30.01.2015 Views

Contents - Konrad Lorenz Institute

Contents - Konrad Lorenz Institute

Contents - Konrad Lorenz Institute

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Michel A. Hofman<br />

ture of the world than a monkey’s brain and an infant’s<br />

brain maps less than an adult’s brain. But<br />

unlike two-dimensional road maps, the neural<br />

maps of reality will be multi-dimensional, probably<br />

very high-dimensional maps (CHURCHLAND 1996;<br />

GLYMOUR 2001).<br />

The coherence and predictive power that representational<br />

models of reality enjoy is explained by<br />

biological evolution. The better and faster the<br />

brain’s predicitve capacities relative to the organism’s<br />

modus vivendi, the better its chances of survival<br />

and reproduction. In the broadest terms, the<br />

solution found by evolution to the problem of prediction<br />

is to modify execution programs by sensory<br />

information. The value of the sensory input is<br />

greater if it can signal organism-relevant features<br />

and causal regularities between events. To achieve<br />

this, the system needs neural cell clusters that are<br />

interposed between the sensory system and the motor<br />

system to find and embody higher order regularities.<br />

According to CHURCHLAND and CHURCHLAND<br />

(2003), the richer the interposed neural resources,<br />

the more sophisticated the statistical capacities and<br />

the greater the isomorphisms achievable between<br />

the brain’s categorial/causal maps and the world’s<br />

categorial/causal structures. Higher degrees of isomorphism<br />

lead to more reliable models of the<br />

world. As we cannot directly compare representational<br />

models and the world modelled, predictive<br />

success is the measure of fidelity and the guide to<br />

the need for model revision. The reality-appearance<br />

distinction ultimately rests on comparisons between<br />

the predicitve merits of distinct representational<br />

models; the better the model’s predicitve profile<br />

the closer it is to the truth.<br />

Neural Substrates of Intelligence<br />

If we now assume that biological intelligence in<br />

higher organisms is the product of processes of<br />

complex sensory information processing and mental<br />

faculties, responsible for the planning, execution<br />

and evaluation of intelligent behavior, variations<br />

among species in intelligence must in<br />

principle be observable in the neural substrate. Before<br />

attempting to determine the underlying neural<br />

mechanisms of intelligence, we should have in<br />

mind a specific biological entity towards which to<br />

direct our attention. Conceiving biological intelligence<br />

as the capacity of an organism to construct an<br />

adequate model of reality, implies that the spectrum<br />

of inquiry may range from the sensory receptor<br />

system to behavior in its broadest sense (that is<br />

to say, overt activity as well as internal homeostatic<br />

action). Usually, however, valid comparisons at the<br />

extremes of the spectrum i.e., at the level of sense<br />

organs and complex behavior patterns, respectively,<br />

are difficult to make in view of the very great<br />

sensorimotor differences that exist among species<br />

(see, e.g., PIRLOT 1987; MACPHAIL 1993, MACPHAIL/<br />

BOLHUIS 2001; ROTH/WULLIMANN 2001). How to<br />

compare in mammals, for example, the sensory capacity<br />

of diurnal monkeys with stereoscopic vision<br />

with that of nocturnal echolocating bats, or the<br />

learning ability of terrestrial shrews with that of<br />

marine dolphins Differences in intelligence may<br />

in fact be uncorrelated with measurable differences<br />

in overt behavior, nor are such differences implicit<br />

in many learning situations, since both activities<br />

depend on the behavioral potential of the organism<br />

as well as on its internal state (attention, motivation,<br />

etc.; a starving rat, for instance, is probably<br />

not more intelligent than a satiated one!).<br />

To avoid these formal problems, one should instead<br />

investigate the ‘general-purpose’ (neo)cortical<br />

areas, where both perception and instruction take<br />

place. It is the organism’s neural substrate where<br />

the external world is interpreted and modelled,<br />

where concepts are formed and hypotheses tested,<br />

in short, where the physical world interacts with<br />

the mind. Since the primary function of the brain is<br />

to adequately interact with the external world,<br />

brain function can be most readily characterized by<br />

the manner in which the brain senses the physical<br />

environment and how it responds to it by generating<br />

motor actions. From experimental and theoretical<br />

studies it has become evident that the brain is a<br />

distributed parallel processor where most of the<br />

sensory information is analyzed in parallel involving<br />

large neuronal networks (FREEMAN 1975; BAL-<br />

LARD 1986; ZEKI/BARTELS 1999). The principle of parallel<br />

processing implies that activities of ordered<br />

sets of nerve cells can be considered to be mathematical<br />

vectors (or tensors). An important aspect of<br />

this vector approach is that it focuses on the explanation<br />

of brain function in terms of neuronal networks,<br />

and that it is therefore compatible with the<br />

modular and hierarchical organization of the brain.<br />

Despite these major developments to explain<br />

brain function in terms of tensors, the attempts<br />

have so far been confined to sensorimotor operations<br />

(PELLIONISZ 1988), whereas no current theory<br />

successfully relates higher brain functions to details<br />

of the underlying neural structure. This is hardly<br />

surprising in view of the enormous functional complexity<br />

of the brain, especially that of higher verte-<br />

Evolution and Cognition ❘ 180 ❘ 2003, Vol. 9, No. 2

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!