30.01.2015 Views

Contents - Konrad Lorenz Institute

Contents - Konrad Lorenz Institute

Contents - Konrad Lorenz Institute

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Darwin and Descartes’ Demon<br />

task in providing a DARWINIAN account of the objective–subjective<br />

distinction is to specify how the capacity<br />

to make this distinction might link to adaptive<br />

voluntary behaviour.<br />

In brief, my suggestion is this: Real and imagined<br />

stimuli typically call for different behavioural responses.<br />

Veridical perceptions often require an immediate<br />

response, whereas sensory imagery does<br />

not. As a result, it is necessary for an agent to discriminate<br />

objective from subjective states (or rather,<br />

subjective states that correspond to objective circumstances<br />

from subjective states that do not). People<br />

unable to differentiate between the subjective<br />

and the objective with a reasonable degree of reliability<br />

would either fail to respond to many important<br />

elements of their environments, or inappropriately<br />

respond to imagery and explicit memories as if<br />

it were real. This would clearly put them at a selective<br />

disadvantage. Individuals capable of making<br />

the distinction reliably would typically have survived,<br />

reproduced, and aided kin more successfully<br />

than those who were not, and thus the genes underlying<br />

this capacity would have increased in frequency<br />

relative to alleles.<br />

Admittedly, veridical perceptions are usually<br />

more detailed and complex than mental imagery,<br />

and it might be argued that there is little danger that<br />

the one could be mistaken for the other. However,<br />

the differences between perception and imagery do<br />

not mean that the subjective–objective distinction<br />

is unnecessary; they just mean that the distinction<br />

may usually be easy to make. Indeed, the level of detail<br />

and complexity of our experience may be one<br />

means by which the perceptual system ‘decides’<br />

whether a given aspect of brain activity should be<br />

classed as objective or as subjective. Derealization<br />

may involve the temporary malfunctioning of the<br />

mechanism involved in making this decision: The<br />

brain may misclassify genuine perceptual material<br />

as mere mental imagery. Conversely, the auditory<br />

hallucinations commonly found in individuals suffering<br />

schizophrenia may be a product of the misclassification<br />

of one’s own inner speech as an objective<br />

aspect of the external world (HADDOCK/TARRIER/<br />

SPAULDING 1998; see FRITH/DOLAN 1996, for an account<br />

of the neurological correlates of this clinical<br />

deficit).<br />

So, the evolutionary function of the objective–<br />

subjective distinction may relate to the fact that perceptual<br />

states require different behavioural responses<br />

than mental imagery. This suggestion takes<br />

the use of mental imagery in human thought as a<br />

given. Clearly, though, this is also something that<br />

must be explained, and a DARWINIAN explanation<br />

may be appropriate. Without going into too much<br />

detail about this matter, which is beyond the scope<br />

of the present exploration, it is plausible that the<br />

ability to use explicit memories and mental imagery<br />

in thinking evolved as a result of its contribution to<br />

long-term behavioural planning. Whatever the reason,<br />

though, the link between this ability and the<br />

subjective–objective distinction has several implications.<br />

First, it allows us to look more deeply into the<br />

evolutionary origins of the capacity to distinguish<br />

between the objective and the subjective. It can be<br />

presumed that the capacity for image-based<br />

thought must have evolved hand-in-hand with the<br />

capacity to distinguish veridical perception from<br />

mere imagery. Therefore, the subjective–objective<br />

distinction may ultimately have been selected because<br />

it made possible mental imagery and explicit<br />

memory. Second, it seems unlikely that most other<br />

animals use mental imagery or explicit memories in<br />

their behavioural planning, and thus we would not<br />

expect them to make the objective–subjective distinction.<br />

It may be difficult for us to imagine, but it<br />

is possible that most other animals perceive their environment,<br />

but do not ‘label’ their perceptual states<br />

as objective. This is not to say that they experience<br />

them as subjective; instead, they may simply not<br />

make the distinction.<br />

It is important to stress that I am not arguing for<br />

the ultimate validity (or otherwise) of the objective–<br />

subjective distinction, or that every aspect of mental<br />

life can be placed neatly and unambiguously<br />

into one or the other category. My suggestion is simply<br />

that the distinction may have an evolutionary<br />

origin. This position only requires that the distinction<br />

is valid enough to be useful, and that in evolutionarily<br />

relevant cases, people will usually class a<br />

given aspect of mental experience in the same way.<br />

For example, when there really is a tiger present,<br />

most people in most cultures will class the resulting<br />

perceptual experience as veridical and objective,<br />

rather than as a memory or mental image.<br />

Mind-Independence<br />

Another reason that it is necessary to differentiate<br />

between the objective and the subjective is this: It is<br />

often adaptively useful to track the continued existence<br />

of objective aspects of the world that are beyond<br />

the range of the senses, whereas this does not<br />

apply in the case of sensory imagery. The ability to<br />

track aspects of the environment is widespread in<br />

the biological world. 1 DENNETT (1991) goes so far as<br />

Evolution and Cognition ❘ 125 ❘ 2003, Vol. 9, No. 2

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!