08.12.2012 Views

Edited by Moe Meyer - Get a Free Blog

Edited by Moe Meyer - Get a Free Blog

Edited by Moe Meyer - Get a Free Blog

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

30 THE POLITICS AND POETICS OF CAMP<br />

use” (1710:195). Such self-knowledge, believed Shaftesbury, was prerequisite to<br />

three goals of philosophy: “Friendship, Society, and the Commerce of Life”<br />

(1710:286).<br />

THE CLOSETED BODY AND THE BODY SOCIAL<br />

What guaranteed the sociality of this speculative habit was “taste,” the sense of<br />

the fitting or the becoming. Taste, as a common way of seeing (an interesting<br />

displacement of bodily functions), guaranteed the identity of looks, not only within<br />

the subject, but also between agents. Taste dictated that, from the study of<br />

himself, the [male] philosopher would “ascend beyond his own immediate<br />

Species, City, or Community, to discover and recognize his higher Polity, or<br />

Community, that common and universal-one, of which he is born a Member”<br />

(1714:158). Thus Shaftesbury criticized the virtuosi’s “pretended Knowledg<br />

[sic] of the Machine of this World, and of their own Frame,” suggesting that<br />

“this super-speculative Philosophy” be replaced <strong>by</strong> “a more practical sort, which<br />

relates chiefly to our Acquaintance, Friendship, and good Correspondence with<br />

our-selves” (1710:291–292).<br />

Taking it as (self-)evident that “in the very nature of Things there must of<br />

necessity be the Foundation of a right and wrong TASTE” (1710:336),<br />

Shaftesbury privileged critics as the arbiters of taste: “Now a TASTE or<br />

Judgment, ‘tis suppos’d, can hardly come ready form’d with us into the World. …<br />

A legitimate and just TASTE can neither be begotten, made, conceiv’d, or<br />

produc’d, without the antecedent Labor and Pains of CRITICISM” (1714:164–<br />

165). Against the virtuosi, who could be aligned with a revival of aristocratic<br />

privilege based on excessive and pleasurable knowledges, Shaftesbury opposed<br />

the critic, whose leadership of taste regulated such privileges according to<br />

morality and normality (1714:163). It was only through taste, Shaftesbury<br />

asserted, repeating his insistence that manners and morals should be one and the<br />

same, that the virtuosi could become virtuous (1710:338).<br />

Shaftesbury identified the greatest good as those networks of friendship<br />

between men that Eve Kosofsky Sedgwick has called homosocialism (1–2).<br />

Shaftesbury distinguished this male-male sociality from more “effeminate”<br />

intercourses between men and women, 9 and from the suspect sexuality of the<br />

more marginal virtuoso. While Sedgwick, in her book Between Men, has<br />

described the various tropes through which homosociality is played out, she has<br />

not described the bodily metaphors through which homosocialism marks itself as<br />

separate from homosexuality. In the late seventeenth and early eighteenth<br />

centuries, the virtuoso kept his collection in a cabinet—a special room or closet<br />

for the private display of his knacks, rareties, intricate machines, or trivialities. As<br />

an externalization of his personal and antisocial taste, the virtuoso’s cabinet<br />

threatened the homosocialism of philosophy, especially in the Greek model of<br />

the public forum or dialogue favored <strong>by</strong> Shaftesbury and others. Whereas the

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!