01.10.2015 Views

CONSERVATIVE

eurocon_12_2015_summer-fall

eurocon_12_2015_summer-fall

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS
  • No tags were found...

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

necessary condition? There is a classic way to ground<br />

the necessity of the Good. It involves tying Goodness<br />

to existence. This is the approach we find in Boethius,<br />

who bequeathed it to the whole Latin Middle Ages. He<br />

presupposes that the Good and Being wax and wane<br />

together, that they run parallel to each other. There’s no<br />

difficulty in recognizing in this foundational assumption<br />

the scholastic doctrine of the convertibility of the<br />

transcendental properties, especially of Being (Ens) and<br />

the Good (Bonum): ens et bonum convertuntur.<br />

If every being, as such, is good, then the presence<br />

of the Good is necessary wherever there is something,<br />

which is to say, everywhere. The Good may even<br />

stretch farther than Being, as Dionysius Areopagita<br />

suggests. But turning to his mystical theology would<br />

lead us too far. I agree with his doctrine, up to a point.<br />

But it is recondite and far from our present-day ways of<br />

thinking. Better, therefore, to proceed indirectly and in<br />

more-familiar terms.<br />

Let us begin with something very much of<br />

concern in the modern era: human freedom. It is<br />

something that ethics presupposes and fosters. Kant’s<br />

account of the foundation of morals shows this with<br />

great clarity. Ethical life is genuinely ethical if and only<br />

if it holds in check the influence of external agents. To<br />

be governed by something external to oneself leads to<br />

what Kant calls “heteronomy”. When we are governed<br />

by others, we are not responsible for our actions. We<br />

may do moral acts at the command of others, but to<br />

be a moral agent in the full sense requires us to obey<br />

our own laws. We need to attain the condition of<br />

“autonomy”, the condition of life in which our doing is<br />

a direct consequence of our will. The truly good person<br />

is thus the person who does good deeds at his own<br />

command.<br />

Yet in this we presuppose something. The good<br />

deeds come from a subject that is already there. There<br />

must be a self who is the seat of self-command. This is<br />

not something we should take for granted. What kind<br />

of subject is the source of free action? Whence comes<br />

this moral subject?<br />

We can begin by stipulating that this subject is<br />

a rational being. It must be rational to be able to act.<br />

As Aristotle points out, simple motion is not action. A<br />

stone that rolls down a steep slope doesn’t act. Neither<br />

does the plant that grows, pushes its roots deep in the<br />

earth, and unfolds its boughs. Nor does an animal act,<br />

properly speaking, for acting means implementing a<br />

course of action that one has planned and chosen, in<br />

freedom.<br />

This should not lead us to assume that human<br />

beings are the only moral subjects that exist. Kant<br />

explicitly states that the subjects that abide by the moral<br />

law are not necessarily human beings, but rational<br />

beings in general. In the Critique of Practical Reason,<br />

he insists that the moral vocation “is declared by the<br />

reason to be a law for all rational beings in so far as<br />

they have a will, that is, a power to determine their<br />

causality by the conception of rules”. This moral calling<br />

stipulates that the law we establish for ourselves must<br />

be a universal law. “It is, therefore, not limited to men<br />

only, but applies to all finite beings that possess reason<br />

and will; nay, it even includes the Infinite Being as the<br />

supreme intelligence”.<br />

Schopenhauer poked fun at the idea and wrote<br />

with contempt that Kant probably thought of the nice<br />

little angels. He was right, even more than he knew. For<br />

Kant appeals to the angelic mode of rational existence<br />

as a way to dramatize what he sees as the all-conquering<br />

power of reason. In “Perpetual Peace,” his meditation<br />

on the triumph of righteousness and the end of history,<br />

he seeks to show that the problem of building an<br />

enduring political constitution is in principle soluble<br />

even if the citizens are devils, provided the devils are<br />

rational. If they listen to their calculating reason, these<br />

utterly bad creatures can understand that it is in their<br />

interest to live in peace with each other.<br />

In his belief that reason can govern even devils,<br />

Kant exaggerates the paradox that David Hume<br />

expressed one generation earlier: that politicians should<br />

take their bearings from the assumption that “every<br />

man must be supposed a knave”. Modern thinkers have<br />

generalized the insight. The trick is to design a political<br />

system in which everyone has a self-interested reason<br />

to play by the rules. Human society is a pack of wolves<br />

domesticated by rational self-interest.<br />

Now, one may ask whether this makes things<br />

too easy. Did Kant not make his task too light? Did<br />

he in fact choose the simpler case, while giving the<br />

impression of choosing to scrutinize the more difficult<br />

one? Because devils are so utterly bad, you can’t expect<br />

the shadow of a good intention when they set up their<br />

pandemonium. This would seem a terrible impediment<br />

to any enduring political arrangements. But this is only<br />

one side of the coin. The flip side is that, by choosing<br />

devilish beings, one avoids the question of the temporal<br />

and bodily existence of rational beings.<br />

As do angelic beings, the devils float in what<br />

Greeks called aiōn, and the Romans aevum, a time of<br />

METROPOLITAN MUSEUM OF ART<br />

Detail of “The Triumph over Evil” (c. 1550/1580) by<br />

Anonymous showing many infants, playing instruments and<br />

carrying weapons, while demons are dragged, hanged, and<br />

pierced with arrows.<br />

40<br />

Summer 2015

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!