04.04.2013 Views

Foreknowledge by Joel Hayes - Library of Theology

Foreknowledge by Joel Hayes - Library of Theology

Foreknowledge by Joel Hayes - Library of Theology

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

62<br />

it suits best to gratify the vilest appetites." There is no doubt that, in a common, loose way <strong>of</strong> speaking,<br />

men's acting voluntarily, their doing what they please, their doing what suits them best, and their dong what<br />

is most agreeable to them, are used synonymously. The question is, Does such a common way <strong>of</strong> speaking<br />

properly serve as a basis for "a careful and strict inquiry" into "the freedom <strong>of</strong> the will?" President Edwards<br />

regards it as evidence that it is a universal dictate <strong>of</strong> the sense and experience <strong>of</strong> mankind that volitions are<br />

always as the greatest apparent good. The synonymous use <strong>of</strong> such expressions, he thinks, is based on<br />

men's intuitions, and constitutes evidence that in some sense <strong>of</strong> the terms men's voluntary actions are<br />

determined <strong>by</strong> their pleasantness or agreeableness. He does not contend that men always do what is most<br />

agreeable to them in a selfish sense, for in that sense it is never true that "it is more agreeable to deny a<br />

vicious inclination that to gratify it;" but in a sense which includes regard for the welfare <strong>of</strong> others. We do not<br />

wish to understand the terms used <strong>by</strong> President Edwards in a different sense from that intended. We only<br />

wish to understand exactly what he means; and we readily admit that, if men always do what is most<br />

agreeable to them in any sense, and if at the same time that agreeableness precedes the act <strong>of</strong> choice, a<br />

point has been made in favor <strong>of</strong> necessity. A more perfect understanding <strong>of</strong> the exact meaning <strong>of</strong> these<br />

expressions as ordinarily used, and <strong>of</strong> their bearing upon the subject in hand, will perhaps be gained when<br />

we come to consider the true nature <strong>of</strong> free volitions.<br />

President Edwards presents the following argument in favor <strong>of</strong> the proposition that volition is always<br />

determined <strong>by</strong> the strongest motive:<br />

62<br />

Will, Part I., Section II., p. 7.<br />

63<br />

An act <strong>of</strong> choice or preference is a comparative act, wherein the mind acts with reference to two or<br />

more things that are compared, and stand in competition in the mind's view. If the mind in this<br />

comparative act, prefers that which appears inferior in the comparison, then the mind herein acts<br />

absolutely without Motive, or inducement, or any temptation whatsoever. Then, if a hungry man has<br />

the <strong>of</strong>fer <strong>of</strong> two sorts <strong>of</strong> food both which he finds an appetite to, but has a stronger appetite to one<br />

than the other; and there be no circumstances or excitements whatsoever in the case to induce him<br />

to take either the one or the other, but merely his appetite: if in the choice he makes between them,<br />

he chooses that, which he has the least appetite to, and refuses that, to which he has the strongest<br />

appetite, this is a choice made absolutely without previous Motive, excitement, reason or temptation,<br />

as much as if he were perfectly without all appetite to either: because his volition in this case is a<br />

comparative act, attending and following a comparative view <strong>of</strong> the food, which he chooses, viewing<br />

it as related to, and compared with the other sort <strong>of</strong> food, in which view his preference has<br />

absolutely no previous ground, yea, is against all previous ground and Motive. And if there be any<br />

principle in man, from whence an act <strong>of</strong> choice may arise after this manner, from the same principle,<br />

volition may arise wholly without Motive on either side. If the mind in volition can go beyond Motive<br />

then it can go without Motive: for when it is beyond the Motive, it is out <strong>of</strong> the reach <strong>of</strong> the Motive,<br />

out <strong>of</strong> the limits <strong>of</strong> its influence, and so without Motive. If volition goes beyond the strength and<br />

tendency <strong>of</strong> Motive, and especially if it goes against its tendency, this demonstrates the<br />

independence <strong>of</strong> volition on Motive. And if so, no reason can be given for what Mr. Chubb so <strong>of</strong>ten<br />

asserts, even that in the nature <strong>of</strong> things volition cannot take place without a Motive to induce it.<br />

If the Most High should endow a balance with agency or activity <strong>of</strong> nature, in such a manner,<br />

that when equal weights are put into the scales, its agency could enable it to cause that scale to<br />

descend, which has the least weight [Query: which is the least <strong>of</strong> two equal weights?], and so to<br />

raise the greater weight; this would clearly demonstrate, that the motion <strong>of</strong> the balance does not<br />

depend on weights in the scales, at least as much as if the balance should move itself, when there<br />

is no weight in either scale. An the activity <strong>of</strong> the balance which is sufficient to move itself against<br />

the greater weight, must certainly be more than sufficient to move it when there is no weight at all. 63<br />

Will, Part II., Section X., p. 57.<br />

33

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!