propriety of self-improvement. To solve this serious problem, I propose that virtue ethicsought to define right acti<strong>on</strong> in terms of the virtuous agent’s reas<strong>on</strong>s for acti<strong>on</strong> instead of defining rightacti<strong>on</strong> in terms of the acti<strong>on</strong>s that the virtuous agent performs. I argue that this revised definiti<strong>on</strong> of rightacti<strong>on</strong> makes sense of the Tightness of self-improving acti<strong>on</strong>s and that it can be given a genuinely virtueethical interpretati<strong>on</strong>.”“Aristotelian virtue ethics is often charged with counseling a self-centred approach to the moral life.Reviewing some influential resp<strong>on</strong>ses made by defenders of virtue ethics, I argue that n<strong>on</strong>e of them goes farenough. I begin my own resp<strong>on</strong>se by evaluating two comm<strong>on</strong> targets of the objecti<strong>on</strong>, Aristotle andAquinas, and based <strong>on</strong> my findings sketch the outlines of a clearly n<strong>on</strong>-self-centred versi<strong>on</strong> of virtue ethics,according to which the ‘center’ is instead located in the agent’s right relati<strong>on</strong> to others and ultimately to theGood. I c<strong>on</strong>clude that while some species of virtue ethics may be self-centred, the objecti<strong>on</strong> cannot be usedto indict the whole genus.”43


Journal of Philosophy.1990 [448] Trianosky, Gregory (1990): What is <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics All About?, American PhilosophicalQuarterly 27, S. 335–44. Wiederabgedruckt in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader, hrsg.v<strong>on</strong> Daniel Statman, Edinburgh 1997, S. 42–55.1990 [449] Trianosky, Gregory (1990): Natural Affecti<strong>on</strong> and Resp<strong>on</strong>sibility for Character: A Critique ofKantian Views of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, in Identity, Character, and Morality. Essays in MoralPsychology, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Owen Flanagan und Amélie Oksenberg Rorty, Cambridge,Mass., S. 93–109.1993 [450] Tugendhat, Ernst (1993): Vorlesungen über Ethik, Frankfurt a. M., S. 227–38 („Tugenden“).2008 [451] Upt<strong>on</strong>, Candace L. (2008): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Character, and Normative Receptivity, Journal ofMoral Philosophy 5, S. 77–95. 892009 [452] Upt<strong>on</strong>, Candace L. (2009): The Structure of Character, Journal of Ethics 13, S. 175–93. 902009 [453] Upt<strong>on</strong>, Candace L. (2009): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Moral Psychology: The Situati<strong>on</strong>ism Debate,Journal of Ethics 13, S. 103–15.2006 [454] van Hooft, Stan (2006): Understanding <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Chesham.2002 [455] van Zyl, Liezl (2002): <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory and Applied Ethics, South African Journal of Philosophy21, S. 133–44.2009 [456] van Zyl, Liezl (2009): Accidental Rightness, Philosophia 37, S. 91–104. 91899091“Classically-c<strong>on</strong>ceived accounts of character posit traits that are both dynamic and global. Dynamic traitsproduce behavior, and global traits produce behavior across the full range of situati<strong>on</strong> kinds relevant to aparticular trait. If you are classically just, for example, you would behave justly across the full range ofsituati<strong>on</strong> kinds relevant to justice. But classical traits are too crude to fulfill trait attributi<strong>on</strong>s’ intrinsicallynormative purpose, which is to reflect the moral merit agents deserve. I defend an extra-classical account ofcharacter traits that endorses flexible traits that might issue in behavior across any narrow or broad range ofsituati<strong>on</strong> kinds, and static traits that might issue in no behavior at all. Extra-classical traits are more subtleand sensitive, and so are normatively receptive to the credit that psychologically-complicated agents merit.Further, extra-classical traits can fulfill all the unproblematic roles of classical traits. Extra-classicism is,hence, a significant and substantial improvement up<strong>on</strong> classically c<strong>on</strong>ceived character traits and traditi<strong>on</strong>alvirtue ethics.”“In this paper, I defend a local account of character traits that posits traits like close-friend-h<strong>on</strong>esty andgood-mood-compassi<strong>on</strong>. John Doris also defends local character traits, but his local character traits areindistinguishable from mere behavioral dispositi<strong>on</strong>s, they are not necessary for the purpose which allegedlyjustifies them, and their justificati<strong>on</strong> is <strong>on</strong>ly c<strong>on</strong>tingent, depending up<strong>on</strong> the prevailing empirical situati<strong>on</strong>.The account of local traits I defend posits local traits that are traits of character rather than behavioraldispositi<strong>on</strong>s, local traits that are necessary to satisfy <strong>on</strong>e of their central purposes, and local traits whosejustificati<strong>on</strong> is dependent up<strong>on</strong> theoretical rather than empirical c<strong>on</strong>siderati<strong>on</strong>s.”“In this paper I argue that the disagreement between modern moral philosophers and (some) virtue ethicistsabout whether motive affects rightness is a result of c<strong>on</strong>ceptual disagreement, and that when they develop atheory of ‘right acti<strong>on</strong>,’ the two parties resp<strong>on</strong>d to two very different questi<strong>on</strong>s. Whereas virtue ethiciststend to use ‘right’ as interchangeable with ‘good’ or ‘virtuous’ and as implying moral praise, modern moralphilosophers use it as roughly equivalent to ‘in accordance with moral obligati<strong>on</strong>.’ One implicati<strong>on</strong> of this44


2009 [457] van Zyl, Liezl (2009): Agent-based <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and the Problem of Acti<strong>on</strong> Guidance, Journalof Moral Philosophy 6, S. 50–69. 922011 [458] van Zyl, Liezl (2011): Right Acti<strong>on</strong> and the N<strong>on</strong>-Virtuous Agent, Journal of Applied Philosophy28, S. 80–92. 931985 [459] Veatch, Robert M. (1985): Against <strong>Virtue</strong>: A De<strong>on</strong>tological Critique of <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory inMedical Ethics, in <strong>Virtue</strong> and Medicine: Explorati<strong>on</strong>s in the Character of Medicine,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Earl Shelp, Dordrecht, S. 329–45.2010 [460] Verbeek, Bruno (2010): Rati<strong>on</strong>al Choice <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 13, S.541–59. 942004 [461] Vranas, Peter B. M. (2004): Review of Lack of Character by John Doris, Philosophical Review113, S. 284–88. – Zu [118].2009 [462] Vranas, Peter B. M. (2009): Against Moral Character Evaluati<strong>on</strong>s: The Undetectability of <strong>Virtue</strong>and Vice, Journal of Ethics 13, S. 213–33. 9592939495is that the possibility of an act being right by accident does not pose a problem for c<strong>on</strong>sequentialism orde<strong>on</strong>tology. A further implicati<strong>on</strong> is that it reveals a shortcoming in virtue ethics, namely that it does not –yet needs to – present an account of moral obligati<strong>on</strong>.”“Agent-based accounts of virtue ethics, such as the <strong>on</strong>e provided by Michael Slote, base the rightness ofacti<strong>on</strong> in the motive from which it proceeds. A frequent objecti<strong>on</strong> to agent-basing is that it does not allow usto draw the comm<strong>on</strong>sense distincti<strong>on</strong> between doing the right thing and doing it for the right reas<strong>on</strong>s, thatis, between act-evaluati<strong>on</strong> and agent-appraisal. I defend agent-basing against this objecti<strong>on</strong>, but argue that amore fundamental problem for this account is its apparent failure to provide adequate argue acti<strong>on</strong>guidance. I then show that this problem can be solved by supplementing an agent-based criteri<strong>on</strong> of rightacti<strong>on</strong> with a hypothetical-agent criteri<strong>on</strong> of acti<strong>on</strong> guidance.”“According to qualified-agent virtue ethics, an acti<strong>on</strong> is right if and <strong>on</strong>ly if it is what a virtuous agent wouldcharacteristically do in the circumstances. I discuss two closely related objecti<strong>on</strong>s to this view, both of whichc<strong>on</strong>cern the acti<strong>on</strong>s of the n<strong>on</strong>-virtuous. The first is that this criteri<strong>on</strong> sometimes gives the wr<strong>on</strong>g result, forin some cases a n<strong>on</strong>-virtuous agent should not do what a virtuous pers<strong>on</strong> would characteristically do. Asec<strong>on</strong>d objecti<strong>on</strong> is it altogether fails to apply whenever the agent, through previous wr<strong>on</strong>gdoing, findsherself in circumstances that a virtuous pers<strong>on</strong> cannot be in. I focus <strong>on</strong> Rosalind Hursthouse’s account ofright acti<strong>on</strong>, and argue that it can provide a satisfactory resp<strong>on</strong>se to both these objecti<strong>on</strong>s. I do so bydrawing attenti<strong>on</strong> to the distincti<strong>on</strong> between acti<strong>on</strong> guidance and acti<strong>on</strong> assessment, and arguing that whilethe above criteri<strong>on</strong> is adequate as a means of acti<strong>on</strong> assessment, we should turn to the virtue- and vice-rules(v-rules) for acti<strong>on</strong> guidance.”“In this essay, I review some results that suggest that rati<strong>on</strong>al choice theory has interesting things to sayabout the virtues. In particular, I argue that rati<strong>on</strong>al choice theory can show, first, the role of certain virtuesin a game-theoretic analysis of norms. Sec<strong>on</strong>dly, that it is useful in the characterizati<strong>on</strong> of these virtues.Finally, I discuss how rati<strong>on</strong>al choice theory can be brought to bear up<strong>on</strong> the justificati<strong>on</strong> of these virtues byshowing how they c<strong>on</strong>tribute to a flourishing life. I do this by discussing <strong>on</strong>e particular example of a norm -the requirement that agents to h<strong>on</strong>or their promises of mutual assistance - and <strong>on</strong>e particular virtue,trustworthiness.”“I defend the epistemic thesis that evaluati<strong>on</strong>s of people in terms of their moral character as good, bad, orintermediate are almost always epistemically unjustified. (1) Because most people are fragmented (theywould behave deplorably in many and admirably in many other situati<strong>on</strong>s), <strong>on</strong>e’s prior probability that any45


1988 [463] Waide, John (1988): <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Principles, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 48, S.455–72.1989 [464] Walker, A. D. M. (1989): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Character, Philosophy 64, S. 349–62.1993 [465] Walker, A. D. M. (1993): The Incompatibility of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Ratio (New Series) 6, S. 44–62.2007 [466] Walker, Rebecca L./Ivanhoe, Philip J. (Hrsg.) (2007): Working <strong>Virtue</strong>. <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics andC<strong>on</strong>temporary Moral Problems, Oxford 2007. 961978 [467] Wallace, James D. (1978): <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Vices, Ithaca.1988 [468] Wallace, James D. (1988): Ethics and the Craft Analogy, in Midwest Studies in Philosophy Vol.XIII: Ethical Theory: Character and <strong>Virtue</strong>, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Peter A. French, Theodore E.Uehling, Jr. und Howard K. Wettstein, Notre Dame, S. 222–32.1991 [469] Wallace, R. Jay (1991): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Reas<strong>on</strong>, and Principle, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 21, S.469–95.2000 [470] Wallroth, Martin (2000): Moral ohne Reife? Ein Plädoyer für ein tugendethisches Moralverständnis,Freiburg, München.1971 [471] Warnock, G. J. (1971): The Object of Morality, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, S. 71–93 (“Moral <strong>Virtue</strong>s”).1984 [472] Wats<strong>on</strong>, Gary (1984): <strong>Virtue</strong>s in Excess, Philosophical Studies 46, S. 57–74.1990 [473] Wats<strong>on</strong>, Gary (1990): On the Primacy of Character, in Identity, Character, and Morality.Essays in Moral Psychology, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Owen Flanagan und Amélie Oksenberg Rorty,Cambridge, Mass., S. 449–69. Wiederabgedruckt in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics. A Critical Reader,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Daniel Statman, Edinburgh 1997, S. 56–81.2006 [474] Weaver, Gary R. (2006): <strong>Virtue</strong> in Organizati<strong>on</strong>s: Moral Identity as a Foundati<strong>on</strong> for MoralAgency, Organizati<strong>on</strong> Studies 27, S. 341–368. 979697given pers<strong>on</strong> is fragmented should be high. (2) Because <strong>on</strong>e’s informati<strong>on</strong> about specific people does notreliably distinguish those who are fragmented from those who are not, <strong>on</strong>e’s posterior probability that anygiven pers<strong>on</strong> is fragmented should be close to <strong>on</strong>e’s prior – and thus should also be high. (3) Because beingfragmented entails being indeterminate (neither good nor bad nor intermediate), <strong>on</strong>e’s posterior probabilitythat any given pers<strong>on</strong> is indeterminate should also be high – and the epistemic thesis follows. (1) and (3)rely <strong>on</strong> previous work; here I support (2) by using a mathematical result together with empirical evidencefrom pers<strong>on</strong>ality psychology.”C<strong>on</strong>tents: 1. Introducti<strong>on</strong> , Rebecca L. Walker and Philip J. Ivanhoe 2. Caring as Relati<strong>on</strong> and <strong>Virtue</strong> inTeaching, Nel Noddings 3. Professing Medicine, <strong>Virtue</strong> Based Ethics and the Retrieval of Professi<strong>on</strong>alism,Edmund D. Pellegrino 4. Doctoring and Self-Forgiveness, Jeffrey Blustein 5. <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics as Professi<strong>on</strong>alEthics: The Case of Psychiatry, Jennifer Radden 6. Trust, Suffering, and the Aesculapian <strong>Virtue</strong>s, AnnetteC. Baier 7. Envir<strong>on</strong>mental <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Rosalind Hursthouse 8. The Good Life for N<strong>on</strong>human Animals:What <strong>Virtue</strong> Requires of Humans, Rebecca L. Walker 9. Law, Morality, and <strong>Virtue</strong>, Peter Koller 10. <strong>Virtue</strong>Ethics, Role Ethics, and Business Ethics, Christine Swant<strong>on</strong> 11. Racial <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Lawrence Blum 12. <strong>Virtue</strong>and a Warrior’s Anger, Nancy Sherman 13. Famine, Affluence and <strong>Virtue</strong>, Michael Slote 14. Filial Piety asa <strong>Virtue</strong>, Philip J. Ivanhoe.“Framing issues of organizati<strong>on</strong>al ethics in terms of virtues and moral agency (rather than in terms of rulesand ethical behavior) has implicati<strong>on</strong>s for the way social science addresses matters of morality in46


2006 [475] Webber, J<strong>on</strong>athan (2006): Character, C<strong>on</strong>sistency, and Classificati<strong>on</strong>, Mind 115, S. 651–58. 98 –Zu [399]. Dazu: [400].2006 [476] Webber, J<strong>on</strong>athan (2006): <strong>Virtue</strong>, Character and Situati<strong>on</strong>, Journal of Moral Philosophy 3, S.193–213. 99 – Zu [118].2007 [477] Webber, J<strong>on</strong>athan (2007): Character, Comm<strong>on</strong>-Sense, and Expertise, Ethical Theory and MoralPractice 10, S. 89–104. 100organizati<strong>on</strong>s. In particular, attending to matters of virtue and moral agency directs attenti<strong>on</strong> to the moralidentity, or self-c<strong>on</strong>cept, of pers<strong>on</strong>s, and to the circumstances that influence self-identity. This articledevelops parallels between philosophical theories of virtue and the c<strong>on</strong>cept of moral identity as developed insocial cognitive identity theory. Explicating noti<strong>on</strong>s of virtue and moral agency in terms of social cognitiveidentity theory, in turn, helps direct attenti<strong>on</strong> to a range of factors – including both organizati<strong>on</strong>al andextraorganizati<strong>on</strong>al, macro-cultural <strong>on</strong>es – that can foster or inhibit moral agency in organizati<strong>on</strong>s.”98“John Doris has recently argued that since we do not possess character traits as traditi<strong>on</strong>ally c<strong>on</strong>ceived,virtue ethics is rooted in a false empirical presuppositi<strong>on</strong>. Gopal Sreenivasan has claimed, in a paper inMind, that Doris has not provided suitable evidence for his empirical claim. But the experiment Sreenivasanfocuses <strong>on</strong> is not <strong>on</strong>e that Doris employs, and neither is it relevantly similar in structure. The c<strong>on</strong>fusi<strong>on</strong>arises because both authors use the phrase ‘cross-situati<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>sistency’ to describe the aspect of charactertraits that they are c<strong>on</strong>cerned with, but neither defines this phrase, and it is ambiguous: Doris uses it in <strong>on</strong>esense, Sreenivasan in another. Partly for this reas<strong>on</strong>, the objecti<strong>on</strong>s Sreenivasan raises fail to block theargument Doris provides. In particular, the most reliable data Doris employs, Milgram’s famous study ofauthority, is entirely immune to Sreenivasan’s objecti<strong>on</strong>s. Sreenivasan has not shown, therefore, that Dorisprovides unsuitable evidence for his claim.”99“Philosophers have recently argued that traditi<strong>on</strong>al discussi<strong>on</strong>s of virtue and character presuppose anaccount of behaviour that experimental psychology has shown to be false. Behaviour does not issue fromglobal traits such as prudence, temperance, courage or fairness, they claim, but from local traits such assailing-in-rough-weather-with-friends-courage and office-party-temperance. The data employed providesevidence for this view <strong>on</strong>ly if we understand it in the light of a behaviourist c<strong>on</strong>strual of traits in terms ofstimulus and resp<strong>on</strong>se, rather than in the light of the more traditi<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>strual in terms of inner eventssuch as inclinati<strong>on</strong>s. More recent experiments have shown this traditi<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> to have greaterexplanatory and predictive power than its behaviourist rival. So we should retain the traditi<strong>on</strong>al c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>,and hence reject the proposed alterati<strong>on</strong> to our understanding of behaviour. This discussi<strong>on</strong> has furtherimplicati<strong>on</strong>s for future philosophical investigati<strong>on</strong>s of character and virtue.”100 “Gilbert Harman has argued that the comm<strong>on</strong>-sense characterological psychology employed in virtue ethicsis rooted not in unbiased observati<strong>on</strong> of close acquaintances, but rather in the ‘fundamental attributi<strong>on</strong>error’. If this is right, then philosophers cannot rely <strong>on</strong> their intuiti<strong>on</strong>s for insight into characterologicalpsychology, and it might even be that there is no such thing as character. This supports the idea, urged byJohn Doris and Stephen Stich, that we should rely exclusively <strong>on</strong> experimental psychology for ourexplanati<strong>on</strong>s of behaviour. The purported ‘fundamental attributi<strong>on</strong> error’ cannot play the explanatory rolerequired of it, however, and anyway there is no experimental evidence that we make such an error. It is truethat trait-attributi<strong>on</strong> often goes wr<strong>on</strong>g, but this is best explained by a set of difficulties that beset theexplanati<strong>on</strong> of other people’s behaviour, difficulties that become less acute the better we know the agent.This explanati<strong>on</strong> allows that we can gain genuine insight into character <strong>on</strong> the basis of our intuiti<strong>on</strong>s,though claims about the actual distributi<strong>on</strong> of particular traits and the correlati<strong>on</strong>s between them must bebased <strong>on</strong> more objective data.”47


2007 [478] Webber, J<strong>on</strong>athan (2007): Character, Global and Local, Utilitas 19, S. 430–34. 1012002 [479] Weber, Verena (2002): <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g> und Kommunitarismus. Individualität, Universalisierung,Moralische Dilemmata, Würzburg. 1022005 [480] Welchman, Jennifer (2005): <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Human Development: A Pragmatic Approach,in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Old and New, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Stephen M. Gardiner, Ithaca, S. 142–55.2006 [481] Welchman, Jennifer (Hrsg.) (2006): The Practice of <strong>Virtue</strong>. Classic and C<strong>on</strong>temporaryReadings in <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics, Indianapolis. 1031997 [482] White, John R. (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong> and Freedom, Internati<strong>on</strong>al Philosophical Quarterly 37, S. 413–422.1991 [483] White, Richard (1991): Historical Perspectives <strong>on</strong> the Morality of <strong>Virtue</strong>, Journal of ValueInquiry 25, S. 217–31.101 “Philosophers have recently argued that we should revise our understanding of character. An individual’sbehaviour is governed not by a set of ‘global’ traits, each elicited by a certain kind of situati<strong>on</strong>al feature,they argue, but by a much larger array of ‘local’ traits, each elicited by a certain combinati<strong>on</strong> of situati<strong>on</strong>alfeatures. But the data cited by these philosophers support their theory <strong>on</strong>ly if we c<strong>on</strong>ceive of traits purely interms of stimulus and resp<strong>on</strong>se, rather than in the more traditi<strong>on</strong>al terms of inner mental items such asinclinati<strong>on</strong>s. We should not adopt the former c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong>, moreover, since doing so would impede pursuit ofthe ethical aims for which we need a theory of character, whereas retaining the latter c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> willfacilitate this pursuit. So we should not revise our understanding of character in the way proposed.”102 „Der heutige Mensch steht im Spannungsfeld v<strong>on</strong> zunehmender Individualisierung und fortschreitenderGlobalisierung. Ein funkti<strong>on</strong>ierendes Ethikmodell muß diesen neuen Bedingungen Rechnung tragen.Ansätze bieten in sehr ähnlicher Weise eine auf Aristoteles <str<strong>on</strong>g>zur</str<strong>on</strong>g>ückgreifende <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g> undkommunitaristische Moralentwürfe. Doch beide, Kommunitarismus und <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g>, widersetzen sichoftmals gerade der Universalisierung. Die Vermittlung v<strong>on</strong> Werten innerhalb einer überschaubarenGemeinschaft steht im Vordergrund. Unterschiede zu anderen ethischen Auffassungen in anderenGemeinschaften werden ohne weiteres akzeptiert. Können <str<strong>on</strong>g>Tugendethik</str<strong>on</strong>g> und Kommunitarismus somitwirklich eine tragfähige Basis für ein modernes Moralk<strong>on</strong>zept bieten? Die Arbeit beschäftigt sich mit dieserzentralen Frage und prüft die Alltagstauglichkeit beider Ethikk<strong>on</strong>zepte anhand der in aktuellen Debattendiskutierten Phänomene, wie dem der moralischen Dilemmata. Es zeigt sich, daß die tugendethischkommunitaristischeDenkrichtung hier interessante und neue Impulse geben kann.“103 This collecti<strong>on</strong> provides readings from five classic thinkers with importantly distinct approaches to virtuetheory, al<strong>on</strong>g with five new essays from c<strong>on</strong>temporary thinkers that apply virtue theories to the resoluti<strong>on</strong> ofpractical moral problems. Jennifer Welchman’s Introducti<strong>on</strong> discusses the history of virtue theory. A shortintroducti<strong>on</strong> to each reading highlights the distinctive aspects of the view expressed. TABLE OFCONTENTS: Preface. Introducti<strong>on</strong>. PART I: CLASSIC VIRTUE THEORIES: Aristotle: Introducti<strong>on</strong>.Nicomachean Ethics. Seneca: Introducti<strong>on</strong>. On the Happy Life. Moral Letters to Lucilius. FrancisHutches<strong>on</strong>: Introducti<strong>on</strong>. An Inquiry into the Original of our Ideas of Beauty and <strong>Virtue</strong>. David Hume:Introducti<strong>on</strong>. An Enquiry C<strong>on</strong>cerning the Principles of Morals. Friedrich Nietzsche: Introducti<strong>on</strong>. On theGenealogy of Morality. Bey<strong>on</strong>d Good and Evil. PART II: CONTEMPORARY APPLICATIONS: RosalindHursthouse: Applying <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics to Our Treatment of the Other Animals. Julia Annas: Seneca: StoicPhilosophy as a Guide to Living. Mark H. Waymack: Francis Hutches<strong>on</strong>, <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics and Public Policy.Jacqueline Taylor: Humean Humanity Versus Hate. Clancy W. Martin: Nietzsche’s <strong>Virtue</strong>s and the <strong>Virtue</strong>sof Business.48


2008 [484] White, Richard (2008): Radical <strong>Virtue</strong>s: Moral Wisdom and the Ethics of C<strong>on</strong>temporary Life,Lanham. 1042006 [485] Wielenberg, Erik J. (2006): Saving Character, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 9, S. 461–91. 1051996 [486] Wiggins, David (1996): Natural and Artificial <strong>Virtue</strong>s: A Vindicati<strong>on</strong> of Hume’s Scheme, inHow Should One Live? Essays <strong>on</strong> the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Roger Crisp, Oxford, S. 131–40.1995 [487] Williams, Bernard (1995): Acting as the Virtuous Pers<strong>on</strong> Acts, in Aristotle and Moral Realism,hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> R. Heinamen, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, S. 13–23.1995 [488] Williams, Bernard (1995): Ethics, in Philosophy. A Guide through the Subject, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> A. C.Grayling, Oxford, S. 545–82: S. 571–75 (“<strong>Virtue</strong>s”).1998 [489] Williams, Bernard (1998): <strong>Virtue</strong>s and Vices, in Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, hrsg.v<strong>on</strong> Edward Craig, Vol. 9, L<strong>on</strong>d<strong>on</strong>, S. 626–31.2006 [490] Winter, Michael/Tauer, John (2006): <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory and Social Psychology, Journal of ValueInquiry 40, S. 73–82.2007 [491] Wolf, Susan (2007): Moral Psychology and the Unity of the <strong>Virtue</strong>s, Ratio 20, S. 145–67. 106104 C<strong>on</strong>tents: Introducti<strong>on</strong>. Chapter One: Courage. Chapter Two: Temperance. Chapter Three: Justice. ChapterFour: Compassi<strong>on</strong>. Chapter Five: Wisdom. C<strong>on</strong>clusi<strong>on</strong>.“What is a good life? What does it mean to be a good pers<strong>on</strong>? Richard White answers these questi<strong>on</strong>s byc<strong>on</strong>sidering aspects of moral goodness through the virtues: courage, temperance, justice, compassi<strong>on</strong> andwisdom. White explores how moral virtues affect and support social movements such as pacifism,envir<strong>on</strong>mentalism, multiculturalism, and animal rights. Drawing <strong>on</strong> the works of Plato, Aristotle, Hume,Nietzsche and others, White’s philosophical treatment of virtue ethics is extended through historical andcross-cultural analysis, and he examines the lives of Socrates, Buddha, and Gandhi who lived virtuous livesto help the reader understand and acquire moral wisdom.”105 “In his recent book Lack of Character, J<strong>on</strong> Doris argues that people typically lack character (understood in aparticular way). Such a claim, if correct, would have devastating implicati<strong>on</strong>s for moral philosophy and forvarious human moral projects (e.g. character development). I seek to defend character against Doris'schallenging attack. To accomplish this, I draw <strong>on</strong> Socrates, Aristotle, and Kant to identify some of thecentral comp<strong>on</strong>ents of virtuous character. Next, I examine in detail some of the central experiments insocial psychology up<strong>on</strong> which Doris's argument is based. I argue that, properly understood, suchexperiments reveal differences in the characters of their subjects, not that their subjects lack characteraltogether. I c<strong>on</strong>clude with some reflecti<strong>on</strong>s <strong>on</strong> the significance of such experiments and the importance ofcharacter.”106 “The ancient Greeks subscribed to the thesis of the Unity of <strong>Virtue</strong>, according to which the possessi<strong>on</strong> of<strong>on</strong>e virtue is closely related to the possessi<strong>on</strong> of all the others. Yet empirical observati<strong>on</strong> seems to c<strong>on</strong>tradictthis thesis at every turn. What could the Greeks have been thinking of? The paper offers an interpretati<strong>on</strong>and a tentative defence of a qualified versi<strong>on</strong> of the thesis. It argues that, as the Greeks recognized, virtueessentially involves knowledge – specifically, evaluative knowledge of what matters. Furthermore, suchknowledge is essentially holistic. Perfect and complete possessi<strong>on</strong> of <strong>on</strong>e virtue thus requires the knowledgethat is needed for the possessi<strong>on</strong> of every other virtue. The enterprise of trying to rec<strong>on</strong>cile the normativeview embodied in this c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of virtue with empirical observati<strong>on</strong> also serves as a case study for the49


2006 [492] Woodcock, Scott (2006): Philippa Foot’s <strong>Virtue</strong> Ethics Has an Achilles’ Heel, Dialogue 45, S.445–68. 1071963 [493] Wright, Georg Henrik v<strong>on</strong> (1963): The Varieties of Goodness, Bristol 1993, S. 136–54(“<strong>Virtue</strong>”).1996 [494] Zagzebski, Linda Trinkhaus (1996): <strong>Virtue</strong>s of the Mind. An Inquiry into the Nature of <strong>Virtue</strong>and the Ethical Foundati<strong>on</strong>s of Knowledge, Cambridge.1997 [495] Zagzebski, Linda Trinkhaus (1997): <strong>Virtue</strong> in Ethics and Epistemology, American CatholicPhilosophical Quarterly 71, Suppl., S. 1–17.2006 [496] Zagzebski, Linda Trinkhaus (2006): The Admirable Life and the Desirable Life, in Values and<strong>Virtue</strong>s: Aristotelianism in C<strong>on</strong>temporary Ethics, hrsg. v<strong>on</strong> Timothy Chappell, Oxford,S. 53–66.2010 [497] Zagzebski, Linda (2010): Exemplarist <strong>Virtue</strong> Theory, Metaphilosophy 41, S. 41–57. 108field of moral psychology in which empirical and normative claims are often deeply and c<strong>on</strong>fusinglyintertwined.”107 “My aim in this article is to argue that Philippa Foot fails to provide a c<strong>on</strong>vincing basis for moral evaluati<strong>on</strong>in her book Natural Goodness. Foot’s proposal fails because her c<strong>on</strong>cepti<strong>on</strong> of natural goodness and defectin human beings either sancti<strong>on</strong>s prescriptive claims that are clearly objecti<strong>on</strong>able or else it inadvertentlybegs the questi<strong>on</strong> of what c<strong>on</strong>stitutes a good human life by tacitly appealing to an independent ethicalstandpoint to sanitize the theory’s normative implicati<strong>on</strong>s. Foot’s appeal to natural facts about humangoodness is in this way singled out as an Achilles’ heel that undermines her attempt to establish anindependent framework for virtue ethics. This problem might seem to be <strong>on</strong>e that is uniquely applicable tothe bold naturalism of Foot’s methodology; however, I claim that the problem is indicative of a moregeneral problem for all c<strong>on</strong>temporary articulati<strong>on</strong>s of virtue ethics.”108 “In this essay I outline a radical kind of virtue theory I call exemplarism, which is foundati<strong>on</strong>al in structurebut which is grounded in exemplars of moral goodness, direct reference to which anchors all the moralc<strong>on</strong>cepts in the theory. I compare several different kinds of moral theory by the way they relate the c<strong>on</strong>ceptsof the good, a right act, and a virtue. In the theory I propose, these c<strong>on</strong>cepts, al<strong>on</strong>g with the c<strong>on</strong>cepts of aduty and of a good life, are defined by reference to exemplars, identified directly through the emoti<strong>on</strong> ofadmirati<strong>on</strong>, not through a descripti<strong>on</strong>. It is an advantage of the theory that what makes a good pers<strong>on</strong> goodis not given a priori but is determined by empirical investigati<strong>on</strong>. The same point applies to what goodpers<strong>on</strong>s do and what states of affairs they aim at. The theory gives an important place to empiricalinvestigati<strong>on</strong> and narratives about exemplars analogous to the scientific investigati<strong>on</strong> of natural kinds inthe theory of direct reference.”50

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!