30.01.2015 Views

Contents - Konrad Lorenz Institute

Contents - Konrad Lorenz Institute

Contents - Konrad Lorenz Institute

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Darwin and Descartes’ Demon<br />

external world, it is not clear what this distinction<br />

would amount to.<br />

But even if some people in every culture hold this<br />

belief, it might be argued that there are surely many<br />

who do not. There are some philosophers, for instance,<br />

who doubt or deny the reality of an external<br />

world (sceptics), and others who deny that the<br />

world is mind-independent (anti-realists). This appears<br />

to be inconsistent with the innateness hypothesis.<br />

However, again there are reasons not to<br />

give this argument too much weight. HUME (1978)<br />

pointed out that, although sceptical philosophers<br />

claim not to believe in an external world, in their<br />

everyday reasoning and actions they act suspiciously<br />

like they do. A similar point was made by<br />

Bertrand RUSSELL (1927), who was fond of telling the<br />

story of the woman who claimed to be a solipsist,<br />

but wondered why more people were not also. Postmodernists<br />

are a contemporary example. Like traditional<br />

idealists or solipsists, some postmodernists<br />

flatly deny the reality of the external world, but in<br />

giving lectures and preparing journal articles on this<br />

theme, their actions contradict their stated beliefs<br />

(GOLDMAN 1999). To borrow a phrase used by HUME<br />

(1978) in another context, it appears that the belief<br />

in an external world is “one of those maxims, which<br />

tho’ they may be deny’d with the lips, ‘tis impossible<br />

for men in their hearts really to doubt of” (Book<br />

I, Part III, Section III, Paragraph 1). Furthermore, an<br />

evolutionary perspective puts an interesting new<br />

spin on the issue of radical scepticism. Consider<br />

HUME’s comments about his own sceptical inquiries:<br />

“Most fortunately it happens, that since reason is<br />

incapable of dispelling these clouds, nature herself<br />

suffices to that purpose, and cures me of this philosophical<br />

melancholy and delirium, either by relaxing<br />

this bent of mind, or by some avocation, and<br />

lively impression of my senses, which obliterate all<br />

these chimeras. I dine, I play a game of back-gammon,<br />

I converse, and am merry with my friends;<br />

and when after three or four hour’s amusement, I<br />

wou’d return to these speculations, they appear so<br />

cold, and strain’d, and ridiculous, that I cannot find<br />

in my heart to enter into them any farther.” (HUME,<br />

1978, Book I, Part IV, Section, VII, Paragraph 9)<br />

The experience HUME describes might profitably<br />

be compared to the phenomenon of ‘instinctive<br />

drift’ (BRELAND/BRELAND 1961, 1966). Early behaviourists<br />

argued that the process of reinforcement<br />

and punishment could shape essentially any behaviour<br />

(SKINNER 1938). Instinctive drift was one among<br />

a number of discoveries that challenged this position.<br />

It occurs when animals are trained to act in<br />

ways that clash with the behaviours typical of their<br />

species. In time, the trained behaviour deteriorates,<br />

and the animals revert to more natural patterns of<br />

behaviour. HUME’s famous passage raises the possibility<br />

that something similar happens to people<br />

who pry their minds away from the natural intuition<br />

that there is an external world. We might<br />

maintain such a belief momentarily, but in time we<br />

may slide back to more ‘instinctive’ ways of thinking.<br />

These arguments do not establish beyond any<br />

reasonable doubt that the belief in an external<br />

world is universal across human cultures; they are<br />

suggestive rather than conclusive. However, they do<br />

call into question some of the main objections that<br />

may be brought against this position. As such, the<br />

universality hypothesis remains a live option. Although<br />

some profess to deny the existence of an objective<br />

world, it is reasonable to think that metaphysical<br />

realism is the intuitive position for most<br />

people in most cultures, and that it is a candidate for<br />

a species-typical component of our worldview. As<br />

mentioned, though, the universality of this position<br />

is not adequate evidence for its innateness. So<br />

the next question is: What is the origin of our realist<br />

bent Does it derive from experience, or is there an<br />

innate contribution<br />

There is unfortunately little evidence bearing on<br />

the issue of the innateness or otherwise of the subjective–objective<br />

distinction. At this stage, the best<br />

reason to entertain the innateness hypothesis is<br />

simply that it makes good evolutionary sense. However,<br />

a stronger case can be made in support of the<br />

innate origin of the understanding that the world<br />

continues to exist when unperceived. My main argument<br />

for this conclusion is a poverty-of-the-stimulus<br />

argument. This draws on epistemological arguments<br />

in the philosophical literature, but turns<br />

them to a new purpose. Philosophers point out that<br />

no evidence could prove beyond a shadow of doubt<br />

that our sensory experience is not all simply a<br />

dream or hallucination, or that the world continues<br />

to exist when we close our eyes, only to spring back<br />

into existence when we open them again. Such possibilities<br />

are usually raised in the context of asking<br />

how we can justify our belief that sensory perception<br />

is veridical. But they also raise another question,<br />

one more psychological than philosophical: If<br />

there is no evidence for this belief, how do we form<br />

the belief in the first place Consider the assumption<br />

of object permanence. As BERKELEY (1982) and<br />

others have noted, it is simply not possible to perceive<br />

an unperceived object. Nonetheless, with the<br />

Evolution and Cognition ❘ 127 ❘ 2003, Vol. 9, No. 2

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!