03.02.2014 Views

01 Meditation Panel Preface.indd - United Nations Day of Vesak 2013

01 Meditation Panel Preface.indd - United Nations Day of Vesak 2013

01 Meditation Panel Preface.indd - United Nations Day of Vesak 2013

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Buddhist Philosophy and<br />

<strong>Meditation</strong> Practice<br />

the agitation (kobha) <strong>of</strong> vitarka and vicra.” 102 This calls to mind Aj ahn Brahm’s understanding <strong>of</strong><br />

vitakka-vicra as the “wobble” <strong>of</strong> the rst jhna. As an advocate <strong>of</strong> a deeply absorbed style <strong>of</strong> jhna,<br />

Brahm does not attribute the instability <strong>of</strong> the rst jhna to discursiveness, but rather to the conative<br />

qualities <strong>of</strong> vitakka and vicra, to “involuntary control” in the form <strong>of</strong> an automatic movement<br />

towards (vitakka) and holding onto (vicra) the bliss <strong>of</strong> pti and sukha. 103 Given that Vasubandhu<br />

denes vitarka and vicra as volitional as well as discursive, he might agree that the rst dhyna is<br />

disturbed by these volitional aspects <strong>of</strong> vitarka and vicra (as well as their discursiveness), but does<br />

not directly connect attachment to prti or sukha to the activities vitarka and vicra. 104<br />

Prīti and Sukha<br />

Most <strong>of</strong> the debates between Vasubandhu and his Vaibhika interlocutors over the dhyna-s<br />

are about their ontology rather than their phenomenology. The one exception might be their debate<br />

over prti and sukha. This debate concerns whether sukha is a bodily or mental sensation and indirectly,<br />

whether the ve sensory consciousnesses are active in the dhyna-s. This same debate (although<br />

typically with respect to pti rather than sukha and auditory consciousness) is one <strong>of</strong> more decisive<br />

debates amongst modern practitioners. After all, a meditative state that is entirely cut <strong>of</strong>f from<br />

the senses, such that there is no sound or awareness <strong>of</strong> the body (or taste or smell or sight), 105 would<br />

seem to be a very distinctive state, easy to distinguish from a state in which the sensory consciousnesses<br />

were engaged. Moreover, because it is impossible to observe the body with no sensory awareness<br />

<strong>of</strong> it, this would seem to decide whether vipassan in the form <strong>of</strong> rst foundation <strong>of</strong> mindfulness<br />

is possible in jhna. Thus, modern advocates <strong>of</strong> vipassan styles <strong>of</strong> jhna typically understand<br />

the jhna-s to involve bodily awareness and tend to interpret pti and/or sukha as referring to bodily<br />

sensations. By contrast, advocates <strong>of</strong> more absorptive styles <strong>of</strong> jhna tend to take the absence <strong>of</strong><br />

bodily awareness and sound as denitional <strong>of</strong> jhna.<br />

Given that it would seem impossible to practice the rst foundation <strong>of</strong> mindfulness without<br />

any bodily awareness, it is somewhat surprising to nd that Vasubandhu’s Vaibhika interlocutor<br />

insists that the ve sensory consciousnesses are cut <strong>of</strong>f in the dhyna-s. His commitment to this<br />

position results in a rather elaborate hermeneutic strategy where he interprets sukha in the rst two<br />

dhyna-s as tranquility (prasrabdhi) and prti as mental happiness (saumanasya). 106 But because<br />

there cannot be two feelings (vedan) in the same moment <strong>of</strong> consciousness according to<br />

the Abhidharma, the he claims that sukha is part <strong>of</strong> the saskra-skandha in the rst two dhyna-s, but<br />

is vedan in the third dhyna, where it refers to the ease (sukha) <strong>of</strong> the mental body (manaskya). 107<br />

102<br />

AKBh: viii.9c; str p. 893. The Vaibhika describe adhytmasamprasda as condence (raddh) resulting from<br />

the conviction that the meditative state can be left behind.<br />

103<br />

Shankman, pp. 172-3.<br />

104<br />

He would also not attribute this only to vitarka an vicra. According the AKBh, any dhyna which takes its own<br />

existence (bhava) as an object <strong>of</strong> enjoyment (asvdna) is deled (klita) by thirst (t). Any <strong>of</strong> the four dhyna-s<br />

(and immaterial attainments) can be deled, pure (ubha, raddhaka) or untainted (ansrava). The one exception is that<br />

Bhavgra cannot be ansrava owing to the weakness <strong>of</strong> perception there.<br />

105<br />

No one seems to argue about these senses. It should also be noted that visual awareness wouldn’t be much <strong>of</strong> an issue<br />

since most modern Theravda jhna practice is with eyes closed.<br />

106<br />

AKBh viii.9b.<br />

107<br />

This is the explanation according to the Vibhstra, Samyuktbhidharmahdaya and Dharmaskandha. See Kuan,<br />

Tse-Fu, “Clarication on Feelings in Buddhist Dhyna/Jhna <strong>Meditation</strong>” Journal <strong>of</strong> Indian Philosophy (2005) 33: 297.<br />

275

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!