03.09.2014 Views

Expanding the Public Sphere through Computer ... - ResearchGate

Expanding the Public Sphere through Computer ... - ResearchGate

Expanding the Public Sphere through Computer ... - ResearchGate

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

CHAPTER 2. THE PUBLIC SPHERE 37<br />

genuine give and take of rational discourse is that <strong>the</strong> force of <strong>the</strong> better argument<br />

can contribute to <strong>the</strong> final shape of whatever type of agreement is<br />

reached (McCarthy 1992, 67).<br />

In <strong>the</strong> second type of dispute described by McCarthy, participants disagree on <strong>the</strong><br />

morality of norms; that is, at least one party argues that a specific action or state<br />

is binding on all human beings [as opposed to <strong>the</strong> first case, in which <strong>the</strong> dispute<br />

centered on what was good for a particular and specific political community].<br />

McCarty cites as examples disputes concerning abortion, euthanasia, pornography<br />

and animal rights. “For example, what one party considers to be a moral<br />

issue, ano<strong>the</strong>r party may regard as a pragmatic issue or as a question of values<br />

open to choice or as a moral issue of ano<strong>the</strong>r sort, or <strong>the</strong> opposing parties may<br />

agree on <strong>the</strong> issue but disagree as to <strong>the</strong> morally correct answer.” McCarthy questions<br />

<strong>the</strong> likelihood of agreement in <strong>the</strong> democratic public sphere on <strong>the</strong>se types<br />

of issues, claiming instead that disagreements are “likely to be a permanent feature”<br />

of discourses “not resolvable by strategic compromise, rational consensus<br />

or ethical self-clarification.” Under Habermas’s model, <strong>the</strong>re is no discursive resolution<br />

possible, and ano<strong>the</strong>r form of coercion is necessary. McCarthy “rescues”<br />

<strong>the</strong> possibility of rationally motivated agreements in <strong>the</strong> cases of moral disputes<br />

by suggesting that participants might, under conditions in which <strong>the</strong> disputatious<br />

party accepts <strong>the</strong> justness of <strong>the</strong> basic political arrangements, rationally enter into<br />

debate and ultimately agree to what <strong>the</strong>y regard as an immoral solution in <strong>the</strong><br />

hopes that <strong>the</strong>y will, in <strong>the</strong> future, “be able to use <strong>the</strong> same [discursive] resources<br />

eventually to change <strong>the</strong>m.”<br />

Ano<strong>the</strong>r aspect of reciprocity includes what Barber (1984) might have termed<br />

“reflective” political talk. Barber postulates a hierarchy of political talk functions,<br />

ranging from those associated with what he termed “thin” democracy to those<br />

more likely to be found in conversations supportive of “strong” democracies:<br />

(T)alk is not mere speech. Talk has been at <strong>the</strong> root of <strong>the</strong> Western idea of<br />

politics since Aristotle identified logos as <strong>the</strong> peculiarly human and peculiarly<br />

social faculty that divided <strong>the</strong> human species from animals o<strong>the</strong>rwise<br />

defined by similar needs and faculties. (Political talk) always involves listening<br />

as well as speaking, feeling as well as thinking, and acting as well as<br />

reflecting (Barber 1984, 178).<br />

Barber’s functions of political talk include <strong>the</strong> notions of exploring mutuality, affection<br />

and affiliation, maintaining autonomy, witness and self-expression, reformulation<br />

and reconceptualization, and community building. Exploring mutuality

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!