01.10.2015 Views

CONSERVATIVE

eurocon_12_2015_summer-fall

eurocon_12_2015_summer-fall

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

The Necessity of the Good<br />

Rémi Brague<br />

We are all disciples of Aristotle. Whether or not<br />

we realize it, whenever we are talking about the Good<br />

we are working with ideas that are Aristotelian in origin.<br />

We speak of good food and good company, good<br />

behaviour and good outcomes. These modes of the<br />

Good share a basic assumption: The good is not the<br />

Good, but instead a quality or attribute of something<br />

else. This is well and good. The Aristotelian way of<br />

thinking has a proper role. But we’re losing our sense<br />

of wonder and enjoyment. We do not see the Good in<br />

which all these good things participate and from which<br />

they draw their lustre. It is time, therefore, to put aside<br />

Aristotle and rehabilitate Plato. For without him we are<br />

in danger of losing our reason to want to continue as a<br />

species.<br />

Aristotle criticized his master Plato and observed<br />

that, for practical purposes, the Idea of the Good is<br />

useless for ethics. More useful is the prakton agathon, the<br />

good that can be done. Plato’s Ideas are ideals, perhaps<br />

idols, but in any case they are idle. Concrete things act<br />

upon each other. To quote the ever-recurring example,<br />

“a human being begets a human being”. Meanwhile, the<br />

Platonic Ideas stay in their heavens and twiddle their<br />

thumbs. In contradistinction to Plato’s flights of fancy,<br />

Kant said that the philosophy of Aristotle is work. The<br />

great Macedonian sage was a business manager of sorts.<br />

He put the ideas in the things, expecting them to roll up<br />

their sleeves and produce something.<br />

look for a living, then for virtue, but only after one has<br />

got a living”. Plato explicitly alludes to this aphorism<br />

in the Republic when discussing the proper education<br />

of the Guardians. The same view is expressed in other<br />

proverbs, for example, primum vivere, deinde … philosophari<br />

(first live, then philosophize). Machiavelli puts the same<br />

sentiment into the mouth of a leader of the Ciompi,<br />

who revolted in Florence: “We have no business to<br />

think about conscience; for when, like us, men have to<br />

fear hunger, and imprisonment, or death, the fear of<br />

hell neither can nor ought to have any influence upon<br />

them.” One can find everywhere stronger and morecynical<br />

versions of the same. In Bertolt Brecht’s The<br />

Threepenny Opera, the line “First comes the grub, then<br />

morals” is in all mouths.<br />

In all this we find the same basic assumption: The<br />

good is something that we do. As a consequence, we<br />

can do the good or fail to do it. From time to time,<br />

we have to let it go provisionally, postponing it to the<br />

fu¬ture. As the object of activity, it belongs to the<br />

realm of practical philosophy, especially to the branch<br />

that deals with the actions of people—which is to say,<br />

morals. Little wonder that we have taken our moral<br />

bearings from Aristotle’s ethics.<br />

Being & freedom<br />

But what if the Good is a condition of life rather<br />

than one of its modes? And what if it is an absolutely<br />

The secondary character of the Good?<br />

From this active point of view, one can consider<br />

the Good as superfluous, as something merely<br />

decorative, as something that makes life more beautiful,<br />

to be sure, but that one can perhaps take or leave. In<br />

entertaining the good as a possibility that we might<br />

do without, we are following Aristotle’s distinction<br />

between life (zēn) and the good life (eu zēn). Aristotle<br />

says the political community comes into being for the<br />

sake of securing “the bare needs of life”. But it goes<br />

on existing for the sake of the good life. To put it in<br />

Marxist terms: Life, in the sense of being alive (zōē) or<br />

leading a life (bios), is the infrastructure; the Good is<br />

hardly more than a superstructure, something that sets<br />

a crown on life. The Good is there as an adjective or an<br />

adverb rather than a noun.<br />

Given the clear priority of life, the Good is<br />

certainly a good thing—nobody gainsays that—but it<br />

is not necessary. Two cheers for the Good, but it is not<br />

the most urgent task. What is most important is being<br />

alive rather than not.<br />

The secondary character of the Good is<br />

expressed in the old popular wisdom of the Greek<br />

people, upon which Aristotle and before him Plato<br />

drew. The Milesian poet Phocylides, in the early 6th<br />

century before Christ, gives us a saying: “We should<br />

BRITISH LIBRARY<br />

Image from p. 21 of Queen Summer; or, the Tourney of the<br />

Lily & the Rose, written and illustrated by Walter Crane, and<br />

published in 1891.<br />

The European Conservative 39

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!