11.12.2012 Views

Avant-propos - Studia Moralia

Avant-propos - Studia Moralia

Avant-propos - Studia Moralia

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

<strong>Studia</strong><br />

<strong>Moralia</strong><br />

Biannual Review<br />

published by the Alphonsian Academy<br />

Revista semestral<br />

publicada por la Academia Alfonsiana<br />

VOL. 40 / 1<br />

2002<br />

EDITIONES ACADEMIAE ALFONSIANAE<br />

Via Merulana 31 - 00185 Roma, Italia


<strong>Avant</strong>-<strong>propos</strong>: 40 years<br />

of <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong><br />

Introducing the first issue of <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> in 1962, Fr. J. Visser<br />

C.Ss.R. explains, in Latin, that the purpose of this journal is not to<br />

add to the already large number of periodicals in existence, but rather<br />

to make available the fruit of current research on fundamental<br />

and practical themes of moral theology.<br />

There is no need to rehearse here how much has changed in the<br />

world, and in moral theology, since 1962. The challenging task is to<br />

try to respond to these changes while remaining faithful to the initial<br />

project.<br />

In biographical terms, 40 years is a land-mark at which the socalled<br />

existential questions emerge: What has it all meant so far?<br />

Where do we go from here? What if…? Perhaps these same questions<br />

can help us all (authors, editorial board and readers) in the course of<br />

this anniversary year in the on-going task of defining the role, shape<br />

and goal of <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong>, not least through a more adequate interpretation<br />

of its history. The second issue of this year will include<br />

more extensive considerations of this kind, in the preparation of<br />

which we welcome comment, critique and suggestions.<br />

————<br />

The fact that <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> is still here to pose itself such interesting<br />

questions is thanks to the generous collaboration of generations<br />

of contributors, editors and collaborators. Particular recognition<br />

is due at this juncture to the former editor Prof. Raphael<br />

Gallagher, of the Alphonsian Academy. Prof. Gallagher has served,<br />

along with his colleagues, diligently and creatively as Secretary of the<br />

Commission for <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> since 1996. In these years the journal<br />

has seen a number of significant developments. Through a period of<br />

experimentation, a format for the layout has been found that is<br />

agreeable to the eye and clear to the mind. The polyglottal nature of


4 AVANT-PROPOS<br />

the publication and its genuinely global distribution have made it<br />

possible to attend to an ever-broader range of pertinent themes. If<br />

one were to single out a particular contribution of Prof. Gallagher it<br />

would perhaps be his attention to the Alphonsian moral tradition,<br />

culminating in the handsome volume produced to commemorate the<br />

proclamation of Alphonsus as Patron of Confessors and Moralists.<br />

Behind these various developments lie many hours of deliberation,<br />

administration and sheer hard work. On behalf of our readership,<br />

and on behalf of the Alphonsian Academy, I would like to<br />

express our most fervent thanks to Raphael for this huge service, and<br />

wish him success in his future work.<br />

MARTIN MCKEEVER,<br />

Secretary of the Editorial Board


AVANT-PROPOS 5<br />

<strong>Avant</strong>-<strong>propos</strong>: 40 años<br />

de <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong><br />

Introduciendo el primer número de <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> en 1962, el P.<br />

J. Visser C.Ss.R. explicaba, en latín, que el objetivo de la revista no<br />

era aumentar las ya muy numerosas publicaciones existentes, sino<br />

más bien poner a disposición el fruto de las actuales investigaciones<br />

sobre temas fundamentales y prácticos de teología moral.<br />

No es necesario repetir aquí cuánto ha cambiado en el mundo, y<br />

en la teología moral, a partir de 1962. El verdadero desafío es intentar<br />

responder a estos cambios permaneciendo fieles al proyecto inicial.<br />

En términos biográficos, 40 años es un punto de referencia en el<br />

que emergen las llamadas “preguntas existenciales”: ¿Qué ha significado<br />

todo esto hasta el presente? ¿Qué dirección tomamos a partir<br />

de aquí? ¿Qué si...? Quizás estas preguntas pueden ayudarnos a<br />

todos (autores, equipo editorial y lectores) a lo largo de este año aniversario<br />

a llevar adelante el desafío de definir el papel, la modalidad<br />

y los objetivos de <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong>, en particular también mediante<br />

una interpretación más adecuada de su propia historia. El segundo<br />

número de este año incluirá consideraciones más amplias de este<br />

tipo; para preparar las mismas son bienvenidos sus comentarios, críticas<br />

y sugerencias.<br />

————<br />

El hecho que <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> se siga planteando estas interesantes<br />

preguntas lo debemos a la generosa participación de muchos sostenedores,<br />

editores y colaboradores. Queremos expresar aquí un<br />

reconocimiento del todo particular al anterior editor Prof. Raphael<br />

Gallagher de la Academia Alfonsiana. El profesor Gallagher se<br />

desempeñó con diligencia y creatividad como Secretario de la<br />

Comisión de <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> desde 1996. Durante estos años la revista<br />

fue objeto de numerosas e importantes modificaciones. Después


6 AVANT-PROPOS<br />

de un período de experimentación, se llegó a una compaginación de<br />

la revista agradable a los ojos y clara al pensamiento. El carácter<br />

políglota de la publicación y su distribución realmente universal han<br />

hecho posible tocar un expectro cada vez más amplio de temas pertinentes.<br />

Si tuvieramos que subrayar una específica contribución del<br />

Prof. Gallagher, ésta podría ser quizás su atención a la tradición<br />

moral alfonsiana, que ha culminado con el hermoso volumen editado<br />

para conmemorar la proclamación de Alfonso como Patrtono de<br />

Confesores y Moralistas.<br />

Detrás de estos variados desarrollos se ocultan muchas horas de<br />

deliberación, de administración y de duro trabajo. En nombre de<br />

nuestros lectores y en nombre de la Academia Alfonsiana quisiera<br />

expresar nuestra más cálida gratitud a Raphael por este gran servicio,<br />

y le deseamos mucho éxito en su trabajo futuro.<br />

MARTIN MCKEEVER,<br />

Secretario de Redacción


<strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> – Vol. 40 / 1<br />

June / Junio 2002<br />

CONTENTS / ÍNDICE<br />

<strong>Avant</strong>-<strong>propos</strong>: 40 years of <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> / 40 años de<br />

<strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong><br />

Summaries / Resúmenes<br />

Articles / Artículos<br />

W. KASPER, Unità della Chiesa e comunione ecclesiale<br />

nella prospettiva cattolica ...........................................<br />

B. V. JOHNSTONE, The War on Terrorism: A Just War? ....<br />

D. J. BILLY, The Healing Role of Friendship in Aelred of<br />

Rievaulx’s De spiritali amicitia ....................................<br />

M. P. FAGGIONI, Lavorare con le cellule staminali............<br />

J. BERKMAN, The Morality of Adopting Frozen Embryos<br />

in light of Donum Vitae ...............................................<br />

E. KOWALSKI, L’uomo pastore dell’essere e l’etica dell’incontro.<br />

Dall’esigenza ontologica all’imperativo etico<br />

nella filosofia dell’uomo in cammino di Gabriel<br />

Marcel...........................................................................<br />

T. SALZMAN, The Basic Goods Theory and Revisionism: A<br />

Methodological Comparison on the Use of Tradition<br />

in Ethical Theory.........................................................<br />

J. CHAPEL, Philosophy in the Ongoing Renewal of Moral<br />

Theology: Dialogical Personalism Revisited ................<br />

M. MCKEEVER, “Can anything good come out of postmodernism?”<br />

A Reading of Zygmunt Bauman’s Postmodern<br />

Ethics in the light of Fides et ratio ..................<br />

3<br />

9<br />

17<br />

39<br />

63<br />

85<br />

115<br />

143<br />

171<br />

205<br />

237


Summaries / Resúmenes<br />

WALTER KASPER<br />

UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE<br />

NELLA PROSPETTIVA CATTOLICA<br />

Remembering at the outset the “scandal” of division between the<br />

churches, the author takes up the “guiding idea” of ecclesial communion<br />

as a possible way of promoting an authentic unity. Having made<br />

a review of the fundamental principles enunciated in the documents of<br />

Vatican II, the article focuses on the recent joint declaration on<br />

Justification as an example of how diversity can be recognised without<br />

necessarily constituting an obstacle to closer union.<br />

Recordando al comienzo el “escándalo” de la división entre las<br />

Iglesias, el autor retoma la “idea-guía” de la comunión eclesial como<br />

una manera posible de promover una auténtica unidad. Después de<br />

examinar los principios fundamentales enunciados en los documentos<br />

del Vaticano IIº, el artículo estudia la reciente declaración conjunta<br />

sobre la Justificación como un ejemplo de cómo la diversidad puede ser<br />

reconocida sin necesariamente constituir un obstáculo para una unión<br />

más estrecha.<br />

BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUST WAR?<br />

Is it appropriate to invoke the just war doctrine to express Catholic<br />

teaching in response to war, and in particular to the war on terrorism?<br />

The article analyses two major criticisms: that the doctrine represents a<br />

corruption of the genuine Christian tradition, and that it has served<br />

merely to justify killing. It is demonstrated that the consideration of the<br />

virtues, in particular of charity, which had been a central feature of the<br />

classic version of the doctrine, disappeared. Thus, assessment of pro-<br />

9


10 SUMMARIES / RESÚMENES<br />

portionality, a key feature of the theory, was now judged in allegedly,<br />

purely objective terms. Such objectivity turned out to be an illusion.<br />

The difficulties which this presents are discussed in relation to the war<br />

on terrorism, and in particular to its expansion beyond its original limits.<br />

It is concluded that abandoning the doctrine would leave us worse<br />

off. But, if it is to be coherent, the consideration of virtue needs to be<br />

reintroduced.<br />

¿Es correcto invocar la doctrina de la “guerra justa ”, como la<br />

expresa la enseñanza católica, en respuesta a la guerra, y particularmente<br />

a la guerra contra el terrorismo? El artículo analiza dos importantes<br />

críticas a esta doctrina: ella representa una corrupción de la<br />

auténtica tradición cristiana y ha servido simplemente para justificar<br />

el asesinato. Se demuestra en particular que ha desaparecido la consideración<br />

de las virtudes, especialmente de la caridad que ha jugado<br />

un papel central en la versión clásica de la doctrina. Así la valoración<br />

de proporcionalidad, una característica central de la teoría, se la juzga<br />

ahora, como suele decirse, en términos puramente objetivos. Esta objetividad<br />

resultó ser una ilusión. Se discuten las dificultades que todo<br />

esto plantea en relación a la guerra contra el terrorismo, y en particular<br />

a su extensión más allá de sus límites originarios. Se llega a la conclusión<br />

que, abandonando esta doctrina, nos encontraríamos en una<br />

situación peor. Pero si se quiere ser coherente con ella, debe reintroducirse<br />

la consideración de la virtud.<br />

DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP<br />

IN AELRED OF RIEVAULX’S DE SPIRITALI AMICITIA<br />

Aelred’s use of the dialogue form and of the Christian doctrines of<br />

creation, fall, and redemption in his De spiritali amicitia give shape to<br />

his teaching on spiritual friendship and cannot be separated from it<br />

without drastically changing it. To do so would be to overlook some<br />

of his most basic presuppositions about the present state of human<br />

nature and the remedies given by God for facilitating a person’s growth<br />

in holiness.<br />

La utilización por parte de Aelred de la forma dialogal y de las doctrinas<br />

de la creación, de la caída y de la redención, en su De spiritali


SUMMARIES / RESÚMENES 11<br />

amicitia configura su enseñanza sobre la amistad espiritual y no puede<br />

ser separada de ella sin modificarla drásticamente. Separarlas implicaría<br />

desconocer algunas de sus <strong>propos</strong>iciones más fundamentales<br />

referidas al estado actual de la naturaleza humana y a los remedios que<br />

Dios ha dado para facilitar el crecimiento de la persona en la santidad.<br />

MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI<br />

Having noted some indispensable scientific considerations, the<br />

article examines the ethical questions concerning the use of stem cells,<br />

that is cells which are partially undifferentiated and hence susceptible<br />

to being used to produce different kinds of cells. Particular attention is<br />

paid to the problems which arise from the use of stem cells derived from<br />

embryros, including the problem of therapeutic cloning. It is argued<br />

that recourse to stem cells derived from the umbilical cord, or even to<br />

those which survive in the adult organism, seems more reasonable<br />

from the moral point of view, while being equally promising from the<br />

therapeutic point of view.<br />

El artículo, después de presentar algunos presupuestos científicos<br />

indispensables, examina las cuestiones éticas relacionadas con el uso<br />

de las “células madre”, células parcialmente indiferenciadas susceptibles<br />

de ser orientadas a la formación de uno u otro tipo celular. Se estudian<br />

en particular los problemas que suscita la utilización de las células<br />

madre derivadas del embrión, incluído el problema de la denominada<br />

“clonación terapéutica”, y se muestra cómo la utilización de las<br />

células madre que provienen del cordón umbilical y aun de aquellas<br />

que persisten en el organismo adulto parece más viable desde el punto<br />

de vista moral e igualmente prometedora desde el punto de vista de las<br />

aplicaciones terapéuticas.


12 SUMMARIES / RESÚMENES<br />

JOHN BERKMAN<br />

THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS<br />

IN LIGHT OF DONUM VITAE<br />

In the light of the moral principles and fundamental goods articulated<br />

by Donum vitae, one may conclude that under some circumstances<br />

it is appropriate and even morally praiseworthy for women to<br />

allow themselves to be impregnated with abandoned frozen embryos,<br />

gestating and raising them as their children. Under appropriate circumstances,<br />

such a decision is legitimately seen, not as surrogacy, but<br />

as a form of “adoption,” and as such can give witness to a profound<br />

form of Christian hospitality.<br />

A la luz de los principios de la moral y de los bienes fundamentales<br />

expresados en la Donum vitae, se puede concluir que bajo ciertas circunstancias<br />

es apropiado e incluso moralmente encomiable para las mujeres<br />

permitir la implantación en su propio útero de embriones congelados<br />

abandonados, gestándolos y criándolos como hijos suyos. Bajo determinadas<br />

circunstancias, una decisión de este tipo es percibida como lícita, no<br />

como “subrogación” (surrogacy), sino como una forma de “adopción”, y<br />

como tal puede testimoniar una forma profunda de hospitalidad cristiana.<br />

EDMUND KOWALSKI<br />

L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE<br />

E L’ETICA DELL’INCONTRO<br />

The article highlights two dimensions of being human and being a<br />

person in the philosophical and anthropological thought of G. Marcel:<br />

the ontological and the ethical. These are studied with a view to<br />

attempting to suggest some hermeneutical implications for contemporary<br />

bioethical reflection. As regards bios, the French scholar suggests<br />

the personalist-existentialist approach, with an ontological-ethical<br />

(logos) and an ethico-relational (ethos) connotation, as the most suitable<br />

ground for testing interpretative and argumentary capacities in<br />

face of new problems in bioethics. Recognising all the transcendental<br />

dimensions of being human and of being a person, in the existential<br />

experience of bios-logos-ethos (that is to say in the dynamic unity of<br />

one’s own “being more”, in relation to God, to others and to the world),<br />

guarantees the dignity of the person in the full sense of the term.


SUMMARIES / RESÚMENES 13<br />

El artículo pone en evidencia dos dimensiones del ser humanopersona<br />

en el pensamiento filosófico-antropológico de G. Marcel, la<br />

dimensión ontológica y la dimensión ética. A partir de allí el autor<br />

intenta sugerir algunas implicaciones hermenéuticas para la reflexión<br />

bioética contemporánea. Por lo que respecta al bios, el enfoque personalístico-existencial<br />

de connotación ontológico-ética (logos) y éticorelacional<br />

(ethos) del pensador francés aparece como la plataforma<br />

más adecuada para verificar las capacidades interpretativas y argumentativas<br />

frente a la gestión de los nuevos problemas bioéticos. El<br />

reconocimiento de todas las dimensiones trascendentales del ser-hombre-persona,<br />

en la experiencia existencial del bios-logos-ethos - es decir<br />

en la unidad dinámica del propio ser-más, en relación creatural con<br />

Dios y co-existencial hacia Dios, interpersonal con los otros y solidario<br />

con el mundo - garantiza plenamente la dignidad de la persona.<br />

TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM:<br />

A METHODOLOGICAL COMPARISON ON THE USE<br />

OF TRADITION AS A SOURCE OF MORAL KNOWLEDGE<br />

The Catholic moral theological debate on the existence of absolute<br />

moral norms and intrinsically evil acts reflects a more fundamental<br />

debate on ethical method. In this article, the author argues that the two<br />

predominant ethical theories in Catholic moral theology, the Basic<br />

Goods Theory and Revisionism, differ fundamentally on their use of<br />

Tradition and tradition in their respective methods. The three questions<br />

the author investigates are: first, the nature of the relationship between<br />

theologians and the magisterium; second, the criteria for determining<br />

whether or not moral teachings belonging to the “secondary object of<br />

infallibility” have been taught infallibly; and third, what types of norms<br />

belong to the “secondary object of infallibility.”<br />

El debate de la teología moral católica sobre la existencia de normas<br />

morales absolutas y de actos intrínsecamente malos refleja un<br />

debate más profundo sobre el método de la ética. En este artículo, el<br />

autor sostiene que las dos teorías éticas predominantes en el campo de<br />

la teología moral católica, “the Basic Goods Theory” [la teoría de los<br />

bienes fundamentales] y el “Revisionism”, difieren basicamente en el<br />

uso de ‘Tradición’ y ‘tradición’ en sus respectivos métodos. Estas son


14 SUMMARIES / RESÚMENES<br />

las tres problemáticas que investiga el autor: en primer lugar la naturaleza<br />

de las relaciones entre los teólogos y el Magisterio; en segundo<br />

lugar los criterios para establecer si las enseñanzas morales, que pertenecen<br />

al “objeto secundario de infalibilidad”, han sido expuestas realmente<br />

como verdades infalibles; y, en tercer lugar, qué clases de normas<br />

pertenecen al “objeto secundario de infalibilidad”.<br />

JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

PHILOSOPHY IN THE ONGOING RENEWAL OF MORAL<br />

THEOLOGY: DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED<br />

In Fides et ratio, John Paull II calls for a renewed dialogue between<br />

philosophy and theology – a recovery of an autonomous philosophy<br />

that can assist theology by confronting the major metaphysical<br />

questions rather than confining itself to limited linguistic and<br />

hermeneutical questions. The author <strong>propos</strong>es that the recovery of dialogical<br />

personalist philosophy, and the work of Ferdinand Ebner in particular,<br />

can assist in this project. Ebner identifies the foundation of human<br />

existence in the “I-Thou” relation with God, mediated through<br />

Jesus Christ, the Word made flesh, the source of language by which<br />

human reason is manifest. The movement toward authentic relation<br />

with God and others has implications for the moral life.<br />

En Fides et ratio, Juan Pablo II propone una renovación del diálogo<br />

entre la fe y la razón – la recuperación de una filosofía autónoma<br />

que sin restringirse a limitados temas lingüísticos y hermeneúticos,<br />

pueda asistir a la teología confrontando los grandes temas metafísicos.<br />

El autor propone que la recuperación del personalismo dialogal, en particular<br />

la obra de Ferdinand Ebner, puede contribuir a este proyecto.<br />

Ebner identifica el origen de la existencia humana en la relación “Yo-<br />

Tu” con Dios, mediada por Jesucristo, la Palabra hecha carne, que es el<br />

origen del lenguaje en el cual la razón humana se manifiesta. El<br />

movimiento hacia una auténtica relación con Dios y los demás tiene<br />

implicaciones para la vida moral


SUMMARIES / RESÚMENES 15<br />

MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT<br />

OF POSTMODERNISM?: A READING OF ZYGMUNT BAUMAN’S<br />

POSTMODERN ETHICS IN THE LIGHT OF FIDES ET RATIO<br />

Taking up the invitation of Fides et ratio to attend seriously to<br />

postmodernity as a cultural phenomenon, this article focuses on the<br />

work of the sociologist Zygmunt Bauman as an example of this line of<br />

thought. Bauman is one of the few who have attempted to tease out the<br />

implications of postmodernity for ethics. The article compares his findings<br />

with the official Catholic position as articulated in Fides et ratio.<br />

While the clash between the positions is clear and sharp, it also proves<br />

to be potentially informative and instructive.<br />

Respondiendo a la invitación de la Fides et ratio a tomar en serio<br />

la posmodernidad como fenómeno cultural, el artículo estudia la obra<br />

del sociólogo Zygmunt Bauman como un ejemplo de esta línea de pensamiento.<br />

Bauman es uno de los pocos autores que intentó extraer las<br />

implicaciones de la posmodernidad en el ámbito de la ética. El artículo<br />

relaciona sus conclusiones con la posición oficial católica expresada<br />

en la Fides et ratio. El contraste entre las posiciones es claro y neto,<br />

pero no deja de ser también potencialmente informativo e instructivo.


StMor 40 (2002) 17-37<br />

W. KASPER<br />

UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE<br />

ECCLESIALE NELLA PROSPETTIVA CATTOLICA<br />

Prolusione dell’anno accademico 2000-2001<br />

dell’Accademia Alfonsiana<br />

I. La problematica<br />

Tutte le Chiese confessano, nei Simboli di fede della Chiesa<br />

antica, la Chiesa una. “Credo unam sanctam... ecclesiam”. Secondo<br />

la testimonianza della Sacra Scrittura l’unica Chiesa corrisponde<br />

all’unico Dio e Padre di tutti, all’unico Signore Gesù<br />

Cristo e all’unico Spirito Santo 1 . “Un solo corpo, un solo spirito...<br />

Un solo Signore, una sola fede, un solo battesimo, un solo<br />

Dio Padre di tutti” (Ef 4,4-6). Nessuna Chiesa e nessuna teologia<br />

può perciò rassegnarsi a una situazione, in cui le Chiese si escludono<br />

a vicenda e si condannano l’un l’altra nel nome del vangelo.<br />

Tale situazione è e rimane uno scandalo. Il fatto che, nel nostro<br />

tempo, tutte le Chiese si siano messe in cammino verso l’unità<br />

va perciò considerato – come dice il Concilio Vaticano II –<br />

un frutto dell’azione dello Spirito Santo 2 .<br />

La Dichiarazione congiunta sulla dottrina della giustificazione<br />

è – così ha sentenziato il papa – una pietra miliare su questa<br />

strada. L’immagine della pietra miliare ci dice che è stata percorsa<br />

una tappa decisiva, ma che non si è ancora raggiunta la<br />

meta. Con tanta maggior urgenza si pone perciò adesso la domanda:<br />

qual’è la meta che dobbiamo raggiungere? Quale la visione<br />

ecumenica che inseguiamo? A quale modello di una futura<br />

unità della Chiesa tendiamo? 3 .<br />

1 E. STAUFFER, “eis”, in ThWNT II (1935) 436-439.<br />

2 UR 1.<br />

3 Così E. JUENGEL, “Amica Exegesis einer roemischen Note”, in ZThK<br />

Beiheft 10, 1998, 275.<br />

17


18 w. KASPER<br />

Tale questione è stata ampiamente discussa in seno al movimento<br />

ecumenico negli anni ‘70 e ‘80 4 . Harding Mayer ha descritto<br />

con precisione questo dibattito, a cui anche lui aveva preso<br />

autorevolmente parte, nel suo scritto Oekumenische Zielvorstellungen<br />

(Idee ecumeniche circa il fine da raggiungere) 5 e ha in<br />

esso individuato due diverse concezioni di fondo: unione delle<br />

Chiese, da un lato, e comunione delle Chiese nel senso della comunione<br />

del pulpito e della cena del Signore di Chiese rimanenti<br />

indipendenti, così come tale comunione è realizzata in particolare<br />

nella Concordia di Leuenberg, dall’altro lato.<br />

Da parte cattolica i documenti del Concilio Vaticano II, il Direttorio<br />

ecumenico (1993) e l’enciclica Ut unum sint (1995) non<br />

lasciano dubbi circa la decisione irreversibile della Chiesa cattolica<br />

in favore del movimento ecumenico. A questo scopo tali testi<br />

danno molte indicazioni pratiche, indicano cioè delle vie da<br />

percorrere, ma non precisano la meta nel senso di un modello<br />

concreto. Tanto più meritevole è perciò il tentativo recentemente<br />

fatto da Wolfgang Thoenissen di ricostruire, in base ai numerosi<br />

dialoghi a cui la Chiesa cattolica ufficialmente partecipa, un<br />

modello cattolico e di proporlo in questi termini: comunione per<br />

mezzo della partecipazione a Gesù Cristo 6 .<br />

Malgrado tutte le non ignorabili differenze, esiste in questa<br />

discussione un punto di partenza comune. Tutte le Chiese partecipanti<br />

al processo ecumenico concordano nel dire che l’unità<br />

non può essere solo un’unità invisibile 7 . L’unità visibile corrisponde,<br />

secondo la dottrina cattolica, alla struttura incarnatoria<br />

di fondo della fede cristiana. Secondo la concezione cattolica la<br />

Chiesa è una “realtà complessa risultante di un duplice elemen-<br />

4 Cfr. la panoramica nel documento del dialogo evangelico-luterano/cattolico<br />

romano intitolato Die Einheit vor uns, Paderborn-Frankfurt a. M.<br />

1985.<br />

5 H. MEYER, Oekumenische Zielvorstellungen (Bensheimer Hefte 78),<br />

Goettingen 1996.<br />

6 W. THOENISSEN, Gemeinschaft durch Teilhabe an Jesus Christus. Ein<br />

katholisches Modell fuer die Einheit der Kirchen, Freiburg 1996.<br />

7 Questa affermazione è ribadita nei documenti del Consiglio Ecumenico<br />

delle Chiese e della Commissione Fede e Costituzione. Cfr. H. Meyer, o. c.,<br />

20-22.


UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE ... 19<br />

to, umano e divino” 8 . E da parte loro le professioni di fede luterane<br />

non parlano della Chiesa invisibile, ma della Chiesa nascosta.<br />

Neppure per esse la Chiesa è una “civitas platonica” 9 , ma è<br />

riconoscibile nella predicazione del vangelo e nella corretta amministrazione<br />

dei sacramenti 10 .<br />

Le difficoltà ovviamente aumentano, se ci domandiamo che<br />

cosa fa costitutivamente parte della visibilità della Chiesa. Secondo<br />

la Confessione Augustana basta il consenso nella retta<br />

dottrina e nell’amministrazione conforme al vangelo dei sacramenti;<br />

invece in campo cattolico vige la dottrina dei tre vincoli<br />

dell’unità: il consenso nella professione della stessa fede, nella<br />

celebrazione degli stessi sacramenti e nell’unico ministero 11 . Tale<br />

differenza non va però sopravvalutata. Infatti secondo la concezione<br />

luterana la predicazione pubblica e l’amministrazione<br />

conforme al vangelo dei sacramenti includono sostanzialmente<br />

il ministero legato all’ordinazione 12 . A sua volta, secondo la concezione<br />

cattolica, il ministero non sta semplicemente in posizione<br />

paritetica accanto alla parola e al sacramento, ma è piuttosto<br />

destinato al loro servizio.<br />

Tuttavia la questione del ministero presenta un problema<br />

più profondo: il problema della mediazione istituzionale della<br />

salvezza, cioè il problema di sapere se e fino a che punto la Chiesa<br />

non è solo comunione, luogo e spazio della salvezza, bensì in<br />

nome di Gesù Cristo anche mediatrice della salvezza nel senso<br />

di una causa strumentale. La risposta data a questo problema investe<br />

la struttura sacramentale di fondo della Chiesa quale segno<br />

e strumento della salvezza 13 . Secondo alcuni autori qui sta un<br />

punto fondamentale, se non il punto fondamentale di dissenso 14 .<br />

8 Cfr. LG 8.<br />

9 Cfr. Aplogia, art. 7.<br />

10 Confessio Augustana, art. 7.<br />

11 LG 14; UR 2.<br />

12 G. WENZ, “‘Est autem...’. Lumen gentium 8 und die Kirchenartikel der<br />

Confessio Augustana”, in Catholica 1998, 24-43.<br />

13 LG 1 e passim. In campo evangelico cfr. E. JUENGEL, “Die Kirche als<br />

Sakrament?”, in ZThK 80 (1983) 423-457. Su questo dibattito cfr. P. LUENING<br />

(cit. nella nota 19), nota 59s.<br />

14 Cfr. W. KASPER, “Grundkonsens und Kirchengemeinschaft. Zum


20 w. KASPER<br />

Il recentissimo documento prodotto dal dialogo evangelico-luterano/cattolico<br />

romano, Chiesa e giustificazione, ha sì portato a<br />

un avvicinamento in questa questione, ma non ancora a una reale<br />

soluzione 15 .<br />

Il problema diventa chiarissimo nella tesi di E. Herms, la<br />

quale parla di una concezione fondamentalmente diversa, che<br />

ha il carattere di una netta contraddizione 16 e di una contrapposizione<br />

dottrinale 17 . Herms e altri autori non intendono con questo<br />

mettere in discussione il processo ecumenico, ma cercano<br />

una unità ecumenica che rinuncia all’unità della professione di<br />

fede, interpreta le concezioni fondamentalmente diverse come<br />

due modi dell’azione dello Spirito, le rispetta come provvidenziali<br />

18 e le ratifica con la ripresa della comunione nella celebrazione<br />

della cena del Signore 19 .<br />

Lascio aperta la questione di sapere se questa tesi salvaguardi<br />

il “consentire de doctrina evangelii”, essenziale per la tradizione<br />

riformatoria, e mi limito alla visuale cattolica. Dovrebbe<br />

essere diventato chiaro che la questione del modello di una futura<br />

unità della Chiesa non è un gioco ozioso e utopico con soldatini<br />

di piombo. La risposta presuppone un serio lavoro teologico<br />

nel tentativo di arrivare a una concezione comune di quella<br />

che, nel Credo, confessiamo come la Chiesa una, santa, cattolica<br />

e apostolica.<br />

Stand des oekumenischen Gespraechs zwischen katholischer und evangelisch-lutherischen<br />

Kirche”, in ThQ 165 (1987) 161-181.<br />

15 Kirche und Rechtfertigung. Das Verstaendnis der Kirche im Licht der<br />

Rechtfertigungslehre, Paderborn-Frankfurt a. M. 1994 (ed. it. “Chiesa e giustificazione.<br />

La comprensione della chiesa alla luce della dottrina della giustificazione”,<br />

in EO 3/1223ss).<br />

16 E. HERMS, Die oekumenische Bewegung der roemisch-katholischen Kirche<br />

im Lichte der reformatorischen Theologie. Antwort auf den Rahner-Plan,<br />

Goettingen 1984, 184, 186 e passim.<br />

17 Ivi 200. Un confronto esauriente con E. Herms non dovrebbe occuparsi<br />

solo della concezione della Chiesa, bensì anche della concezione della<br />

rivelazione e della verità, cosa che in questo contesto non possiamo fare, per<br />

cui nelle pagine che seguono ci limitiamo alla concezione della Chiesa.<br />

18 Ivi 192.<br />

19 Ivi 199s.


UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE ... 21<br />

II. Il nuovo inizio del Concilio Vaticano II<br />

Punto di partenza per comprendere la visuale cattolica sono<br />

i nuovi accenti posti dal Concilio Vaticano II. La posizione preconciliare<br />

è reperibile soprattutto nell’enciclica Satis cognitum<br />

(1896) di Leone XIII e nell’enciclica Mortalium animos (1928) di<br />

Pio XI. Quest’ultima è l’esposizione più chiara del punto di vista<br />

cattolico romano circa il movimento ecumenico prima del Concilio<br />

Vaticano II. Possiamo riassumerla brevemente così: Gesù<br />

Cristo ha fondato una sola Chiesa e l’ha voluta come unica Chiesa.<br />

Di qui l’invito rivolto ai cristiani, che vivono separati dalla<br />

Chiesa cattolica romana, a tornare all’unica vera Chiesa di Cristo.<br />

Ciò posto, una partecipazione della Chiesa cattolica o di singoli<br />

cristiani cattolici al movimento ecumenico sembrava impossibile<br />

e fu perciò espressamente interdetta.<br />

Questo punto di vista fu ribadito ancora una volta da Pio XII<br />

nell’enciclica Mystici corporis (1943), che insegnò la stretta identità<br />

del corpo di Cristo con la Chiesa cattolica romana. La sua tesi<br />

esplicita suonava così: il corpo di Cristo è la Chiesa cattolica<br />

romana. Questo non significava che tutti i cristiani non appartenenti<br />

alla Chiesa cattolica avrebbero perso la salvezza eterna.<br />

L’enciclica riconosce che i cristiani non cattolici possono essere<br />

uniti a Cristo e alla sua Chiesa mediante il “votum”, cioè mediante<br />

il desiderio. Tuttavia questa affermazione si riferiva solo<br />

allo stato salvifico di singoli cristiani, non alle Chiese, alle comunità<br />

ecclesiali o a loro elementi esistenti al di fuori della Chiesa<br />

cattolica romana. Per l’enciclica esistono cristiani separati<br />

dalla Chiesa cattolica, ma non Chiese o comunità cristiane da essa<br />

separate.<br />

L’ingresso ufficiale della Chiesa cattolica nel movimento ecumenico<br />

divenne possibile solo dopo che il Concilio Vaticano II ebbe<br />

effettuato una svolta su questo punto decisivo. Il fondamento<br />

fu posto nella Costituzione sulla Chiesa Lumen gentium. L’art. 8<br />

di questa costituzione spezza la stretta identificazione del corpo<br />

di Cristo con la Chiesa cattolica romana e sostituisce l’“est” identificante<br />

i due con un “subsistit”. Adesso leggiamo: “Questa Chiesa...<br />

sussiste (subsistit) nella Chiesa cattolica, governata dal successore<br />

di Pietro e dai vescovi in comunione con lui”.<br />

Come il teologo belga G. Philips, principale redattore della<br />

Costituzione sulla Chiesa, aveva previsto, molto inchiostro è sta-


22 w. KASPER<br />

to versato dalla fine del Concilio in poi circa il significato più<br />

preciso di questo “subsistit”. Ci porterebbe troppo lontano ripercorrere<br />

questo dibattito 20 . Preferisco lasciare da parte tutte le<br />

teorie, che si sono formate attorno a questo verbo, e limitarmi al<br />

suono letterale dei documenti conciliari. Stando a tali documenti<br />

21 “subsistit” significa: l’unica Chiesa di Gesù Cristo ha il<br />

suo luogo concreto, il suo modo di esistere nella Chiesa cattolica;<br />

in lei essa è concretamente realizzata. “Questo non esclude”,<br />

così continua il concilio, “che al di fuori del suo organismo si<br />

trovino parecchi elementi di santificazione e di verità che, appartenendo...<br />

alla Chiesa di Cristo, spingono verso l’unità cattolica”.<br />

L’art. 15 della Costituzione sulla Chiesa e l’art. 3 del Decreto<br />

sull’ecumenismo Unitatis redintegratio riprendono poi questo<br />

discorso degli elementi esistenti al di fuori dell’organismo<br />

della Chiesa cattolica romana e ne menzionano alcuni.<br />

Tale enumerazione ci dice che, al di fuori dell’organismo della<br />

Chiesa cattolica, non esistono solo singoli cristiani che sono<br />

uniti mediante un “votum” interiore a Cristo e alla sua Chiesa,<br />

bensì esistono anche elementi costitutivi della Chiesa, il più fon-<br />

20 Possiamo perciò lasciare irrisolta la questione di sapere se il “subsistit”<br />

è usato nel senso del concetto aristotelico-scolastico di “hypostasis”/”subsistentia”<br />

oppure in un senso più generale e se serve semplicemente<br />

a garantire, rispetto all’“est”, uno spazio alle Chiese e comunità ecclesiali<br />

esistenti al di fuori della compagine della Chiesa cattolica. Cfr. il<br />

commento di A. GRILLMEIER in LThK Vat. II, vol. 1, p. 174s e di G. PHILIPS, L’Eglise<br />

et son mystère au II. Concile du Vatican, Paris 1976, 119 (tr. it. La chiesa<br />

e il suo mistero, storia, testo e commento della Costituzione Lumen gentium,<br />

Jaca Book, Milano 1982). Il dibattito più recente, che spesso si spinge molto<br />

al di là dell’affermazione conciliare, in P. LUENING, “Das ekklesiologische Problem<br />

des ‘subsistit in’ (LG 8) im heutigen oekumenischen Gespraech”, in<br />

Catholica (1998) 1-23. Importanti le interpretazioni del cardinal J. WILLE-<br />

BRANDS e del cardinal J. RATZINGER, Deus locutus est nobis in Filio. Some Reflections<br />

on Subjectivity, Christology and the Church, 23-29.<br />

21 Cfr. il commento di A. GRILLMEIER, o. c., 200-205 e di J. FEINER, ivi, vol.<br />

II, 50-58. Il termine “elementi” non è certo il migliore, anche se non è facile<br />

trovarne uno più adeguato. Esso risale in ultima analisi all’espressione “vestigia<br />

ecclesiae” di Calvino; ma mentre in Calvino tale espressione indica<br />

tracce residuali povere e misere, nella cornice del movimento ecumenico essa<br />

indica realtà importanti, che spingono dinamicamente verso l’unità. Cfr.<br />

J. FEINER, o. c., 53.


UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE ... 23<br />

damentale dei quali è il battesimo. Attraverso il battesimo infatti<br />

il battezzato diventa membro della Chiesa di Gesù Cristo 22 . Al<br />

di fuori della compagine visibile della Chiesa cattolica esistono<br />

perciò Chiese e comunità ecclesiali 23 che stanno in una comunione<br />

reale, anche se non piena, con la Chiesa cattolica 24 . E lo<br />

Spirito di Dio si serve di esse come di mezzi della salvezza 25 .<br />

Il fine del movimento ecumenico nel senso del Concilio Vaticano<br />

II non è perciò “il ritorno degli altri cristiani alla Chiesa<br />

cattolica, bensì lo stabilimento della piena comunione di queste<br />

Chiese e comunità ecclesiali con la Chiesa cattolica” 26 .<br />

Il grande problema ecumenico consiste nell’armonizzare<br />

queste due affermazioni: l’affermazione che la Chiesa di Gesù<br />

Cristo sussiste nella Chiesa cattolica, e l’affermazione che esistono<br />

Chiese al di fuori della Chiesa cattolica. Il concilio non dice<br />

da parte sua nulla al riguardo. Non corrisponderebbe però al<br />

senso delle sue affermazioni sostenere che la Chiesa può sussistere<br />

anche in altre Chiese o che essa sussisterebbe solo in maniera<br />

frammentaria anche nella Chiesa cattolica. Il concilio afferma<br />

infatti in maniera inequivocabile che l’unità, che Cristo<br />

fin dall’inizio donò alla sua Chiesa, “sussiste” secondo la nostra<br />

fede, “senza possibilità di essere perduta, nella Chiesa cattolica”<br />

27 . Il concilio afferma inoltre – “opportune-importune” sotto<br />

il profilo ecumenico – che nella Chiesa cattolica esiste la pienezza<br />

dei mezzi di salvezza, mentre le altre Chiese e comunità ecclesiali<br />

soffrono di una certa carenza sotto questo aspetto.<br />

Il fatto che elementi essenziali propri della Chiesa cattolica<br />

sussistano al di fuori della sua compagine visibile non lascia naturalmente<br />

illesa e incolume la Chiesa cattolica; in queste condizioni<br />

essa non riesce a realizzare concretamente la sua piena<br />

cattolicità 28 e deve perciò impegnarsi, per amore di se stessa, nel<br />

dialogo e nello scambio con le altre Chiese e comunità ecclesia-<br />

22 LG 7; UR 22 e passim.<br />

23 UR 3; 14ss; 19ss.<br />

24 UR 3 e passim.<br />

25 UR 3.<br />

26 J. FEINER, o. c., 52.<br />

27 UR 4.<br />

28 Ivi.


24 w. KASPER<br />

li e crescere in tal modo nella concreta realizzazione della sua<br />

unità, cattolicità e apostolicità. Cattolico e ecumenico non sono<br />

perciò due aggettivi antitetici, né sono tra loro congiunti in maniera<br />

puramente esteriore. L’impegno ecumenico non è un’aggiunta<br />

esteriore e discrezionale alla nostra ecclesialità, ma scaturisce<br />

dal dinamismo più intimo della stessa cattolicità.<br />

III. Lo sviluppo postconciliare<br />

Sulla base dei principi del Decreto sull’ecumenismo la Chiesa<br />

cattolica ha avviato, dopo il concilio, dialoghi ufficiali con<br />

quasi tutte le Chiese e comunità ecclesiali. Wolfgang Thoenissen<br />

ha dimostrato in maniera convincente che tutti i risultati finora<br />

raggiunti in seno a tali dialoghi – in quelli bilaterali con ortodossi,<br />

anglicani, luterani e altri, così come in seno a dialoghi<br />

multilaterali nell’ambito del Consiglio Ecumenico delle Chiese –<br />

convergono in maniera sorprendente 29 . L’idea guida normativa<br />

presente in tutti i documenti prodotti in tali sedi suona: “comunione<br />

ecclesiale”. Egli pensa addirittura di poter constatare la<br />

tendenza a sostituire il termine “unità” con quello di “comunione”<br />

(communio) e a interpretare l’unità per mezzo della “communio”<br />

30 .<br />

Naturalmente in questi documenti il termine “communio” è<br />

adoperato solo in maniera più o meno coerente e valida e con<br />

accenti diversi non ignorabili. Abbiamo perciò a che fare più con<br />

un movimento ecumenico di ricerca che con un preciso traguardo<br />

da raggiungere. Tale movimento non è però un vagabondaggio<br />

senza meta, perché cerca in continuazione di raccordare<br />

il concetto di comunione ecclesiale con il concetto biblico e veteroecclesiale<br />

di “koinonia/communio”, lasciando così intendere<br />

di voler radicare la propria idea in una tradizione più antica, co-<br />

29 Ivi 41-60. Molte testimonianze anche in H. SCHUETTE, Ziel: Kirchengemeinschaft.<br />

Zur oekumenischen Orientierung, Paderborn 1985, 19-33; Id.,<br />

Kirche im oekumenischen Verstaendnis, Paderborn-Frankfurt a. M. 1991,<br />

45s, 171-174.<br />

30 Ivi 77 e passim.


UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE ... 25<br />

mune a tutte le Chiese, e di volerla interpretare e legittimare partendo<br />

di là.<br />

La concezione dell’unità della Chiesa come unità comunionale,<br />

come “communio”, era molto diffusa nella Chiesa antica;<br />

ma nel secondo millennio essa fu in larga misura soppiantata da<br />

una ecclesiologia spesso unilaterale dell’unità 31 , pur riaffiorando<br />

di nuovo sia in Tommaso d’Aquino 32 e sia nel primo Lutero 33 . In<br />

tempi recenti furono anzitutto e soprattutto Ludwig Hertling 34 ,<br />

da parte cattolica, e Werner Elert 35 , da parte evangelico-luterana,<br />

a mettere in risalto il significato della “koinonia/communio”<br />

e la concezione veteroecclesiale della Chiesa e dell’unità stante<br />

alla base di questi termini. Nel frattempo molti studi furono<br />

pubblicati al riguardo sia da parte ortodossa 36 che da parte cattolica<br />

37 , studi che influirono sulle affermazioni del Concilio Vaticano<br />

II 38 . Il Sinodo straordinario dei vescovi del 1985 ritenne<br />

addirittura di poter affermare che “communio” sarebbe il con-<br />

31 Cfr. al riguardo le pubblicazioni fondamentali di H. DE LUBAC E Y. CON-<br />

GAR.<br />

32 Cfr. W. KASPER, “Steuermann mitten im Sturm. Das Bischofsamt nach<br />

Thomas von Aquin”, in Theologie und Kirche II, Mainz 1999, 103-127, spec.<br />

119-122.<br />

33 M. LUTHER, “Ein Sermon von dem hoschwuerdigsten Sakrament des<br />

heiligen Leichnams Christi. Und von den Bruderschaften” (1519), in WA 2,<br />

742s.<br />

34 L. HERTLING. Communio und Primat. Kirche und Papstum in der Antike<br />

(Miscellanea Historiae Pontificiae 7), Roma 1943.<br />

35 W. ELERT, Abendmahl und Kirchengemeinschaft in der alten Kirche<br />

hauptsaechlich des Ostens, Berlin 1954.<br />

36 Fondamentali sono i lavori di N. AFANASIEV, J. MEYENDORF, A. SCHME-<br />

MANN, J. ZIZIOULAS e altri.<br />

37 Per il periodo anteriore al concilio: H. de Lubac, Y. Congar, J. Hamer,<br />

M. J. Le Guillou ecc. Dopo il concilio la bibliografia è sterminata: A. Grillmeier,<br />

H. U. von Balthasar, O. Saier, J. Ratzinger, W. Kasper, J. M. R. Tillard,<br />

M. Kehl, B. Forte ecc. Importanti sono le miscellanee in onore del vescovo P.<br />

W. SCHEELE, Communio Sanctorum (1988), e dell’arcivescovo O. SAIER, Gemeinsame<br />

Kirche sein. Theorie und Praxis der Communio (1992). Aggiunto va<br />

anche il dibattito canonico su “communio” in W. Aymans, D. Pirson, E. Corecco,<br />

I. Riedel-Spangenberger ecc.<br />

38 Menzionati vanno soprattutto LG 3, 7, 13. Cfr. anche 14; UR 3, 13, 14,<br />

19, 20.


26 w. KASPER<br />

cetto ecclesiologico guida decisivo del Concilio Vaticano II 39 .<br />

Sotto il profilo storico e filologico tale giudizio non è esatto.<br />

Al centro dei testi del concilio stanno piuttosto le espressioni<br />

“popolo di Dio”, “corpo di Cristo” e “Chiesa come sacramento<br />

universale della salvezza”. Ma una analisi testuale più approfondita<br />

evidenzia che il concetto di “communio” svolge un ruolo<br />

centrale nell’interpretazione sia del concetto di “popolo di Dio”,<br />

sia dell’immagine del “corpo di Cristo” e sia della denominazione<br />

della Chiesa come “sacramento universale della salvezza” e<br />

che, in questo senso, esso è radicato nel centro dei documenti<br />

conciliari 40 .<br />

Il dibattito postconciliare ha ripreso alcuni principi del concilio<br />

e li ha nello stesso tempo sviluppati. Dopo l’assenso di fondo<br />

espresso dal Sinodo straordinario dei vescovi del 1985, la Congregazione<br />

romana per la dottrina della fede ha ripreso in maniera<br />

fondamentalmente positiva questo dibattito in un suo documento<br />

“su alcuni aspetti della Chiesa intesa come comunione”<br />

(1992), anche se lo ha sviluppato e è intervenuta in esso in modo<br />

critico 41 . Interessante è soprattutto il fatto che anche la dichiarazione<br />

ufficiale congiunta della Federazione luterana mondiale e<br />

della Chiesa cattolica, effettuata in occasione della firma della<br />

Dichiarazione congiunta sulla dottrina della giustificazione riprende<br />

questo dibattito e parla del cammino verso “la piena comunione<br />

ecclesiale” e verso “una unità nella diversità, in cui diversità<br />

permanenti sono tra loro ‘riconciliate’ e non più tali da dividere<br />

le Chiese” 42 . In questo modo il concetto guida del dibattito<br />

ecumenico ha conosciuto una prima ricezione ufficiale.<br />

39 Sinodo straordinario dei vescovi 1985 C 1.<br />

40 Cfr. l’approfondita analisi di W. THOENISSEN, o. c., 105s; 168-174.<br />

41 Verlautbarungen des Apostolischen Stuhles, nr. 107 ed. it. in Enchiridion<br />

Vaticanum 1991-1993, EDB, Bologna).<br />

42 “Gemeinsame offizielle Festellung des Lutherischen Weltbundes und<br />

der katholischeen Kirche”, cit. in Osservatore Romanum del 22.11.1999, Supplemento<br />

A, VI (cfr. Il Regno doc, 1999, 476ss, 708ss).


UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE ... 27<br />

IV. Prospettive nella cornice della ecclesiologia della “communio”<br />

Se partiamo dal concetto biblico e veteroecclesiale di “koinonia/communio”<br />

43 dobbiamo prendere in partenza atto di un<br />

dato: “koinonia/communio” non significa originariamente “comunione”,<br />

ma “partecipazione”, in concreto partecipazione ai<br />

beni della salvezza o, meglio, partecipazione alla vita del Dio<br />

unitrino per mezzo di Gesù Cristo nello Spirito Santo, cosa che<br />

avviene attraverso la predicazione del vangelo e attraverso i sacramenti,<br />

in particolare attraverso il battesimo e l’eucaristia.<br />

La comune partecipazione a questi “beni” della salvezza fonda<br />

poi, in secondo luogo, la comunione fra i cristiani. Importante<br />

per la Chiesa antica, in specie per Agostino 44 , divenne a<br />

questo scopo il passo di 1 Cor 10,16s: “Il pane che noi spezziamo,<br />

non è forse comunione con il corpo di Cristo? Poiché c’è un<br />

solo pane, noi, pur essendo molti, siamo un corpo solo”. Attraverso<br />

la partecipazione all’unico corpo eucaristico di Cristo noi<br />

diventiamo quindi l’unico corpo ecclesiale di Cristo. Questa ecclesiologia<br />

eucaristica della “communio” è stata più volte ripresa<br />

dall’ultimo concilio 45 .<br />

Da questo principio seguono due cose:<br />

1. L’unità della Chiesa è una realtà data in antecedenza alla<br />

nostra azione. Essa si verifica primariamente non in senso “orizzontale”<br />

attraverso la socializzazione, attraverso l’unione di uomini<br />

o di Chiese. L’ecclesiologia della “communio” della Chiesa<br />

antica differisce dall’ecclesiologia liberale risalente a Schleiermacher,<br />

secondo la quale la Chiesa “nasce per mezzo di libere<br />

azioni umane e solo così può continuare a sussistere” 46 . La co-<br />

43 Sulla concezione biblica cfr. le ricerche di A. Seesemann, J. Hainz, P.<br />

C. Bori, K. Kertelge ecc.<br />

44 Cfr. F. HOFMANN, Der Kirchenbegriff des hl. Augustinus, Muenchen<br />

1933, 390-413; J. RATZINGER, Volk Gottes und Haus Gottes in Augustins Lehre<br />

von der Kirche, nuova ed. St. Ottilien 1922, 211-215.<br />

45 SC 47; LG 7; UR 2.<br />

46 F. SCHLEIERMACHER, Der christliche Glaube nach den Grundsaetzen der<br />

evangelischen Kirche im Zusammhang dargestellt, a cura di M. Redeker, Berlin<br />

1960, § 2.2 (tr. it. La dottrina della fede, Paideia, Brescia 1985).


28 w. KASPER<br />

munione ecclesiale è fondata “verticalmente” da Cristo; essa non<br />

è qualcosa che noi possiamo “fare”, ma è grazia e dono. Nella<br />

Chiesa vige il primato del ricevere rispetto al fare dell’uomo. Qui<br />

sta il limite intrinseco di ogni ecumenismo negoziale e nello<br />

stesso tempo la reale possibilità dell’ecumenismo; esso non è<br />

mai completamente calcolabile e manipolabile, bensì deve lasciare<br />

una possibilità all’azione sovrana dello Spirito di Dio. Qui<br />

sta l’importanza dell’ecumenismo spirituale, che significa conversione,<br />

ascolto della parola di Dio e preghiera per l’unità 47 .<br />

2. La Chiesa è lì dove si predica la parola di Dio e la si accoglie<br />

con fede e lì dove si celebra l’eucaristia. La Chiesa si invera<br />

quindi sempre come Chiesa locale. Ma poiché in ogni Chiesa locale<br />

è presente Gesù Cristo e poiché Gesù Cristo è soltanto uno,<br />

ogni Chiesa locale è in Gesù Cristo una cosa sola con tutte le altre<br />

Chiese locali. La Chiesa è sempre contemporaneamente<br />

Chiesa locale e Chiesa universale. Nessuna Chiesa locale può esistere<br />

da sola in maniera autosufficiente, bensì può esistere solo<br />

e sempre in comunione con tutte le altre Chiese locali. Questa<br />

“communio” non sopravviene successivamente al suo essere<br />

Chiesa locale. Come la Chiesa locale non è semplicemente una<br />

provincia della Chiesa universale, così la Chiesa universale non<br />

è semplicemente l’unione successiva delle Chiese locali. La comunione<br />

di una Chiesa locale con le altre Chiese locali, la sua<br />

“communio” con tutte le altre Chiese locali è data con la sua essenza.<br />

Dove manca questa “communio”, lì manca qualcosa al<br />

suo essere Chiesa.<br />

Per questo la Costituzione sulla Chiesa può dire che l’unica<br />

Chiesa sussiste nelle Chiese locali ed è costituita dalle Chiese locali<br />

48 . La Congregazione per la dottrina della fede ha aggiunto<br />

che la Chiesa locale sussiste nella Chiesa universale e in virtù<br />

della Chiesa universale 49 . La Chiesa locale e la Chiesa universale<br />

47 Il Decreto sull’ecumenismo Unitatis redintegratio e l’enciclica Ut<br />

unum sint annetteno giustamente grandissima importanza a questo tipo di<br />

ecumenismo.<br />

48 LG 23.<br />

49 Schreiben ueber einige Aspekte der Kirche als communio, nr. 9 (ed. it.<br />

“Alcuni aspetti della chiesa come comunione”, in Enchiridion Vaticanum<br />

(1991-1993), EDB, Bologna).


UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE ... 29<br />

si compenetrano intimamente; tra di loro esiste una reciproca<br />

pericoresi 50 . Poiché ogni Chiesa locale attua necessariamente la<br />

propria ecclesialità nella cultura del tempo e quindi in modi culturali<br />

storici specifici, lo scambio con le altre Chiese locali significa<br />

reciproco arricchimento e, eventualmente, anche critica<br />

reciproca. L’unità della Chiesa e la comunione ecclesiale sono<br />

pertanto una unità nella diversità delle Chiese locali.<br />

V. Unità-communio e comunione ecclesiale<br />

Il dibattito ecumenico, che parte dall’idea di “communio”, si<br />

muove quindi in linea di principio su un solido fondamento. Ma<br />

nel mentre esso concepisce l’unità-communio come comunione<br />

ecclesiale, conferisce al concetto veteroecclesiale della “communio”<br />

un significato che esso così non aveva né addirittura poteva<br />

avere nella Chiesa antica. Là infatti si trattava della comunione<br />

di Chiese locali, le quali avevano la stessa fede, gli stessi<br />

sacramenti e gli stessi ministeri e che stavano, su questo fondamento,<br />

in una comunione ecclesiale piena o – come nel caso delle<br />

Chiese orientali – in una comunione ecclesiale ancora imperfetta.<br />

Si trattava di Chiese sorelle, un concetto questo che oggi<br />

svolge un ruolo decisivo nella relazione con le Chiese ortodosse<br />

51 .<br />

Invece la questione della comunione ecclesiale tra Chiese<br />

confessionali, che sono tra loro diverse nella dottrina, nei sacramenti<br />

e nei ministeri, è un problema che si pone solo dopo la<br />

formazione di confessioni in seguito alla Riforma. In questo<br />

nuovo senso il concetto di “comunione ecclesiale” affiora soprattutto<br />

nei dibattiti relativi alla Chiesa Evangelica della Germania<br />

e alla Federazione luterana mondiale, e specialmente nella<br />

“Concordia di Leuenberg”. Esso fu formato inizialmente senza<br />

alcun esplicito riferimento alla ecclesiologia della “commu-<br />

50 Ivi nr. 17.<br />

51 Cfr. soprattutto PAOLO VI nel Breve “Anno ineunte” (1967), in Tomos<br />

agapes, Roma-Istanbul 1971, 386-392, che si rifà in <strong>propos</strong>ito e UR 14 e lo<br />

sviluppa; enc. Ut unum sint, 55-58.


30 w. KASPER<br />

nio” della Chiesa antica 52 . Solo di recente nell’ecumenismo extracattolico<br />

si tenta di approfondire l’idea della comunione ecclesiale<br />

con l’idea della “communio”.<br />

Viene perciò da domandarsi se e fino a che punto l’ecclesiologia<br />

della “communio” può essere utilizzata come idea che rappresenta<br />

il fine da raggiungere non solo per il dialogo cattolicoortodosso<br />

e, in altro modo, per il dialogo intraevangelico, bensì<br />

anche per il dialogo ecumenico cattolico-evangelico. Leuenberg<br />

ebbe senza dubbio “metodicamente la funzione di una accensione<br />

iniziale” per la ricerca intitolata “Lehrverurteilungen - kirchentrennend?”<br />

(Le condanne dottrinali separano le Chiese?) 53 .<br />

Così divenne però anche chiaro che la questione di sapere come<br />

il modello di Leuenberg può essere cattolicamente adattato abbisogna<br />

ancora di una discussione approfondita. Leuenberg infatti<br />

si riferisce a una comunione ecclesiale tra Chiese uscite dalla<br />

Riforma, che rappresentano un tipo di Chiese affini tra di loro.<br />

Per sapere se questo tipo di unità possa essere trasposto alla<br />

Chiesa cattolica, alla sua concezione della Chiesa e alla sua concezione<br />

dell’ecclesiologia della “communio” ci vuole ancora una<br />

accurata verifica. Questa questione è interessante e di scottante<br />

attualità anche perché la richiesta spesso avanzata di una comunione<br />

e ospitalità eucaristica scaturisce consciamente o inconsciamente<br />

dal modello di Leuenberg, che concepisce la comunione<br />

ecclesiale come comunione di pulpito e di cena del Signore<br />

di Chiese rimanenti autonome e anche differenziantisi.<br />

La risposta a questa questione dipende in modo decisivo<br />

dalla possibilità di raggiungere un consenso circa la struttura sacramentale<br />

e la forma istituzionale della Chiesa. Si tratta cioè<br />

52 Cfr. E. SCHIEFFER, Von Schauenberg nach Leuenberg. Entstehung und<br />

Bedeutung der Konkordie reformatorischer Kirchen in Europa, Paderborn<br />

1983. Sulla storia dell’espressione cfr. H. MEYER, “‘’Kirchengemeinschaft’. Als<br />

Konzept kirchlicher Einheit. Zur Entstehung und Bedeutung des Konzepts”,<br />

in Versoehnte Verschiedenheit. Aufsaetze zur oekumenischen Theologie I,<br />

Frankfurt a. M.-Paderborn 1998, 137-162.<br />

53 Così i curatori K. LEHMANN e W. PANNENBERG in Lehrverurteilungen - kirchentrennend?<br />

Freiburg i. Br.-Goettingen 1986, 14, sulla base di un suggerimento<br />

comune del vescovo regionale E. LOHSE e del cardinal J. RATZINGER, ivi<br />

178s.


UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE ... 31<br />

della questione del ministero in generale e, in particolare, del<br />

ministero episcopale nella sua successione storica e, in ultima<br />

analisi, del ministero petrino.<br />

Il documento Chiesa e giustificazione (1994), messo a punto<br />

in seno al dialogo evangelico-luterano/cattolico romano, ha affrontato<br />

questa questione e l’ha in buona parte chiarita 54 . Inoltre<br />

il Porvoo-Statement (1982) siglato tra le Chiese anglicane britanniche<br />

e irlandesi, da un lato, e le Chiese luterane nordiche e<br />

baltiche, dall’altro lato, rappresenta similmente, dal punto di vista<br />

cattolico, un passo in avanti, anche se esso, con la sua accentuazione<br />

del ministero episcopale storico, contrasta in una<br />

maniera finora irrisolta con la concezione di Leuenberg, che è<br />

sostenuta dalle Chiese luterane continentali.<br />

Dobbiamo perciò attendere e vedere se e fino a che punto in<br />

questa questione si addiverrà a dei consensi e a delle convergenze<br />

all’interno delle Chiese protestanti e tra queste e la Chiesa cattolica.<br />

Realisticamente dobbiamo dire che le difficoltà ancora da<br />

superare sono notevoli. Ma l’unificazione è senza prospettive?<br />

La risposta dipende, oltre che dalle questioni oggettive implicite,<br />

in cui in questo contesto non dobbiamo addentrarci, da quel<br />

che si intende per consenso e dal tipo di consenso che è necessario<br />

per l’unità della Chiesa.<br />

VI. Quale consenso è necessario?<br />

La domanda suona quindi: quanto consenso ci vuole per una<br />

unità-communio? E che dobbiamo intendere per consenso? Si<br />

tratta di una questione molto dibattuta sul piano ecumenico 55 .<br />

Neppure all’interno della Chiesa cattolica il consenso è mai<br />

totale. E ciò non solo oggi. Infatti anche prima è sempre esistito<br />

all’interno di questa Chiesa uno spazio per un pluralismo di teo-<br />

54 Cfr. nr. 174-242.<br />

55 Sul concetto di consenso cfr. G. SAUTER, “Consensus”, in TRE 8 (1981)<br />

182-189; “Konsens, Konsenstheorien”, in LThK 6, 3 ed. (1997) 288-292;<br />

Grundkonsens - Grunddifferenz, a cura e con una introduzione di A. Bimelé<br />

e H. Meyer, Frankfurt a. M.-Paderborn 1992; H. MEYER, “Die Struktur oekumenischer<br />

Konsense”, ivi, 60-74. Cfr. sopra, nota 16s.


32 w. KASPER<br />

logie e delle loro diverse scuole, di forme e tradizioni liturgiche,<br />

di stili di pietà e di mentalità diverse culturalmente condizionate.<br />

I concili – non da ultimo il Concilio di Trento – cercarono in<br />

linea generale di tener conto di questa legittima multiformità.<br />

Essi cercarono di porre dei paletti nei confronti dell’eresia, ma<br />

anche di concedere spazio alla discussione intracattolica. Che<br />

l’unità con il ministero petrino e sotto il ministero petrino ammetta<br />

una multiformità è cosa che risulta chiara soprattutto dall’esistenza<br />

delle Chiese orientali unite a Roma; esse sono Chiese<br />

“sui juris”, che con la loro ogni volta specifica tradizione liturgica,<br />

teologica, spirituale e canonica sono un patrimonio ereditario<br />

essenziale e un arricchimento della cattolicità della Chiesa<br />

universale 56 .<br />

Il modello delle Chiese di rito orientale unite a Roma ha tenuto<br />

a battesimo l’idea di una unificazione corporativa 57 e l’idea<br />

del “typos” formulata dal cardinal J. Willebrands 58 . Secondo<br />

questi progetti il riconoscimento dell’ufficio petrino non significherebbe<br />

l’inserimento nell’attuale “sistema” della Chiesa latina.<br />

Ne risulterebbe piuttosto quello che il cardinal Ratzinger ha così<br />

definito: le Chiese devono rimanere Chiese e diventare sempre<br />

più un’unica Chiesa 59 . In modo simile il cardinal J. Willebrands<br />

ha definito la futura comunione ecclesiale come “communio ecclesiarum<br />

in ecclesia Christi” 60 . Anche lo scritto L’unità attraverso<br />

la diversità di O. Cullmann va in una direzione simile 61 .<br />

Una tale unità nella diversità, se prendiamo seriamente la<br />

struttura incarnatoria dell’ordine cristiano della salvezza, così<br />

come esso è concepito sia dalla teologia cattolica che da quella<br />

56 OE 7; Lettera Apostolica Orientale lumen (1995).<br />

57 Vescovo H. TENHUMBERG, “Kirchliche Union bzw. korporative Wiedervereinigung”,<br />

in W. DANIELSNEYER-C. H. RATSCHOW, Kirche und Gemeinde, Witten<br />

1974, 25.<br />

58 J. WILLEBRANDS, in Information Service.<br />

59 J. RATZINGER, “Die Kirche und die Kirchen”, in Reformatio 13 (1964)<br />

105.<br />

60 J. WILLEBRANDS, in Proche Orient chrétien 25 (1975) 14s.<br />

61 O. CULLMANN, Einheit durch Vielfalt. Grundlegung und Beitrag zur Diskussion<br />

ueber die Moeglichkeiten ihrer Verwirchlichung, Tuebingen 1986 (tr.<br />

it. L’unità attraverso la diversità. Il suo fondamento e il problema della sua realizzazione,<br />

Queriniana, Brescia 1987).


UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE ... 33<br />

luterana, non può essere semplicemente invisibile o sussistere<br />

come una comunione accompagnata da contrasti. Il consenso<br />

nella dottrina non è solo, per l’unità della Chiesa, un’esigenza<br />

cattolica, bensì anche un’esigenza luterana. Perciò a me pare<br />

che vadano esclusi una rinuncia radicale al consenso ecumenico<br />

e un ecumenismo fermi restando i contrasti, come a volte si propone<br />

62 . Ciò vale in misura ancora maggiore per un cambiamento<br />

ecumenico di paradigmi in direzione della concezione di un<br />

ecumenismo puramente secolare, per il quale l’unità della Chiesa<br />

diventa una cosa marginale, quando non viene addirittura<br />

persa completamente di vista 63 .<br />

Con queste delimitazioni negative non abbiamo ancora naturalmente<br />

detto di quale specie di consenso ci sia bisogno per<br />

l’unità. Questa questione fu ampiamente discussa, da parte cattolica,<br />

in occasione del piano <strong>propos</strong>to da Rahner-Fries. Secondo<br />

questi teologi ogni unità della Chiesa presuppone un certo<br />

numero di formulazioni fondamentali comuni nel campo della<br />

fede. Essi pensano con ciò in primo luogo alle verità fondamentali,<br />

così come esse sono espresse nella Sacra Scrittura, nel Simbolo<br />

Apostolico e nel Simbolo Nicenocostantinopolitano. Al di là<br />

di questo nucleo di fondo vincolante Rahner-Fries formulano il<br />

seguente principio quale un principio realistico nel campo della<br />

fede: nessuna Chiesa parziale può respingere con decisione e sul<br />

piano della professione di fede una <strong>propos</strong>izione, che in un’altra<br />

Chiesa parziale è un dogma vincolante. Questo principio non significa<br />

per loro naturalmente che una Chiesa parziale abbia<br />

l’obbligo di professare in maniera esplicita e positiva, al di là delle<br />

professioni di fede menzionate, un dogma professato in un’altra<br />

Chiesa parziale 64 . Essi vorrebbero che ci si accontentasse di<br />

una tolleranza gnoseologica.<br />

62 Cfr. al riguardo, oltre a E. HERMS (sopra, nota 12), le posizioni di E.<br />

Geldbach e L. Klein nel “DOeSTA-Studie”, in OER 1988/2.<br />

63 K. KAISER, Oekumene im Uebergang. Paradigmenwechsel in der oekumenischen<br />

Bewegung, Muenchen 1989. Con ciò non contestiamo il fatto che<br />

l’unità della Chiesa non è fine a se stessa, ma è a sua volta sacramento del<br />

mondo. Cfr. LG 1; GS 42, 45 e passim.<br />

64 H. FRIES-K. RAHNER, Einigung der Kirchen - reale Moeglichkeit (Quaestiones<br />

disputatae 100), Freiburg i. Br. 1983, tesi 2, p. 23-24 (tr. it. Unione delle<br />

chiese - possibilità reale, Morcelliana, Brescia 1986).


34 w. KASPER<br />

Questa idea di una tolleranza gnoseologica fu in vari modi<br />

criticata, e a mio giudizio giustamente criticata. Dobbiamo infatti<br />

sì ammettere che, al di là del consenso nei Simboli fondamentali<br />

della fede, basta che nessuna Chiesa dica a <strong>propos</strong>ito<br />

delle professioni di fede delle altre Chiese che esse non contraddicono<br />

il vangelo, però dobbiamo aggiungere – e questo va al di<br />

là della tolleranza gnoseologica di Rahner-Fries – che ogni Chiesa,<br />

pur senza adottarle positivamente, deve riconoscere che le<br />

formulazioni di fede di un’altra Chiesa possono essere una articolazione<br />

storica possibile dell’unico vangelo comune.<br />

Che questa non sia una semplice teoria o utopia risulta chiaro<br />

dal fatto che oggi si riconosce generalmente che il “filioque”,<br />

controverso tra Oriente e Occidente, è sì espressione di una teologia<br />

trinitaria orientale e occidentale diversa, ma che esso non<br />

indica alcuna oggettiva differenza nel campo della fede e che<br />

perciò Oriente e Occidente non devono imporre le loro diverse<br />

formulazioni 65 . La stessa cosa vale a <strong>propos</strong>ito delle formulazioni<br />

del Concilio di Calcedonia (451) circa la dottrina delle due nature,<br />

che furono respinte già nel secolo V dalle Chiese veteroorientali<br />

(precalcedonensi), per questo considerate fino ai nostri<br />

giorni Chiese monofisite. Nel frattempo, nelle dichiarazioni ufficiali<br />

comuni, si riconosce che si tratta qui di differenze terminologiche<br />

che non mettono in discussione l’unica fede comune 66 .<br />

Nella Dichiarazione congiunta sulla dottrina della giustificazione<br />

abbiamo a che fare con un processo simile. In essa non abbiamo<br />

infatti un consenso totale, ma un consenso differenziato.<br />

Si è trovato un consenso circa le verità fondamentali della dottrina<br />

della giustificazione, ma si è nello stesso tempo preso atto<br />

che, in altre questioni, esistono impostazioni, accentuazioni e<br />

terminologie differenti, che tuttavia non eliminano il consenso<br />

raggiunto e sono piuttosto tollerabili all’interno della comunione<br />

ecclesiale. Le differenze rimanenti non sono contraddittorie,<br />

ma complementari. Esse non hanno un carattere capace di dividere<br />

la Chiesa, bensì rappresentano un’unità in una diversità ri-<br />

65 Y. CONGAR, Der Heilige Geist, Freiburg i. Br. 1986, 361-376 (ed. it. Credo<br />

nello Spirito Santo, 3 voll., Queriniana, Brescia 1981-1983).<br />

66 In Dokumente wachsender Uebereinstimmung 1931-1982, Paderborn-<br />

Frankfurt a. M. 1983, I 541-542; II 1982-1990, 572.


UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE ... 35<br />

conciliata 67 .<br />

Questa teoria del consenso differenziato e dell’unità nella diversità<br />

riconciliata risale sostanzialmente a Johann Adam Moehler,<br />

l’importantissimo rappresentante della Scuola di Tubinga del<br />

secolo XIX e uno dei grandi precursori dell’odierna teologia ecumenica.<br />

Nella sua opera giovanile L’unità nella Chiesa egli distingue,<br />

nello spirito del romanticismo del suo tempo, tra “Gegensatz”<br />

(contrasto, diversità) e “Widerspruch” (contraddizione,<br />

antitesi). I contrasti, le diversità fanno per Moehler parte della<br />

vita; ogni vera vita, anche la vita della Chiesa, si svolge in seno a<br />

una compenetrazione di cose tra loro diverse, che si muovono<br />

pertanto nell’unità. L’eresia invece è una contraddizione e come<br />

tale una diversità sbagliata, che si esclude e si assolutizza. Ma tali<br />

contraddizioni possono, secondo Moehler, di nuovo trasformarsi<br />

in diversità, allorché esse si riconciliano con l’unità 68 . Un<br />

insigne ecumenista cattolico, il domenicano Yves Congar, riprese<br />

queste idee e le utilizzò per il dibattito ecumenico 69 .<br />

Il modello di una unità in una diversità riconciliata è molto<br />

importante per la teologia ecumenica sia per quanto riguarda il<br />

fine del lavoro ecumenico e sia per quanto riguarda il suo metodo.<br />

Esso, poiché non mira a un consenso completo, è spesso detto<br />

modello della convergenza, un modello il quale si contenta in<br />

molti casi di stabilire delle analogie e delle equivalenze che<br />

esprimono una intenzione comune, un modello che supera le<br />

differenze senza poterle eliminare fino a raggiungere un pieno<br />

consenso 70 . La Dichiarazione congiunta è sotto questo aspetto –<br />

pur con tutti i suoi lati deboli – un modello tutto sommato riu-<br />

67 Gemeinsame Erklaerung zur Rechtfertigunslehre (Dichiarazione congiunta<br />

sulla giustificazione), in modo riassuntivo nel nr. 40s. Cfr. la riguardo<br />

K. Lehmann. Cfr. anche A. DULLES, “Catholic and Protestant: Contrary or<br />

Complementary?”, in The Catholicity of the Church, New York 1995, 147-166.<br />

68 JOHANN ADAM MOEHLER, Die Einheit in der Kirche oder das Prinzip des<br />

Katholizismus dargestellt im Geiste der Kirchenvaeter der drei ersten Jahrhunderte<br />

(1825), a cura e con introduzione di J. R. Geiselmann, Darmstadt 1957,<br />

§ 46, 152-157 (tr. it. L’unità nella Chiesa, cioè il principio del cattolicesimo nello<br />

spirito dei Padri della Chiesa dei primi tre secoli, Città Nuova, Roma 1969).<br />

69 Y. CONGAR, Diversités et commmunion, Paris 1982 (tr. it. Diversità e comunione,<br />

Cittadella, Assisi 1984).<br />

70 Cfr. W. THOENISSEN, o. c., 28-32.


36 w. KASPER<br />

scito, che ci dice quale forma una simile unità nella multiformità<br />

riconciliata può assumere.<br />

VI. Visione trinitaria di una futura comunione ecclesiale<br />

In ultima analisi la visione di una unità nella diversità è fondata<br />

sul fatto che la Chiesa è formata ad immagine del Dio unitrino,<br />

sul fatto che essa è come una icona della Trinità 71 . Come<br />

nella Trinità l’unità dell’essenza e la distinzione delle tre persone<br />

sono indissolubilmente unite, così avviene in modo analogo anche<br />

nella Chiesa. In questa visuale trinitaria l’unità della Chiesa<br />

non è un sistema uniformistico, così come non è una semplice<br />

accumulazione o federazione di Chiese eterogenee, ma è comunione<br />

attraverso la partecipazione, nell’unico Spirito Santo, all’unico<br />

Signore Gesù Cristo. L’unità della Chiesa non può perciò<br />

essere strutturata in base a qualche modello politico. Essa non<br />

corrisponde né a uno Stato assolutistico, né a una costituzione<br />

statale federativa, ma è una unità “sui generis” che affonda le<br />

proprie radici nel mistero del Dio unitrino e ne è, nello stesso<br />

tempo, una espressione.<br />

Nel mondo moderno facciamo fatica a trovar ascolto con<br />

questo nostro messaggio del mistero di Dio. Se non lavoriamo<br />

ecumenicamente insieme, ben difficilmente ci riusciremo ancora.<br />

Ma questo nostro mondo con i suoi molteplici conflitti potenziali,<br />

che si unifica sempre di più ed è tuttavia profondamente<br />

lacerato, di che cosa avrebbe più che mai bisogno se non della<br />

testimonianza di una simile unità, che non solo tollera la diversità,<br />

ma la sperimenta e la riconosce come un arricchimento?<br />

La realizzazione della piena unità-communio quale unità nella<br />

multiformità è perciò oggi diventata una questione esistenziale<br />

non solo per la cristianità, bensì per tutto il mondo.<br />

Proprio oggi c’è bisogno dell’unità dei discepoli di Gesù, affinché<br />

il mondo creda (Gv 17,21). Solo nella fede in colui che è<br />

71 LG 4; UR 3. Cfr, B. FORTE, La Chiesa, icona della Trinità, 1984; G. Greshake,<br />

Der dreieine Gott. Eine trinitarische Theologie, Freiburg i. Br. 1997,<br />

377-438 (tr. it. Il Dio unitrino. Teologia trinitaria, Queriniana, Brescia 2000).


UNITÀ DELLA CHIESA E COMUNIONE ECCLESIALE ... 37<br />

la via, la verità e la vita (Gv 14,6) il nostro mondo può infatti finalmente<br />

trovare la pace e l’unità.<br />

Molti lamentano il fatto che il cammino dell’avvicinamento<br />

ecumenico procede troppo lentamente. In realtà ci vuole un’infinita<br />

pazienza lungo questo percorso. Ma ci sono anche segni<br />

che inducono a sperare. La celebrazione ecumenica dell’apertura<br />

della porta santa a San Paolo fuori le mura, svoltasi il 18 gennaio,<br />

è stata per me un segno profetico del genere, nonché un<br />

presagio e una anticipazione di una possibile unità nella molteplicità<br />

malgrado tutte le difficoltà: il papa aprì la porta santa non<br />

da solo, ma insieme al delegato di Costantinopoli e all’arcivescovo<br />

di Canterbury, insieme essi si inginocchiarono davanti alla<br />

porta che simboleggia Cristo. Alla fine delegazioni di ventidue<br />

Chiese orientali e occidentali scambiarono con il papa il bacio<br />

della pace.<br />

Quella fu molto di più di una splendida celebrazione esteriore.<br />

Fu un’ora della grazia. Tutti erano profondamente commossi<br />

e intimamente felici. Noi, che avevamo lavorato duramente<br />

per questo, fino a poco tempo prima quasi non l’avremmo<br />

ancora ritenuto possibile in quella forma. Perciò sono convinto<br />

che l’unità della Chiesa sia, malgrado tutte le difficoltà,<br />

non un semplice sogno, ma come dono dello Spirito di Dio una<br />

reale possibilità.<br />

W. KASPER<br />

—————<br />

Cardinal Walter Kasper is Prefect of the Pontifical Council for<br />

the Promotion of Unity among Christians.<br />

El Cardenal Walter Kasper es Prefecto del Pontificio Consejo<br />

para la promoción de la unidad entre los cristianos.<br />

—————


StMor 40 (2002) 39-61<br />

BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE, C.SS.R.<br />

THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUST WAR?<br />

In response to the terrorist attacks on the Twin Towers and<br />

the Pentagon, and the subsequent “war on terrorism,” a number<br />

of Catholic spokespersons, including lay experts in military<br />

affairs, and some Cardinals and Bishops appealed to the doctrine<br />

of the “Just War” and argued that armed force in this case<br />

could be accepted as a just response. 1 Pope John Paul II himself<br />

has made a number of statements, affirming that religion should<br />

never be used to justify war 2 , promoting tolerance and dialogue<br />

between Christians and Muslims, and calling for aid for the victims<br />

of violence. The Pope has not expressed a moral judgment<br />

about this particular war as such, but has called for the rejection<br />

of all war. 3 Indeed there seem to be two levels of discourse<br />

involved here: a prophetic denunciation of war on the part of the<br />

Pope, and a calculated, ethical acceptance of it, under certain<br />

conditions, by a number of other Church leaders. The Pope’s<br />

statements reflect the longing for peace and opposition to violence<br />

which has been present in Christianity from its beginnings.<br />

The others, using the language of the just war, continue<br />

1<br />

MICHAEL QUINLAN, “The Just War litmus test,” Tablet, 13 October, 2001,<br />

1451; Editorial, America, Oct. 29, 2001, “The aerial attack by the United<br />

States on terrorist and Taliban targets in Afghanistan has been declared a<br />

just war by a number of Catholic leaders, including some bishops and cardinals,”<br />

URL http://www.americapressorg/terror.htm; Cardinal Cormac<br />

Murphy-O’Connor and Archbishop Patrick Kelly in their joint statement<br />

published in Tablet, 29 September, 2001, 1390; “Living With Faith and Hope<br />

After September 11,” Origins 31 (2001) 416.<br />

2<br />

JOHN PAUL II, “Do not use religion as a reason for conflict,” Origins 31<br />

(2001) 285.<br />

3 In his Angelus message for Sunday, 27 January 2002, the Pope said:<br />

“Violence never again! War never again! Terrorism never again! In the name<br />

of God, may every religion bring upon the earth justice and peace, forgiveness<br />

and life, love!” URL http://www.vatican.va.<br />

39


40 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

the centuries old search for a responsible way to deal with<br />

unavoidable violence. Is it still appropriate to present the “traditional”<br />

doctrine of the just war, 4 in the public forum, as a moral<br />

framework within which we may answer questions concerning<br />

the legitimacy of a war and the morality of the conduct of that<br />

war?<br />

In its present form, the JWD is usually taken to mean an ethical<br />

and/or legal doctrine which, while adopting a presumption<br />

against war, holds that it may be justified, according to a set of<br />

criteria. A first group of these criteria refers to the decision to go<br />

to war, and requires legitimate authority, just cause, right intention,<br />

while the second concerns the conduct of war, and requires<br />

discrimination, proportionality, last resort, and reasonable hope<br />

of success. The criteria of proportionality refer both to the decision<br />

to go to war— the foreseen harms which inevitably accompany<br />

war ought be proportionate to the good being sought—<br />

and to the use of violence for particular objectives, which ought<br />

to be proportionate to the importance of this objective for<br />

achieving the purpose of the war.<br />

Critics, have long seen the doctrine as a corruption of the<br />

genuine Christian tradition. 5 It is further charged that it has not<br />

fostered peace, but has simply opened the way to the justification<br />

of violence, which has resulted in the murder of millions. 6<br />

As a response to the first criticism, this article will offer an interpretation<br />

of how the change in the tradition, from the early<br />

Church’s rejection of violence, to the acceptance of just war,<br />

came about. In respect to the second charge, historical studies<br />

have claimed that the doctrine was invoked to legitimize wars,<br />

or at least that authorities twisted the doctrine to provide pretexts<br />

for their wars. 7 According to one author, even St. Francis of<br />

4 Henceforth, the JWD.<br />

5<br />

ROLAND H. BAINTON, Christian Attitudes to War and Peace (Nashville:<br />

Abingdon, 1960) 236.<br />

6<br />

JOHN DEAR, The God of Peace:Towards a Theology of Nonviolence<br />

(Maryknoll N.Y: Orbis Books, 1994) 126.<br />

7<br />

JAMES TURNER JOHNSON, Ideology, Reason, and the Limitations of War<br />

(Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1975) 19.


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 41<br />

Assisi invoked the doctrine to justify war. 8 Has the JWD been<br />

effective in restraining war? In some circumstances, it does<br />

seem to have acted as a restraint, at least during the era of<br />

Christendom. 9 However, there is not sufficient published evidence<br />

available to form a reasonable judgment on the historical<br />

effectiveness, or lack of it, of the doctrine over a longer period.<br />

In relation to the war against terrorism, up to the present, conducted<br />

in Afghanistan, the JWD criteria may well have had a<br />

restraining influence on military planning and conduct. But the<br />

issue is complicated by tight restrictions on information; journalists<br />

were kept away from the theatre of war so that people<br />

have been deprived of the factual knowledge needed to form a<br />

responsible judgment. To some extent at least this lack is now<br />

being remedied. 10<br />

Some of the criticism of the JWD can be answered by a clarifications<br />

of its presuppositions. It does not maintain that war as<br />

such is just, or that all wars are just; it holds that war is not, in<br />

itself, always immoral, or, in other words, that it is not intrinsically<br />

evil. Any particular war, to be justified, must satisfy all of<br />

the criteria it <strong>propos</strong>es. It would thus be logically possible that,<br />

after considering the purposes and conduct of historical wars,<br />

the upholders of the doctrine would have to condemn all wars.<br />

At present, both International Law and official Catholic teaching<br />

accept defence only as just cause. The only form of war now<br />

legally permissible for a state, is a war of individual or collective<br />

self-defense. 11 Pius XII also taught that defense was the only just<br />

8 CRISTOPH T. MAIER, Preaching the Crusades: Mendicant Friars and the<br />

Cross in the Thirteenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,<br />

1994) 15; JAMES TURNER JOHNSON, The Holy War Idea in Western and Islamic<br />

Traditions, (Pennsylvania: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1997) 57.<br />

9 JOHNSON, Ideology, 13.<br />

10 CARL CONETTA, “Strange Victory: A critical appraisal of Operation<br />

Enduring Freedom and the Afghanistan war.” Cambridge, MA: Commonwealth<br />

Institute Project on Defense Alternatives Research Monograph, #6, 30 January<br />

2002; URL http://www.comw.org/pda/O201strangevic.html; Idem., “Why a<br />

Higher Rate of Civilian Bombing Casualties?” 18 January 2002, URL<br />

http://www.comw.org/pda/0201oef.html.<br />

11 Article 51 of Chapter 7 of the United Nations charter recognizes war<br />

of defense as a right to be exercised pending action by the Security Council.


42 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

cause for which war might be fought, 12 and this has become the<br />

accepted official teaching of the Church. The Second Vatican<br />

Council (1965) affirmed that: “As long as the danger of war<br />

remains and there is no competent and sufficiently powerful<br />

authority at the international level, governments cannot be<br />

denied the right to legitimate defence once every means of<br />

peaceful settlement has been exhausted.” 13<br />

This teaching implies an acceptance of the JWD, in the form<br />

of a doctrine of just defence. This statement has provided the<br />

basis for a number of the comments made by some Church leaders,<br />

on the war in Afghanistan. The attack of September 11 th and<br />

the implied threat of similar attacks in the future, judged in<br />

terms of the doctrine, clearly provides a just cause for defensive<br />

war. The issue is relatively much clearer than was the case with<br />

the Gulf War of 1990-91. 14 Indeed, the attack on the U.S.A. clearly<br />

violated all the criteria of the JWD. However, while a war of<br />

defence may be justified in principle, a definitive judgment on<br />

the morality of initiating the war would still require the test of<br />

proportionality: is war proportionate to the just end of selfdefence,<br />

or should other methods be preferred, such as those<br />

provided by international law or sanctions? 15<br />

The proportionality requirement presents special difficulties<br />

for the upholders of the JWD. Furthermore, many of those who<br />

condemn war completely, do not do so simply on the basis of<br />

abstract principle, but because they have concluded from historical<br />

evidence that war can never, in reality, be a proportionate<br />

means. Hence, in this article, particular attention will be given<br />

to this criterion, both in reference to the decision to initiate war,<br />

and to the conduct of particular operations during that war.<br />

WILLIAM V. O’BRIEN, The Conduct of Just and Limited War (New York: Praeger,<br />

1981) 23.<br />

12 JOHN COURTNEY MURRAY, S.J. “War as a Moral Problem,” in Idem., We<br />

Hold These Truths (London: Sheed and Ward, 1960) 258.<br />

13 Gaudium et Spes, # 79.<br />

14 Cf. JOHN LANGAN, S.J. “The Just-War Theory After the Gulf War,”<br />

Theological Studies 53 (1992) 95-112.<br />

15 Cf. “A Just War,” Editorial, America, Oct. 8, 2001, URL<br />

http://www.americapress.org/terror.htm.


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 43<br />

After the terrorist act of September 11 th 2001, journalists<br />

asked some Catholic spokespersons, whether an armed response<br />

was justifiable in terms of “traditional just war teaching.” As J.<br />

Bryan Hehir has well pointed out, this is too narrow a question.<br />

16 Nevertheless, it does call for an answer. To what does “tradition”<br />

refer here? Does it mean the secular tradition which<br />

emerged and separated from the Christian tradition, with a view<br />

to providing a generally acceptable, rational code governing the<br />

initiating and conduct of war, which is now, at least in part,<br />

embodied in international law? Or does it mean, as Michael<br />

Walzer <strong>propos</strong>ed, that set of commonly accepted, but largely<br />

unarticulated principles on which we base the arguments we<br />

have about war 17 ? Or does it mean the just war doctrine as it<br />

developed and is maintained within the Christian, or specifically<br />

within the Catholic tradition? 18 The answer can make a considerable<br />

difference to the way in which the doctrine is interpreted.<br />

The criteria of the JWD, as stated above, are abstracted<br />

from the tradition or traditions within which they were formed,<br />

and if they are to be understood must be interpreted within<br />

those traditions. Since the question to be answered in this article<br />

is the appropriateness of the use of the doctrine by Catholic<br />

spokespersons, the following explanation will be concerned<br />

principally with the Catholic tradition, while taking others into<br />

account.<br />

Since there is no generally accepted notion of “tradition,”<br />

and in particular of the kind of moral tradition we are dealing<br />

with here, it will be necessary to make some stipulations about<br />

the meaning of tradition. John Courtney Murray, in discussing<br />

the morality of war, referred to the “tradition of reason,” but<br />

without explaining in any depth what this might mean. 19 What I<br />

16 J. BRYAN HEHIR, “What can be done? What should be done?” America<br />

Oct. 8, 2001,URL http://www.americapress.org/terror.htm.<br />

17 cf. MICHAEL WALZER, Just and Unjust War (New York: Basic Books,<br />

1977).<br />

18<br />

JOSEPH JOBLIN, L’Église et la Guerre: Conscience, violence, pouvoir<br />

(Paris: Desclée de Brouwer, 1988) 9.<br />

19 John Courtney Murray, S.J. “The Problem of the Moral Vacuum,” in<br />

Idem., We Hold These Truths (London: Sheed and Ward, 1960) 285.


44 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

offer here may be taken as an endeavour to provide an account<br />

of that notion. According to Alasdair McIntyre, a tradition may<br />

be defined as “… an historically extended, socially embodied<br />

argument, and an argument precisely in part about the goods<br />

which constitute that tradition.” 20 For the purposes of this<br />

inquiry, I will adapt this definition somewhat so as to bring out<br />

more clearly that the “goods” are not merely ideas about goods,<br />

but lived realities, and that the form of discourse is wider than<br />

formal “argument.” Thus, in this article, tradition means an<br />

extended process of communication, by testimony and argument<br />

over time, of what has proved itself to be a good way of<br />

life. That which is communicated is not merely information,<br />

beliefs and doctrines about that life, but the substance of that<br />

good life, that is its actual embodiment in the way of life of a<br />

community. Commitment to a tradition entails the acceptance of<br />

a defining experience, which may take the form of accepting a<br />

charismatic person or a group, who are seen as having inaugurated<br />

the tradition to which its present inhabitants now adhere.<br />

The latter see the tradition, entailing a continuity from the present<br />

to the past, as bringing them into contact with the original<br />

experience of the good life in which they now participate.<br />

Accepting the tradition in this manner, and verifying it through<br />

their own experience and critical reflection, opens the possibility<br />

of continuing that good life in the future.<br />

Coherence with the tradition will therefore entail coherence<br />

with the particular experiences and insights of the founding figure<br />

or group, insofar as they have been accepted by those committed<br />

to the tradition, as defining what is a good life.<br />

Commitment to the Christian tradition entails a commitment in<br />

this sense to the person of Jesus, and to the experience and<br />

insights of the apostolic church. These are expressed normatively<br />

in the continuing tradition, embodied in the Scriptures.<br />

Commitment to the tradition includes acceptance of the teachings<br />

of authority which interpret these sources, namely what we<br />

now call the “teachings of the Magisterium.” Living that tradi-<br />

20 ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, After Virtue, 2 nd ed. (Notre Dame, Ind.: University<br />

of Notre Dame Press, 1984) 222.


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 45<br />

tion will, of course, entail modifications and adaptations as the<br />

subsequent adherents to the tradition seek to live out the defining<br />

form of the good life in their own historical circumstance.<br />

Recalling the past may confirm the coherence of the present<br />

notions of the good life with those of the past, or it may reveal<br />

that some values have been forgotten and need to be recovered,<br />

or may manifest elements in the previous stages that offer genuine<br />

alternatives which can exercise a critique of the present; or<br />

again, it may show that some positions, which have been accepted<br />

from the past, were based on faulty arguments and need to be<br />

revised. Being committed to a tradition thus includes both an<br />

acceptance of and a critical engagement with that tradition. I<br />

must accept the position which has been reached so far in the<br />

process of argument, because it has behind it the tradition to<br />

which I myself am committed and on which I depend for my<br />

own arguments. But I may criticize that position, for example,<br />

on the grounds that it is not fully coherent with the goods <strong>propos</strong>ed<br />

by the tradition itself. Tradition, for those who are committed<br />

to it, sets the burden of proof in cases of dispute, so it is<br />

those who challenge the tradition who must prove their case. In<br />

this way the inner logic of tradition explains why certain<br />

requirements, such as the criteria of the JWD, have “prima facie”<br />

validity. 21 Commitment to the tradition implies faith in its transcendent<br />

source, God. Faith in God, who created human reason,<br />

sustains faith in that reason, while this subsumes a human faith<br />

in that same reason, engendered by reason’s proven capacity to<br />

discover and explain the basic elements of a good life.<br />

The “tradition of reason” embodied in the JWD has been<br />

elaborated within the Catholic tradition, “in the light of faith.”<br />

How faith and reason combined in this process can best be<br />

shown not by abstract formulae constructed a-priori, but by an<br />

examination of how they collaborated in the historical process<br />

by which the doctrine was formulated. An outline of this I will<br />

now seek to provide. Since a full account of the tradition, is not<br />

21 Cf. JAMES F. CHILDRESS, “Just War Criteria,” in Thomas A. Shannon, ed.,<br />

War or Peace ? (Maryknoll, NY.: Orbis, 1980) 41. The basis for accepting<br />

“prima facie” remains unaccounted for by this author. Hence, the suggestion<br />

of tradition in this article.


46 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

possible within the limits of an article, particular attention will<br />

be directed to the point at which the alleged corruption in the<br />

tradition is said to have taken place, namely in the work of St.<br />

Augustine and in the consolidation of the doctrine by St.<br />

Thomas Aquinas and his followers.<br />

Although the negative influence of Augustine’s teaching has<br />

been well documented, 22 it is not appropriate to read St.<br />

Augustine merely as the father of the just war doctrine, or the<br />

original justifier of religiously sanctioned violence. Indeed,<br />

Augustine has been studied as the “doctor of peace.” 23 Augustine<br />

held that war can be justified only if it is directed to peace. 24 But<br />

to understand this position, we must place it in its context.<br />

Augustine dealt with three options in regard to the political<br />

order. He could adopt the strongly eschatological view of the<br />

early Church, which saw the Church as alien to worldly affairs<br />

and in particular to the State. It would be in keeping with such<br />

a view to hold that Christians should have nothing to do with<br />

war. A second model was that of Eusebius of Caesarea (d.340<br />

A.D.) according to which the use of secular power had a sacral<br />

significance, in that the use of such power for religious ends was<br />

considered as an instrument of God in the working out of the<br />

history of salvation. 25 It would be in keeping with such a position<br />

to see war, in particular the wars of the Roman state as<br />

instruments in the providential plan of God. It would seem that<br />

Augustine accepted this second model for some years. Only later<br />

(after the sack of Rome by Alaric in 410) did he move away from<br />

seeing the coercive policies of the empire in favour of<br />

Christianity as the instruments by which God was fulfilling his<br />

plan. Especially in the City of God, he then developed a doctrine<br />

of the political order, which insisted firmly on the fulfilment of<br />

22 FREDERICK H. RUSSELL, The Just War in the Middle Ages (Cambridge:<br />

Cambridge University Press, 1975) 16-39.<br />

23 STANISLAW BUDZIK, Doctor Pacis: Theologie des Friedens bei Augustinus<br />

(Innsbruck: Tyrolia Verlag, 1988).<br />

24 Letter 189.6 (CSEL 57.489)<br />

25 EUSEBIUS, Preparation for the Gospel, 1.4.4, SC 206, 121. Cited in, Louis<br />

J. Swift, The Early Fathers on War and Military Service (Wilmington,<br />

Delaware: Michael Glazier, 1983) 83.


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 47<br />

God’s plan only in the eschatological kingdom to be realized<br />

beyond human history, but recognized a role for the state, and<br />

for war in the present dispensation, as a lamentable necessity. 26<br />

What were Augustine’s views on war as the instrument of<br />

God? The question arose in a special way in connection with a<br />

Gospel text, the interpretation of which has had an ominous and<br />

fateful history: it was used for centuries to justify the use of violence<br />

against the Jewish people. The prophecy of the divine punishment<br />

which will fall on Jerusalem (Lk 19: 41-44; 21: 20-24; Mt<br />

22:7) presents the destruction as punishment for not accepting<br />

God’s call. Augustine believed that those Roman armies who<br />

destroyed Jerusalem were wicked, but they were despite this, the<br />

instruments of God in punishing the Jews. 27 Similarly, the invasions<br />

by the Barbarians are interpreted by Augustine as a punishment<br />

of the wicked for the corruption of morals, and a purifying<br />

trial for the good. 28 However, even if God is using an invading<br />

army to fulfil his purposes, it does not follow that the soldiers<br />

of that army are, for that reason, morally justified in what<br />

they do. God uses what they do, even if what they do is morally<br />

evil. Man may act in a disordered way, but this does not escape<br />

the counsel of God, who uses that disorder for his own purposes.<br />

29 Augustine makes a clear distinction between the sinful soldier<br />

bent on domination and the Christian soldier serving legitimate<br />

authority: God may use the sin of the former for his own<br />

purposes, but will eventually punish it. 30 What of the case of war<br />

waged by legitimate authority for a just purpose? Could it be<br />

26 R. A. MARCUS, Saeculum: History and Society in the Theology of St.<br />

Augustine (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988) 70, 98. De Civitate<br />

Dei, XIX, 17. CCSL XLVIII, 685.<br />

27 H. A. DEANE, Political and Social Ideas of St. Augustine (New York and<br />

London: Columbia University Press, 1963) 309, Notes to ch. 5, n.12. (En. in<br />

P., LXXIII, 7-8; CCSL XXXIX, 1010-11).<br />

28<br />

DEANE, Political and Social Ideas, 310, n.12. (De Civitate Dei, I,1; CCSL<br />

XLVII, 2).<br />

29<br />

HENRY PAOLUCCI, ed. The Political Writings of St. Augustine (Chicago:<br />

Henry Regnery 1962) x. Augustine.<br />

30 . JOHN HELGELAND, ROBERT J. DALY and J. PATOUT BURNS, Christians and<br />

the Military: The Early Experience (Philadelphia: Fortress Press 1985) 80.


48 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

said that God wills or commands such a war? It would seem<br />

rather that for Augustine, waging a just war is something<br />

imposed on the just man by those necessities which arise in a<br />

sinful world. Good men may be required to undertake war “at<br />

God’s command, or the command of a legitimate authority” but<br />

such a divine command would come into play only in those situations<br />

where maintaining order in a sinful world required violence.<br />

This was his view at least when writing against Faustus<br />

(397-398). 31 Divine authority does not descend arbitrarily from<br />

the heavens; it applies to situations where war would be considered<br />

just on other grounds than the divine fiat.<br />

What of Augustine’s notorious support of state coercion<br />

against heretics, in his case against the Donatists? This would be<br />

a clear case of religion fostering coercion, if not violence or war.<br />

The Edict of Unity (405) which branded the Donatists as heretics,<br />

and so brought them under the general laws on heresy, was an<br />

act of the imperial court. 32 However, Augustine accepted the<br />

change of policy it embodied as an act of providence. In interpreting<br />

its significance, Augustine fell back on some of the ideas<br />

we have already discussed. The edict and the suppression which<br />

followed, he viewed as an act of divine “disciplina” by which<br />

God, the stern father, inflicts punishment on his delinquent children,<br />

checking their evil tendencies, by a series of catastrophes<br />

as he did in the Old Testament period and continues to do now. 33<br />

As Peter Brown describes it, Augustine saw this necessary persecution<br />

of the Donatists heretics as another form of such necessary<br />

discipline or “controlled catastrophe.” 34<br />

31 Contra Faustum, 22.74; Migne, PL t. XLII, 447; Swift, The Early<br />

Fathers, 120.<br />

32<br />

PETER BROWN, Augustine of Hippo (Berkely: University of California<br />

Press, 1969) 234. It needs to be remembered that the edict imposed “inconveniences”<br />

(as Augustine called them) restricting the Donatists ability to dispose<br />

of property and to hold office. It did not impose the death penalty.<br />

Augustine was opposed in principle to the death penalty, ibid., 241 although<br />

the means of disciplina included flogging, ibid., 239.<br />

33 Letter, 93.2.6. The Fathers of the Church, St. Augustine, Letters, vol. 2<br />

(Washington, D.C. The Catholic University of America Press, 1985) 61. Swift,<br />

The Early Fathers, 148.<br />

34<br />

BROWN, Augustine, 237.


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 49<br />

For Augustine, while no political community can claim to<br />

embody true justice, this does not mean that all human political<br />

communities are equally unjust and immoral. Political societies<br />

are better or worse according to what they love. 35 Thus, the<br />

earthly peace which such a political community sustains is a<br />

genuine good, and gift of God. But it may not be identified with<br />

the true peace of the Kingdom. It follows, therefore, that those<br />

who work to preserve this limited, but necessary, peace do a<br />

good work and should not shirk or withdraw from it, even<br />

though they may feel pain in the exercise of their task. Living in<br />

a sinful world, in the Kingdom of this world, we ought use what<br />

is available to us to preserve the wretched kind of peace that we<br />

can attain here. Provided it is directed to this end, namely peace,<br />

the activity of war may be justified. According to St. Augustine,<br />

a soldier may be justified in waging war, and in killing in war, if<br />

he acts as the agent of the law. Since the law is necessary, given<br />

the condition of sinful mankind, to prevent men from destroying<br />

each other and to maintain a certain kind of peace, the activities<br />

of a soldier who acts as an instrument of the law can be justified.<br />

In later writings, however, St. Augustine seems to have moved<br />

away from such a justification in favour of one looking to the<br />

protection of others, and the common good. 36 Whatever may be<br />

said of these differences, it is generally accepted that, “Augustine<br />

of Hippo developed a theory of the complementarity of the<br />

earthly and heavenly cities which legitimated the waging of war<br />

by Christian rulers” 37 and the participation of Christian soldiers<br />

in submission to authority.<br />

What we find in St. Thomas’s treatment of war is a theological<br />

context heavily dependent on St. Augustine, combined, however,<br />

with a return to a Greek view, specifically that of Aristotle,<br />

of political order. However, in the question on war itself, while<br />

there are many citations from Augustine in St. Thomas’ princi-<br />

35 De Civitate Dei, 19.24. CCSL XLVIII, 695.<br />

36 GREGORY LEONARD COONEY, C.M. The Magisterium in Moral Matters of<br />

Bishops’ Conferences in the Light of the Document The Challenge of Peace.<br />

(Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Faculty of Theology, Gregorianum<br />

University, Rome, 1989) 76.<br />

37 HELGELAND, Christians, 73.


50 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

pal text on the subject, there is only one from Aristotle. 38<br />

According to Russell, St.Thomas makes an innovative move in<br />

invoking the common good as a justification of war, and invoking<br />

an Aristotelean doctrine of politics to justify the ruler’s<br />

authority to wage war. 39 However, as the recent research on St.<br />

Thomas’s teaching on peace and war by Gerhard Beestermöller<br />

shows, his teaching on just war must be read as a systematic,<br />

theological ethic of peace. 40 The more specific context, in the<br />

Summa, 41 of the treatment of peace and force is the section on<br />

the vices opposed to charity, and more particularly the vices<br />

opposed to the effect of charity, which is peace. 42 St. Thomas<br />

presents peace first of all as an interior effect of charity. But he<br />

does not restrict it to interior morality, interior peace is meaningless<br />

without its “opus” or work, which we might translate<br />

“peace-making.” War is treated as a sin against peace in its opus<br />

or work. Since St. Thomas drew on the thought of Aristotle, his<br />

final views on the origin and status of political authority diverge<br />

from those of Augustine. 43 However, he retains Augustine’s argument<br />

that the use of the sword is justified, provided it is used in<br />

due subjection to authority and law, in the case of a private person,<br />

or from zeal for justice, in the case of a public official, who<br />

acts quasi ex autoritate dei. 44<br />

St. Thomas develops Aristotle’s thinking in two ways. First,<br />

he draws on the biblical doctrine of God the creator so as to<br />

widen his analysis of the good human life, from the limited polis,<br />

to the quasi-political community of all human creatures under<br />

the universal authority of the creator. Secondly, he adopts<br />

Aristotle’s political notion of philia (amicitia) as his model for<br />

the caritas which is the foundation of the community of the<br />

38 S. Th. II-II, q. 40, a. 2; Politics, I, (1252b3).<br />

39 S. Th. II-II, q. 40, a. 1. ad 2. FREDERICK H. RUSSELL, The Just War in the<br />

Middle Ages (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975) 261.<br />

40<br />

GERHARD BEESTERMÖLLER, Thomas von Aquin und der gerechte Krieg<br />

(Cologne: J-P. Bachem, 1990) 31.<br />

41 Other texts relevant to the question are: S. Th. II-II, q. 64, art 3; S. Th.<br />

II-II, q. 83, art 8; Scriptum super Sententias, lib. 3, dist. 30.<br />

42 S. Th. II-II, q. 39, intro. and q. 40.<br />

43<br />

MARCUS, Saeculum, 224.<br />

44 S. Th. II-II, q. 40, a. 1, ad 1.


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 51<br />

human family as not merely creatures but children of God. The<br />

city state or polis, for Aristotle, had its basis in philia. This<br />

means not so much friendship in our modern sense, but “companionship<br />

with trust.” 45 For Aristotle, acts against this philia<br />

are absolutely ruled out. Thus, St. Thomas distinguishes<br />

between “... not living the life of the spirit well,” perhaps by not<br />

cultivating the virtues through prayer, for such dispositions are<br />

not merely something which we acquire by education and exercise,<br />

but are gifts of the Holy Spirit, and “... those acts which are<br />

simply incompatible with membership of the community sustained<br />

and defined by caritas.” 46 War is such an act. By placing<br />

his discussion of war in the context of charity, St. Thomas is saying<br />

that it is the kind of sin which tears apart, not only the very<br />

foundations of the universal human community, that community<br />

which is the necessary support of the good life for all, but that<br />

community which is the foundation of the family of all as the<br />

children of God.<br />

St. Thomas develops his treatment of war within a virtue<br />

ethic, complimented by an ethic of office, and an ethic of law. 47<br />

But all is contained within the wider teleological vision, such<br />

that the ethic itself must be integrated into a life of peace and<br />

friendship with God, and with one another, of which the causal<br />

power is the divine energy, the Spirit of Jesus risen. 48 This peace<br />

and friendship, as I have already noted, is to be embodied in the<br />

community of the faithful, and extended to the whole human<br />

community by the opus or work of peace. This theological teleology<br />

is embodied in a political teleology, where community law<br />

serves to foster the common good, whose principal feature is<br />

peace. 49<br />

The first question in the Summa’s treatment of war is: “Is<br />

war always a sin?”. The presumption being that it is. Why it is<br />

so, is explained in terms of the violation of order, now under-<br />

45<br />

HERBERT MCCABE, “Manuals and Rule Books,” in Understanding<br />

Veritatis Splendor, ed. John Wilkins (London: SPCK, 1994) 64.<br />

46<br />

MCCABE., “Manuals,” 65.<br />

47<br />

RUSSELL, The Just War, 262-263.<br />

48 S. Th. III, q. 56.<br />

49<br />

RUSSELL, The Just War, 261.


52 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

stood as the order of creation and charity, which is the foundation<br />

of the community of all humanity. The destruction of this<br />

community is sinful, moreover, because it destroys that human<br />

reality which is meant to be a participation of the divine idea of<br />

peace. However, war may be justified under certain very restrictive<br />

conditions: the argument in summary form is that, in certain<br />

particular situations of violence arising from the sinfulness<br />

of humankind, violence may be a means to peace, and the waging<br />

of war may, indeed, be required of the prince. War, then, may<br />

be justified, if it is directed to a just cause, ultimately peace; if it<br />

is directed by right authority, and thus respects political order; if<br />

it is guided by a right intention, that is not aimed at domination<br />

or self-glorification, but at the restoration of peace. This is not<br />

merely a justification of war in the name of natural law and a<br />

theory of natural justice. This was to come later, particularly in<br />

the work of Grotius. 50 The political element, for St. Thomas, has<br />

its own proper moral orientation towards peace in this world,<br />

and so can be the appropriate matter for human action directed<br />

ultimately towards the definitive peace of the Kingdom of God.<br />

How may we judge whether the complex argument presented<br />

in outline here entailed a corruption of the tradition or not?<br />

I suggest the way to proceed would be to ask whether we, as persons<br />

committed to this tradition, and therefore also committed<br />

to a critical reception of that tradition, can follow the process<br />

through without detecting demonstrable incoherence between<br />

the positions taken and the goals of the tradition, and between<br />

the doctrine <strong>propos</strong>ed and the goals present to our consciences,<br />

which are formed by the tradition, and, in turn, form that tradition.<br />

This does not require that we agree with everything that St.<br />

Augustine or St. Thomas wrote on the subject; it is rather an<br />

invitation to reason with the tradition which they have shaped,<br />

so as to form a responsible judgment in our own circumstances.<br />

It would take much further work to prove that this is the case<br />

with regard to the JWD. However, I would argue that, at least in<br />

50 DAVID LITTLE, “Hugo Grotius and Just War Theory,” in Suche nach Frieden:<br />

Politische Ethik in der Frühen Neuzeit I., Norbert Brieskorn and Markus<br />

Riedenauer eds. (Stuttgart Berlin Cologne: Kohlhammer, 2000) 259-273.


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 53<br />

the light of the evidence which has been presented here, a definitive<br />

rejection of the doctrine is not required of one who is committed<br />

to the Catholic tradition. It is, as the moral theologians of<br />

the past would have said, a “probable” position, that is to say,<br />

there are reasonable grounds for accepting it as a norm for practice.<br />

As was indicated previously, a particularly contentious element<br />

of the JWD is the rule of proportionality; this can best be<br />

dealt with in relation to the question of the immunity of the<br />

innocent in war. St. Augustine does not deal with the question<br />

explicitly. He urged the Roman general Boniface, “And so, even<br />

in the act of waging war be careful to maintain a peaceful disposition<br />

so that by defeating your foes you can bring them to the<br />

benefits of peace… And so, let it be because of necessity rather<br />

than your own desire that you kill the enemy fighting against<br />

you.” 51 It was not sufficient that Augustine’s Christian warrior<br />

preserve an interior disposition and then simply engage in whatever<br />

degree of violence was judged to be necessary. The action<br />

needed to be tempered by the aim of bringing the adversaries to<br />

peace, which could, presumably, not be done by slaughtering the<br />

innocent wholesale. There is, at least, an intimation that the<br />

virtues, and in particular charity, would set limits to the employment<br />

of justified force.<br />

Nor does St. Thomas raise the matter, although an argument<br />

for the immunity of the innocent can be constructed from his<br />

texts. The clear assertion of the prohibition to kill the innocent,<br />

specified as noncombatants, is now accepted as a constitutive<br />

element of the tradition, but it came to be acknowledged as such<br />

through a lengthy and complex process. 52 We must read St.<br />

Thomas brief articles on war in the context of his theologicalmoral<br />

vision; the people to whom he is providing moral guidance<br />

are the same ones whom he has sought to make aware of<br />

51 Letter 189.6 (CSEL 57.135). Translation from Swift, Early Fathers,<br />

114. Cf. JOHN LANGAN, S.J. “The Elements of St. Augustine’s Just War Theory,”<br />

The Journal of Religious Ethics 12 (1984) 30.<br />

52 B. JOHNSTONE, “Noncombatant Immunity: The Origins of the Principle<br />

in Theology and Law,” <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> 24/1 (1986) 120.


54 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

the nature of God, the way of return to God through acts which<br />

are intended to be manifestations of the divinity in action,<br />

moved by charity and the gifts of the Holy Spirit, and of salvation<br />

through Jesus Christ. Such persons may be presumed to be<br />

unlikely to engage in the indiscriminate slaughter of innocents<br />

in the course of pursuing earthly, military purposes.<br />

Furthermore, the theological-eschatological context would prevent<br />

any cause of war from being considered as absolute, and<br />

thus affect the judgment as to which means are proportionate to<br />

that cause. If one loves God, even the deepest love for community<br />

and nation must be recognized as finite and of a different<br />

order of value. The same love, in its human expression, must<br />

include both friends and enemies, so that even the use of force<br />

against the latter must be contained within an effective will to<br />

bring them peace. Thus, love or charity would limit the use of<br />

force, even when this becomes necessary as the last resort in<br />

defense of self and others.<br />

A detailed examination of the important subsequent development<br />

of the tradition, the detailed exposition of the doctrine<br />

and the further development of its specific criteria by Vitoria 53<br />

and Suarez 54 would be beyond the limits of one article. Some<br />

remarks on particular points must be sufficient. Suarez (d.<br />

1617) made explicit the link between self-defense and defense of<br />

the state, (a link not found in St.Thomas). Charity in his<br />

account, still has a fundamental place, indeed, he places his<br />

analysis of the morality of war in the tract on charity, as did St.<br />

Thomas. 55 Timothy M. Renick has argued that, for Suarez, the<br />

requirements of charity, require a limit on the losses of innocents,<br />

to what is “absolutely unavoidable.” 56 Thus the applica-<br />

53<br />

HEINZ-GERHARD JUSTENHOVEN, Franciscus de Vitoria zu Krieg und<br />

Frieden (Cologne: J. P. Bachem, 1991).<br />

54<br />

RAINER SPECHT, “Francisco Suárez über den Kreig,” in Suche nach<br />

Frieden: Politische Ethik in der Frühen Neuzeit I., Norbert Brieskorn and<br />

Markus Riedenauer eds. (Stuttgart Berlin Cologne: Kohlhammer, 2000) 191-<br />

222.<br />

55<br />

FRANCISCO SUAREZ, S.J. Omnia Opera, t.12, (Paris: Vivès, 1858) tr. III De<br />

Charitate, Disputatio XIII, Sect. I, disp. XIII, p. 737.<br />

56<br />

TIMOTHY M. RENICK, “Charity Lost: The Secularization of the Principle<br />

of Double Effect in the Just-War Tradition,” The Thomist 58 (1994) 452.


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 55<br />

tion of the JWD is not only a matter of justice, and the assessment<br />

of proportionality is not to be made by a mere quantitative<br />

calculation of numbers of losses. The just war tradition, within<br />

the Catholic tradition, did not manifest any substantial development<br />

after this period, until the Second Vatican Council, with its<br />

requirement to “to undertake an evaluation of war with an<br />

entirely new attitude.” 57 The process of re-evaluation is now taking<br />

place.<br />

As the secular version of the JWD divided from the Catholic<br />

tradition, the theological-eschatological context was set aside in<br />

favour of “reason.” The link with the ethic of charity, although<br />

retained by Grotius, soon disappeared, 58 and with it any consideration<br />

of the virtues of the subject, while the assessment of the<br />

acceptable losses of non-combatants was calculated in purely<br />

“objective” terms.<br />

What would be the role and significance of the consideration<br />

of the charity in ethical decisions regarding war and the<br />

acceptable range of losses of non-combatants? Renick argues<br />

that charity would require the protagonists to do more “… than<br />

merely create a greater sum of good than evil. We must minimize<br />

the evil done, and we must be willing to sacrifice to do so,<br />

if we are meaningfully to call our actions moral.” 59 But one<br />

might ask, what is the criterion by which the minimum ought to<br />

be set? Would we want to say that, in a military action, only that<br />

number of losses may be accepted, which is strictly necessary<br />

for the success of this particular attack, and, overall, only that<br />

number of losses is acceptable which is strictly necessary for victory?<br />

But what does “necessary” mean? Does it mean what is<br />

necessary for the fitting punishment of the aggressor? Or does it<br />

mean what is required to re-establish peace, or to make the<br />

world a better place? Or does it simply mean that which is strictly<br />

necessary only to repel the aggression?<br />

The argument put forward here will be that, for Catholics, at<br />

least, and perhaps also for other Christians, the JWD has mean-<br />

57 Gaudium et Spes # 80.<br />

58 RENICK, “Charity Lost,” 455.<br />

59 RENICK, “Charity Lost,” 460-461.


56 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

ing within the tradition of their community, and these particular<br />

questions must be addressed in reference to that tradition. Thus,<br />

accepting (or rejecting) the doctrine must be understood as one<br />

element in a moral life, within a community which has committed<br />

itself to an historical purpose, of preventing war, checking<br />

violence, and fostering peace for all. Because it is this kind of<br />

life, it requires certain virtues and the elaboration of specific<br />

norms, for example those norms governing the decision to go to<br />

war and the conduct of war. Conversely, because those who<br />

inhabit the tradition live by certain virtues, they will seek to<br />

develop such norms, and engage in a continual process of<br />

review, to assure themselves that the norms express what the<br />

virtues require. General moral terms are the product of this constant<br />

interaction, engaging the intellect and the will. Sometimes,<br />

within the tradition, the intensity of the concern to protect people<br />

threatened with harms has led some exponents of the tradition<br />

to reinforce certain prohibitions with language originally<br />

proper to timeless, ontological essences. 60 I would suggest that<br />

they are not so much essences as the fruit of a long history of<br />

experience, and of a refinement of virtue, together with moral<br />

insight, which are carried forward from generation to generation<br />

through the testimony of those committed to the tradition.<br />

We relearn what murder means, by reading the narratives of the<br />

tradition. The stories evoke something of the revulsion which<br />

the past members of the tradition felt for this crime, and with<br />

that also something of the intensity of their concern for life.<br />

Thus, the present members of the tradition, accepting their testimony,<br />

absorb a similar motivation. Norms express in <strong>propos</strong>itional<br />

form the historical requirements of that concern for life.<br />

In the Christian tradition, for example, the prohibition to kill the<br />

innocent in war, or more specifically non-combatants, is such a<br />

norm. If such norms are detached from their tradition and presented<br />

in isolation, as if they were they were simply items in a<br />

general, “secular” ethic, they are deprived both of their sub-<br />

60 An example is Augustine’s notion of order, see Budzik, Doctor Pacis,<br />

386.


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 57<br />

stance and of their motivating power. Separated from the context<br />

of virtue, within which they were formed, they do not have<br />

within themselves the capacity to move people towards those<br />

goals which give them meaning, namely the limitation of war,<br />

the overcoming of violence and the fostering of peace. This is<br />

not to say that those who follow the generally accepted war convention<br />

do not possess virtue, or do not allow virtue to guide<br />

their concrete decisions. The contrary is evident from experience.<br />

61 The problem is that the necessary virtue ethic has been<br />

omitted from the standard presentations of the J.W.D.: there is<br />

no mention of charity, and justice is often treated as if it consisted<br />

in purely objective rules. 62 Hence, if the JWD is to be presented<br />

in its “traditional” form, by which is meant that form<br />

which it assumed within the Catholic tradition, then it must<br />

include an ethics of virtue.<br />

It can be argued further, that without such an ethic of virtue,<br />

attempts to assess proportionality cannot succeed. Consider the<br />

following version of the JWD norms and their application to the<br />

war against terrorism.<br />

(In reference to)… the in bello field. There, the two Just War criteria<br />

call for action that does not seek to work through the deaths of<br />

non-combatants - the principle of discrimination; and that does<br />

not foreseeably and avoidably entail such deaths, even collaterally,<br />

on a scale disproportionate to the military effect properly sought -<br />

the principle of proportionality. The initial strikes do indeed seem<br />

to be so designed and their outcome so far appears to fit the aim. 63<br />

Thus, the action was not planned to bring pressure to bear on<br />

the government to surrender, or modify its policies, by directly<br />

61 See the story of Frank Richards, WALZER, Just and Unjust Wars, 152.<br />

62 For an otherwise excellent argument, which, however omits considerations<br />

of virtue, and specifically of charity, see JOHN LANGAN, S.J. “From<br />

Ends to Means: Devising a Response to Terrorism,” America (October 8,<br />

2001), URL http://www.americapress.org/terror.htm.<br />

63 MICHAEL QUINLAN, The Tablet, 23 October, 2001, 1451. This was written<br />

at the start of the operation. As can be seen, the author leaves room for a<br />

revision in view of later evidence.


58 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

killing the inhabitants of the country (as was the case with<br />

Hamburg, Dresden, Hiroshima, Nagasaki, and, perhaps most<br />

recently, Washington in 2001) which would clearly make it<br />

morally wrong. It is claimed that the action does not “foreseeably”<br />

entail the deaths of non-combatants. But we could now<br />

add that such deaths of non-combatants could have been foreseeable<br />

in the light of recent experience of the use of similar tactics<br />

in recent wars, and in view of the type of attacks that were<br />

planned. 64<br />

Did the action “avoidably” include the loss of non-combatants?<br />

Could the losses incurred not have been avoided, at least<br />

to a greater degree than they were, by other tactics than a broad<br />

campaign of high level aerial bombardment? 65 It is estimated<br />

that the non-combatant losses were “… 1000-1300 civilian<br />

deaths due to aerial bombardment; a minimum of 3000 civilian<br />

deaths attributable to the impact of the bombing campaign and<br />

war on the nation’s refugee and famine crises.” 66 How does one<br />

calculate whether some 4000 deaths are proportionate or disproportionate<br />

to “the military effect properly sought”? No one<br />

has suggested that the due proportion should be calculated in<br />

relation to the number of civilians killed on September 11 th . As<br />

stated in the text cited, the proportion must be assessed in terms<br />

of the “military” effect <strong>propos</strong>ed. Suppose we accept that this<br />

effect was the removal of those forces and persons likely to make<br />

another, similar attack on the U.S.A., or another country. But<br />

how is it possible to determine who these people are, and how<br />

would the determination be carried out? Perhaps some intelligible<br />

form of calculation might be possible. But we are told that<br />

the war is to involve a “long hall” aimed at eliminating “terrorism.”<br />

Does this involve the removal from power of every national<br />

leader who is deemed to pose a threat to national security?<br />

How many leaders does this involve? How many countries will<br />

be attacked as Afghanistan was? How can any such assessment<br />

reasonably be made, when the end itself is so ill defined? Even<br />

64 CONETTA, “Why a Higher Rate of Civilian Bombing Casualties?” p. 2.<br />

65 CONETTA, “Strange Victory,” p. 5.<br />

66 CONETTA, “Strange Victory,” p. 4.


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 59<br />

where the object of a particular action can be precisely defined,<br />

such as the destruction of a truck depot, deemed to be “necessary”<br />

to complete the campaign, how many “collateral” deaths<br />

are proportionate to this? Would the figure be one, twenty or<br />

fifty?<br />

The apparent objectivity of such assessments of proportionality<br />

is an illusion; other factors are operating in such judgments.<br />

In a recent article on the accomplishments of President<br />

Bush, an author writing under the pseudonym “Lexington”,<br />

noted, among the many genuinely praiseworthy achievements of<br />

President Truman, that: “He had the grit to use the atomic<br />

bomb.” 67 In the judgment of the author, it apparently takes “grit”<br />

to accept as proportionate the loss of some 200,000 people.<br />

According to Michael Walzer, Truman, and most of his advisers<br />

accepted the “war is hell” doctrine, and believed that “… the<br />

Americans could do almost anything to win (and shorten the<br />

agony of war).” 68 The combination of the repudiation of the JWD<br />

doctrine, according to which war is not simply an amoral “hell”<br />

but subject to moral restraint, and the alleged “grit” that provided<br />

the inner direction and motivation of the judgment, produced<br />

the devastation of Hiroshima and Nagasaki.<br />

How then might virtue and reasonable estimation according<br />

to JWD norms yield a more responsible judgment of proportionality.<br />

This provides a crucial test for the doctrine; if no such<br />

judgment can be shown to be “reasonable” in the appropriate<br />

sense, then the doctrine is indeed both incoherent and useless.<br />

First of all, what is to count as reason? In terms of the argument<br />

developed here, this must mean, for Catholics, the tradition of<br />

reason as that has been developed within the actual historical<br />

tradition to which the Catholic community is committed.<br />

Reason therefore, must include the requirements of virtue,<br />

specifically of charity and justice. Thus reason calls for attention<br />

both to the inner requirements of the virtues, together with the<br />

danger of moral corruption their neglect will bring, and to the<br />

67 “A Leader is Born,” The Economist September 20, 2001, 3, URL<br />

http://www.Economist.com.<br />

68<br />

WALZER, Just and Unjust Wars, 264-265.


60 BRIAN V. JOHNSTONE<br />

objective requirements, that is the promotion of peace, and,<br />

where necessary, the protection of those to whom one has commitments<br />

in love and responsibilities in justice. Where one cannot<br />

protect these persons by any other means except armed<br />

force, armed force may be justifiable. In assessing the proportionality<br />

of the war itself, proportionality must be assessed not<br />

only in regard to the immediate needs of a particular nation, but<br />

also with respect to the wider interest in the peace of the whole<br />

human family. Charity would require the limitation of the use of<br />

violence to what is necessary to defend those persons under<br />

threat or attack. Vague metaphysical notions of condign punishment<br />

are not admissible, since they are not reasonably calculable.<br />

The range of action must be limited to what is needed to<br />

repel this particular aggression, and to prevent these perpetrators<br />

from further aggression. War may not be engaged in for<br />

quasi religious ends, such as making the world a better place, or<br />

making the world safe for democracy, or conquering “evil”, since<br />

such notions are simply indefinable and can never be used in<br />

assessing proportionality.<br />

Concerning the assessment of proportionality in relation to<br />

particular operations, a first requirement is to learn from experience.<br />

When it is evident that certain forms of attack simply<br />

cannot adequately be controlled, then they may not be used. The<br />

criteria must be what is strictly necessary to defend those persons<br />

who have claims in charity and justice to be protected.<br />

The tradition of reason, as explained here, means that which<br />

has been developed in the Catholic tradition. Would this mean<br />

that it applies only within that tradition? Those who hold to the<br />

Catholic tradition do not claim that they necessarily have a better<br />

grasp of the requirements of reason than do others. But they<br />

do believe that, in the light of their understanding of reason,<br />

they can responsibly offer to others what they themselves have<br />

discovered to be a way of leading a good life, even in the circumstances<br />

of what seems to be the intractable violence of our<br />

world. Accordingly, they believe they have grounds to argue their<br />

case in public, and to critique policies and tactics, which while<br />

claiming to be “reasonable, ” can sometimes by shown not to be<br />

so, using by the very criteria of reason that their proponents<br />

themselves presuppose. The major focus of critique will be the<br />

inner coherence of such <strong>propos</strong>als. It may be added here, that


THE WAR ON TERRORISM: A JUSTWAR? 61<br />

the four nations now engaged most directly in the “war against<br />

terrorism” were themselves engaged in nuclear terrorism for<br />

decades, targeting cities with their innocent inhabitants, so as to<br />

threaten other governments,<br />

The conclusion of this article is that the JWD, with all its<br />

defects, provides us with moral resources without which we<br />

would be worse off. But it is only when the objective criteria of<br />

the doctrine are combined with the subjective virtue of charity,<br />

and justice, that the assessments required by the doctrine can be<br />

made in a genuinely moral way.<br />

—————<br />

B.V. JOHNSTONE, C.SS.R<br />

The author is Ordinary Professor of Systematic Moral Theology<br />

at the Alphonsian Academy.<br />

El autor es profesor ordinario de Teología Sistemática en la<br />

Academia Alfonsiana.<br />

—————


StMor 40 (2002) 63-84<br />

DENNIS J. BILLY, C.SS.R<br />

THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP<br />

IN AELRED OF RIEVAULX’S DE SPIRITALI AMICITIA<br />

Cistercian abbot Aelred of Rievaulx’s De spiritali amicitia 1<br />

numbers among the great works of Christian literature on<br />

friendship. Composed in a monastic setting over a number of<br />

years and completed sometime before Aelred’s death in 1167, it<br />

offers a comprehensive vision of the nature of Christian friendship<br />

and some very practical advice about how such friendships<br />

should be developed and maintained over time. Using Cicero’s<br />

famous dialogue, De amicitia, 2 for his inspiration and point of<br />

departure and incorporating insights from Scripture, the fathers<br />

of the Church (especially Augustine), and his own experience,<br />

Aelred provides his readers with some very profound insights in-<br />

1 The critical Latin edition Aelred’s De spiritali amicitia [hereafter referred<br />

to as DSA] appears in CCCM 1:279-350. The English translation [hereafter<br />

referred to as SF] comes from AELRED OF RIEVAULX, Spiritual Friendship,<br />

Cistercian Fathers Series, no. 5, trans. Mary Eugenia Laker, with an Introduction<br />

by Douglass Roby (Kalamazoo, MI: Cistercian Publications,<br />

1977). The treatise has been described as “…probably the most popular of all<br />

the early Cistercian texts.” See BERNARD MCGINN, JOHN MEYENDORFF, and JEAN<br />

LECLERCQ, eds., Christian Spirituality I: Origins to the Twelfth Century (New<br />

York: Crossroad, 1985), 214. For the life of Aelred, see AELRED SQUIRE, Aelred<br />

of Rievaulx: A Study, Cistercian Studies, no. 50 (Kalamazoo, MI: Cistercian<br />

Publications, 1981). For critical studies of DSA, see CCCM 1: xii. For a concise<br />

summary of his spirituality and the major theological influences on his<br />

life, see JEAN LECLERCQ, FRANÇOIS VANDENBROUCKE, and LOUIS BOUYER, A History<br />

of Christian Spirituality, vol. 2, trans. The Benedictines of Holme Eden<br />

Abbey (New York: The Seabury Press, 1968), 205-8. See also MARCEL VILLER<br />

et al., eds., Dictionnaire de spiritualité, ascétique et mystique, doctrine et histoire<br />

(Paris, Beauchesne, 1934-), s. v. “Aelred,” by A. Le Bail.<br />

2 CICERO, De senectute, De amicitia, De divinatione, The Loeb Classical<br />

Library (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1923; reprint ed. 1979),<br />

100-211.<br />

63


64 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

to the healing role of friendship in a person’s journey through<br />

life. 3<br />

Literary Context: The Uses of ‘Dialogue’<br />

Aelred’s choice of the dialogue form has great significance<br />

for the content of his teaching. Deeply rooted in the Western<br />

philosophical tradition, the dialogue was a widely accepted<br />

means of learned discourse in classical civilization, one that was<br />

eventually taken up by a wide spectrum of interested Christian<br />

authors. 4 In selecting the dialogue form, Aelred embraces this<br />

3 For the sources of the De spiritali amicitia, see DOUGLASS ROBY,<br />

“Sources of the Spiritual Friendship,” in SF, 29-35. For the centrality of Scripture<br />

in Aelred’s spirituality, see ANDRÉ VAUCHEZ, The Spirituality of the Medieval<br />

West: The Eighth to the Twelfth Century, trans. Colette Friedlander, Cistercian<br />

Studies, 145(Kalamazoo, MI: Cistercian Publications, 1993), 157-58.<br />

In addition to Church fathers such as Ambrose, Augustine, and Jerome, later<br />

monastic authors such as Bernard of Clairvaux, sometimes called “the last of<br />

the fathers,” must also be taken into account. According to ÉTIENNE GILSON:<br />

“Aelred of Rievaulx, although belonging to a later generation, still directly depends<br />

upon St. Bernard. Living wholly within the twelfth century, he is not<br />

divided from the latter by any considerable interval; and although various<br />

doctrinal influences interposed between them, accentuated, no doubt, by<br />

their individual differences, he remains nevertheless a qualified interpreter of<br />

the master whose presence in his writings may be constantly felt.” See The<br />

Mystical Theology of St. Bernard, trans. A. H. C. Downes (Kalamazoo, MI: Cistercian<br />

Publications, 1990), 6. Aelred, in fact, was often referred to as “the<br />

English Bernard.” See GUERRINO PELLICCIA and GIANCARLO ROCCA, eds.<br />

Dizionario degli istituti di perfezione (Rome: Edizioni Paolini, 1962-), s. v.<br />

“Aelredo,” by H. TRIBOUT DE MOREMBERT According to BERNARD MCGINN,<br />

“[t]he appeal to experience that formed the leitmotif of all Christian mysticism<br />

seems somehow more accessible in Aelred’s personal and at times<br />

painful expressions of how he actually “felt” his friendships as a part of the<br />

quest for God than it may be in Bernard’s lush evocations of male-female<br />

erotic symbolism of the encounter with God.” See The Presence of God: A History<br />

of Western Christian Mysticism, vol. 2, The Growth of Mysticism: From<br />

Gregory the Great to the Twelfth Century (London: SCM Press, 1994), 323.<br />

4 “The monks prefer to cultivate genres like the letter, the dialogue, and<br />

history in all its short forms from short chronicles and accounts of individual<br />

events to long annals.” See JEAN LECLERCQ, The Love of Learning and the


THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP 65<br />

venerable tradition of philosophical and theological expression.<br />

He casts his teaching in this literary genre because he desires a<br />

flexible way of expressing his very particular concerns about the<br />

nature of human relationships. Those concerns are closely connected<br />

with what Jean Leclercq terms “monastic theology,” a<br />

broad, descriptive phrase used to distinguish the practical, experiential,<br />

and symbolic interests of the cloister setting from the<br />

more theoretical, abstract, and dialectical interests of the<br />

scholastic aula. 5 The two approaches differ in fundamental<br />

ways. Monastic theology values the epistemological role of love<br />

and looks upon learning as a means to holiness. Scholastic theology,<br />

in turn, while having nothing against the pursuit of holiness,<br />

sees it as only ancillary to the specific goal of theology itself,<br />

which is to clarify the objective content of the faith through<br />

a critical use of dialectical reasoning. 6 In the twelfth century, the<br />

dialogue form was used very creatively and to great benefit by<br />

monastic and scholastic authors alike. 7<br />

Aelred’s interests in using the dialogue form coincide closely<br />

with his practical interest as a monastic author in showing his<br />

readers how friendship can heal them and draw them closer to<br />

Christ. A close examination of his treatise shows that he departs<br />

from the general characteristics of monastic theology only in his<br />

general hesitancy to incorporate allegorical interpretations into<br />

his text. Since he employs such interpretations in many of his<br />

Desire for God, trans. Catharine Misrahi (New York: Fordham University<br />

Press, 1982), 153-54. For the dialogue as a literary form, see IRWIN EDMAN,<br />

ed., “Introduction” in The Works of Plato (New York: Tudor Publishing Company,<br />

1931), xxiii-xxvi.<br />

5 LECLERCQ, The Love of Learning, 191-235.<br />

6 For a comparison of monastic and scholastic theology, see B. P. GAYBBA,<br />

Aspects of the History of Theology: 12 th -14 th Centuries (Pretoria: University of<br />

South Africa, 1988), 52-57. See also JEAN LECLERCQ, “Monastic and Scholastic<br />

Theology in the Reformers of the Fourteenth to Sixteenth Century,” in<br />

From Cloister to Classroom: Monastic and Scholastic Approaches to Truth, ed.<br />

E. Rozanne Elder, The Spirituality of Western Christendom III (Kalamazoo,<br />

MI: Cistercian Publications, 1986), 178-201, esp. 194.<br />

7 Compare, for example, DSA with PETER ABELARD’S Dialogus inter<br />

philosophum, iudaeum et christianum, ed. R. Thomas (Stuttgart-Bad-<br />

Cannstatt: Friedrich Frommann, 1970).


66 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

other works, he restrains himself probably because of the philosophical<br />

nature of the work by Cicero used for his point of departure.<br />

8 Contrary to what some might claim, his reliance on a<br />

secular source like Cicero is not out of step with general monastic<br />

sensitivities of his day. In most monastic circles, secular<br />

knowledge had little value in itself and was considered useful<br />

only to the extent that it helped the monk in his spiritual journey.<br />

9 Aelred borrows so heavily from Cicero precisely because he<br />

finds the pagan orator and philosopher genuinely useful for his<br />

theological goals. Rather than merely imitating Cicero, however,<br />

Aelred “baptizes” him by immersing him in the life-giving waters<br />

of Scripture and the Fathers. 10<br />

Through the dialogue form, Aelred is able to give his readers<br />

a glimpse of a conversation among close friends in a monastic<br />

setting. The physical location of the conversations – the monastic<br />

cloister – should not be downplayed. Aelred writes with a<br />

monastic (and specifically Cistercian) audience in mind, but<br />

seems to be aware that it might eventually have a wider circulation.<br />

11 Although the dialogue provides little by way of description,<br />

one understands immediately when reading it that those<br />

engaged in the dialogue are thoroughly immersed in such an environment.<br />

Aelred conveys this sense through carefully placed<br />

references to monastic practice and community life that, in his<br />

day, would make sense only if the conversations were taking<br />

place within the cloister. 12 In the dialogue, simplicity of speech,<br />

8 In DSA, Aelred employs the allegorical interpretation of Scripture<br />

only in his treatment of Sg 1:1 [DSA 2:21-27; CCCM 1:306-8 (155-203); SF<br />

75-77]. He uses it extensively, however, in De Jesu puero duodenni (CCCM<br />

1:245-78). See ROBY, “Sources of the Spiritual Friendship,” 33.<br />

9 For the legitimate uses of reason and secular knowledge in monastic<br />

theology, see GAYBBA, Aspects of the Medieval History of Theology, 47-52.<br />

10 DSA “…gives the impression of a thoroughly Augustinian structure,<br />

built on the foundation provided by Cicero. The doctrine is expressed in<br />

scriptural and patristic terms but is no more a florilegium of the Fathers<br />

than it is a simple copy of Cicero.” See ROBY, “Sources of the Spiritual<br />

Friendship,” 31.<br />

11 DSA 2:7 [CCCM 1:303(50-53); SF 71].<br />

12 For the place of DSA in the tradition of monastic friendship, see<br />

DOUGLASS, “Aelred in the Tradition of Monastic Friendship,” in SF 36-41.


THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP 67<br />

good humor, purity of heart, and a genuine desire to draw closer<br />

to Christ give the reader a sense that the monastic ideal has<br />

been enfleshed in the lives of real people.<br />

The dialogue’s erratic chronological framework, moreover,<br />

conveys the strong impression that time itself is of only relative<br />

importance to the characters. Aelred and his friends are keenly<br />

aware of the small amount of time they have at their disposal for<br />

talking about friendship, but do not seem particularly concerned<br />

about it. Shaped by a Rule that seeks to sanctify the day through<br />

a strict regimen of prayer, spiritual reading, and manual labor,<br />

they recognize time itself as a gift from God to be used primarily<br />

for giving glory to him. This attitude frees them from pressures<br />

of an exclusively utilitarian view of time based on output<br />

and production. As a result, they are not overly concerned if<br />

their conversation is broken off in mid-course by the demands<br />

of the Rule or community duties. What has been dropped can be<br />

taken up again as the need arises. In their eyes, the span of years<br />

between books one and two and of a single day between books<br />

two and three are of little consequence. What matters is not if<br />

they finish what they are doing, but if they are using their time<br />

in a way that give honor and glory to God. 13<br />

Finally, Aelred uses the dialogue form to introduce the reader<br />

to a variety of relationships both in and out of time. He makes<br />

this clear in the very first sentence of Book One when he says to<br />

Ivo, “Here we are, you and I, and I hope a third, Christ, is in our<br />

midst.” 14 Whether consciously averted to or not, Christ is the in-<br />

13 Breaks in time within the DSA occur between Books One and Two (a<br />

number of years) and between Books Two and Three (a single day). A break<br />

for an unspecified amount of time also occurs between DSA 2:7 and 2:8 (CC-<br />

CM 1:303(53-54); SF 71). Although annoyance may be expressed at the need<br />

of having to postpone their conversation for a time (e.g, DSA 1:71, 2:72; CCM<br />

1:301(413-15), 2:315-16(470-73); SF 66, 87, Aelred and his dialogue partners<br />

never openly complain about the Rule and what it requires of them. The<br />

monastic attitude toward time is closely linked to the “devotion to heaven,”<br />

which manifested itself in a life of “busy leisure” (negotiosissimum otium)<br />

that steered clear of the dual perils of idleness (otiositas) and business<br />

(negotium). The business of the monk, one might say, was to live a life of holy<br />

leisure. See LECLERCQ, The Love of Learning, 53-70, esp. 67.<br />

14 DSA 1:1 [CCCM 1:289(4-5); SF 51].


68 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

visible partner in all genuine Christian friendships. All such relationships<br />

flow from, rest in, and tend toward Christ, who provides<br />

the model of genuine spiritual friendship and helps one to<br />

attain it. Aelred also gently reminds his readers that true friendships<br />

do not end but are merely changed by death. Such is what<br />

happens to Aelred and Ivo, the interlocutors of the Book One.<br />

Years later, when Ivo has long been dead, Aelred resumes his discussion<br />

of spiritual friendship and reveals the depth of their<br />

bond:<br />

Indeed, the fond memory of my beloved Ivo, yes, his constant love<br />

and affection are, in fact, always so fresh to my mind, that, though<br />

he has gone from this life in body, yet to my spirit he seems never<br />

to have died at all. For there he is ever with me, there his pious<br />

countenance inspires me, there his charming eyes smile upon me,<br />

there his happy words have such relish for me, that either I seem<br />

to have gone to a better land with him or he seems still to be<br />

dwelling with me here on earth. 15<br />

Aelred’s friendship with Ivo deepens rather than weakens with<br />

death. The reason for this is that the latter’s drawing closer to<br />

Christ through death has had some residual effects on the former.<br />

Aelred, in turn, carries his deep friendship with Ivo into his<br />

daily activities, and especially into the discussion on spiritual<br />

friendship that he takes up again with Walter and Gratian in<br />

Books Two and Three.<br />

This sense of the extended reach of friendship has important<br />

ramifications for Aelred’s readers; they too are silent, invisible<br />

partners in the discussion that is taking place. As mentioned earlier,<br />

Aelred uses the dialogue form to give his readers a glimpse<br />

of a conversation between close friends in a monastic setting. By<br />

allowing them to become quiet observers in this conversation,<br />

he tries to awaken in them the hope that this invisible bond will<br />

one day reap visible fruit. This reader/text dynamic is already<br />

hinted at near the beginning of Book Two when, before setting<br />

out to discuss related concerns on the topic of spiritual friend-<br />

15 DSA 2:5 [CCCM 1:303(30-37); SF 70].


THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP 69<br />

ship, Aelred asks Walter to read the paper containing Aelred’s<br />

and Ivo’s earlier discussion on its nature and origins. 16 Just as<br />

Walter befriends Ivo through the act of reading, so too the readers<br />

of De spiritali amicitia get to know those conversing throughout<br />

its pages. This bond with the characters of the text should<br />

awaken in readers a desire to taste the sweet fruit of spiritual<br />

friendship in their own lives and to be more keenly attuned to<br />

the invisible presence of Christ in their midst.<br />

Theological Context: Creation, Fall, Redemption<br />

In addition to the above literary context, Aelred provides<br />

some important theological parameters for understanding his<br />

teaching on the healing role of friendship. These parameters<br />

concern the Christian doctrines of creation, humanity’s fall, and<br />

redemption in Christ.<br />

1. Creation. In his discussion with Ivo in Book One about the<br />

nature and origin of friendship, Aelred states that God “…has<br />

willed that peace encompass all his creatures and society unite<br />

them.” 17 Every level of creation reveals some trace or vestige of<br />

that unity. A look at inanimate creation, for example, reveals<br />

that the earth produces not a single stone, but many, while<br />

forests contain not a single tree of a single kind, but a great number<br />

of different species. For Aelred, such variety reveals that a<br />

certain love of companionship has been imprinted into the very<br />

nature of the inanimate world. 18 Much the same can be said for<br />

animate life. Although they are irrational, by nature, a look at<br />

the way animals run, play, and enjoy each other’s company almost<br />

makes one want to believe that they are acting with reason.<br />

Their enjoyment of one another’s company is another sign that<br />

the love for companionship has been implanted in their natures.<br />

19 Even immaterial beings such as angels delight in each<br />

16 DSA 2:7-8 [CCCM 1:303(50-59); SF 71].<br />

17 DSA 1:53 [CCCM 1:298(300-2); SF 62].<br />

18 DSA 1:54 [CCCM 1:298(305-10); SF 62].<br />

19 DSA 1:54-55 [CCCM 1:298(310-18); SF 62-63].


70 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

other’s company. God created not one but many of them, thus<br />

giving them the opportunity to live together in charity through a<br />

union of will and desire. 20 Finally, within this hierarchical ordering<br />

of creation, God united the animal and spiritual realms<br />

in the figure of Adam. Because God deemed that it was not good<br />

for man to be alone, however, a helper was made for him, one<br />

like unto himself. In Aelred’s mind, “It was from no similar, nor<br />

even from the same, material that divine Might formed this help<br />

mate, but as a clearer inspiration to charity and friendship he<br />

produced the woman from the very substance of the man.” 21<br />

Aelred goes on with a beautiful description of the equality of the<br />

sexes and the need for friendship as the basis of their existence<br />

and mutual relationship: “How beautiful it is that the second human<br />

being was taken from the side of the first, so that nature<br />

might teach that human beings are equal and, as it were, collateral,<br />

and that there is in human affairs neither a superior nor an<br />

inferior, a characteristic of true friendship.” 22 Aelred’s point in all<br />

of this is that nature was created in such a way that, from the<br />

very beginning, the desire for friendship and charity was implanted<br />

in the human heart.<br />

2. The Fall. Up until this point, Aelred’s description of the<br />

orientation towards companionship and society implanted in<br />

creation by the divine will and the eternal reason does not take<br />

into full account the reality of sin. When the fall of Adam occurs,<br />

however, the original harmony within nature and in the human<br />

heart is radically disrupted. Since Aelred is primarily interested<br />

in spiritual friendship, he focuses on the repercussions of this<br />

fall for humanity. The main effect, for Aelred, has to do with a<br />

fundamental dissonance that enters into the relationship between<br />

charity and friendship. Prior to the sin of Adam, charity<br />

and friendship are coextensive; after it, however, they grow<br />

apart:<br />

…after the fall of the first man, when with the cooling of charity<br />

concupiscence made secret inroads and caused private good to<br />

20 DSA 1:56 [CCCM 1:298(318-24); SF 63].<br />

21 DSA 1:57 [CCCM 1:298(327-30); SF 63].<br />

22 DSA 1:57 [CCCM 1:298-99(330-33); SF 63].


THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP 71<br />

take precedence over the common weal, it corrupted the splendor<br />

of friendship and charity through avarice and envy, introducing<br />

contentions, emulations, hates and suspicions because the morals<br />

of men had been corrupted. From that time the good distinguished<br />

between charity and friendship, observing that love ought to be extended<br />

even to the hostile and perverse, while no union of will and<br />

ideas can exist between the good and wicked. And so friendship<br />

which, like charity, was first preserved among all by all, remained<br />

according to the natural law among the few good. 23<br />

This passage identifies the fall of Adam as the primary cause for<br />

disruption between charity and friendship. Prior to the fall, the<br />

intimate union between nature and grace allowed friendship<br />

and charity to exist in close relationship with one another and to<br />

share a certain “splendor.” After the fall, however, this “splendor”<br />

was corrupted: friendship contracted in its extension and<br />

was limited to a very few; charity, in turn, remained limited in<br />

scope, but was possible only under the influence of grace. Elsewhere<br />

in the treatise, Aelred describes the relationship between<br />

charity and friendship in this manner: “…divine authority approves<br />

that more are to be received into the bosom of charity<br />

than into the embrace of friendship. For we are compelled by<br />

the law of charity to receive in the embrace of love not only our<br />

friends but also our enemies. But only those do we call friends<br />

to whom we can fearlessly entrust our heart and all its secrets;<br />

those, too, who, in turn, are bound to us by the same law of faith<br />

and security.” 24 For Aelred, the fall is also responsible for the different<br />

types of friendship in the world today. Since reason was<br />

not completely corrupted through the fall, the wicked experience<br />

an inclination toward companionship and society that of-<br />

23 DSA 1:58-59 [CCCM 1.299(336-47); SF 63-64].<br />

24 DSA 1.32 [CCCM 1:294(183-89); SF 58]. Aelred develops his general<br />

theory of love in De speculo caritatis (CCCM 1:3-161. For an analysis of this<br />

work, see AMÉDÉE HALLIER, The Theology of Aelred of Rievaulx: An Experiential<br />

Theology, Cistercian Studies, no. 2 (Spencer, MA: Cistercian Publications,<br />

1969). For a general treatment of Aelred’s position on friendship, see<br />

DOUGLASS, “The Doctrine of Spiritual Friendship,” in SF, 15-35. See also<br />

SQUIRE, Aelred of Rievaulx: A Study, 98-111. `


72 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

ten resembles friendship. After the fall, therefore, it is important<br />

to distinguish between true friendship and other relationships<br />

“of some slight resemblance.” 25 Aelred’s discussion of the differences<br />

between “carnal” and “spiritual” friendship presupposes<br />

and springs from this underlying theological premise. 26<br />

3. Redemption. Aelred’s doctrine of the fall helps one to understand<br />

how the disharmony between charity and friendship<br />

crept into human affairs. Aelred recognizes its importance in<br />

this regard, but refuses to dwell on it. His theology of friendship<br />

is eminently positive, one that flows from the love of God who,<br />

through the death of Christ, enables a person once again to enjoy<br />

the friendship of God. In Aelred’s mind, “Christ himself set<br />

up a definite goal for friendship when he said: ‘Greater love than<br />

this no man hath, than a man lay down his life for his friends.’” 27<br />

Through his redemptive suffering, a healing process begins that<br />

will eventually make them co-extensive. In Jesus, charity and<br />

friendship once again exist in close harmony. Through him,<br />

original sin is overcome and its effects will eventually be completely<br />

wiped out:<br />

And so in friendship are joined honor and charm, truth and joy,<br />

sweetness and good-will, affection and action. And all these take<br />

their beginning from Christ, advance through Christ, and are perfected<br />

in Christ. Therefore, not too steep or unnatural does the ascent<br />

appear from Christ, as the inspiration of the love by which we<br />

love our friend, to Christ giving himself to us as our Friend for us<br />

to love, so that charm may follow upon charm, sweetness upon<br />

sweetness and affection upon affection. And thus, friend cleaving<br />

to friend in the spirit of Christ, is made with Christ but one heart<br />

and one soul, and so mounting aloft through degrees of love to<br />

friendship with Christ, he is made one spirit with him in one kiss.<br />

Aspiring to this kiss the saintly soul cries out: ‘Let him kiss me with<br />

the kiss of his mouth.’ 28<br />

25 DSA 1:60 [CCCM 1:299(358-59); SF 64].<br />

26 See DSA 1:39-49 [CCCM 1:295-97(220-79); SF 59-61].<br />

27 DSA 2:33 [CCCM 1:309(238-39); SF 78].<br />

28 DSA 2:20-21 [CCCM 1:306(143-55); SF 74-75].


Friendship, for Aelred, is the “medicine of life,” because it ultimately<br />

brings a person into relationship with Christ, who is the<br />

Way, the Truth, and the Life” (Jn 14:6). 29 It plays a healing, even<br />

elevating role in the human sojourn. By entering into a true<br />

“spiritual” (as opposed to “carnal”) friendship with another human<br />

being, a person begins a process that will eventually enable<br />

him or her to share in the friendship of Christ. For Aelred,<br />

“…friendship is a stage bordering upon that perfection which<br />

consists in the love and knowledge of God, so that man from being<br />

a friend of his fellowman becomes the friend of God, according<br />

to the words of the Savior in the Gospel: ‘I will not now<br />

call you servants, but my friends.’” 30<br />

Applications<br />

THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP 73<br />

This general theological framework of creation, fall, and redemption<br />

helps one to interpret some of Aelred’s better-known<br />

statements on spiritual friendship. Aelred himself insists that<br />

“…friendship bears fruit in this life and in the next.” 31 The<br />

phrase, “in this life,” implies that friends receive concrete benefits<br />

in the present even though they are still weighed down by the<br />

effects of original sin. The phrase, “in the next,” points to the<br />

time when, on account of Christ’s redemption, they are completely<br />

free from the shackles of concupiscence and live in close<br />

intimate union with God and the communion of saints. By keeping<br />

the distinction between the fruits of friendship clear in one’s<br />

mind, the reader is better able to understand the significance of<br />

Aelred’s teaching on the meaning of the goodness, the three kisses,<br />

and the formation of spiritual friendships.<br />

29 The phrase “A faithful friend is the medicine of life” (Amicus fidelis<br />

medicamentum vitae est) comes from Sir 6:16. See Biblica sacra iuxta vulgatam<br />

versionem ed. Robertus Weber, vol. 2 (Stutgart: Wüettenbergische<br />

Bibelanstalt, 1969), 1036. Aelred refers to it in DSA 2:12; 3: 74, 97[CCCM<br />

1:304(82-83), 332(532), 339(750); SF 72,109,117].<br />

30 DSA 2:14 [CCCM 1:305(104-8);; SF 73].<br />

31 DSA 2:9 [CCCM 1:304(64-65); SF 71].


74 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

Application One: The Meaning of ‘Goodness’<br />

It may be surprising to learn that, for Aelred, friendship<br />

“…can begin among the good, progress among the better, and be<br />

consummated among the perfect.” 32 If this is so, one may wonder<br />

if anyone can be good in a world where the effects of original<br />

sin influence human activity so strongly. Aelred, however,<br />

draws a strong distinction between goodness as it exists in God<br />

and in one who is journeying to God. God, in Aelred’s mind, is<br />

“…supremely powerful and supremely good, is sufficient good<br />

unto himself, since his good, his joy, his glory, his happiness, is<br />

himself.” 33 In God, there is no distinction between good, better,<br />

and best. His goodness is his perfection – and vice versa. Man,<br />

by way of contrast, is on a journey that hopefully involves a<br />

movement along a distinct series of grades of spiritual and<br />

moral perfection.<br />

When Aelred says that spiritual friendship begins with the<br />

good, he does not mean that two people must be good in the<br />

same way that God is good. Nor does he mean that they are good<br />

in the same sense as those who have already passed through<br />

death and experience God in an immediate way in the beatific<br />

vision. Nor does he mean that they have no experience of concupiscence<br />

in their lives as a result of the effects of original sin.<br />

He merely intends to say that spiritual friendships in this life are<br />

forged by those who struggle to move further along (as opposed<br />

to away from) the journey of eventual intimacy with God. In answer<br />

to a question by Gratian about friendship among those<br />

who are not good, Aelred says:<br />

I am not cutting “good” so finely as do some who call no one<br />

“good” unless he is lacking no whit in perfection. We call a man<br />

“good” who, according to the limits of our mortality, “living soberly<br />

and justly and godly in this world,” is resolved neither to ask others<br />

to do wrong nor to do wrong himself at another’s request.<br />

32 DSA 2:38 [CCCM 1:309(252-53); SF 78-79].<br />

33 DSA 1:51 [CCCM 1:297(290-91); SF 62].


THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP 75<br />

Among such, indeed, we have no doubt that friendship can spring<br />

up and that by such it can be perfected. 34<br />

As far as human beings are concerned, “goodness,” for Aelred,<br />

resides in the firm resolution not to participate in wrongdoing of<br />

any kind. It does not mean that a person is perfect or that he or<br />

she has never committed sin or will not do so in the future. A<br />

“good person,” for Aelred, is someone who intends not to sin and<br />

who takes appropriate measures to keep himself or herself from<br />

being overcome by unruly passions.<br />

Friendships among “good persons” of this type are not rare<br />

in this life. As Aelred reminds his readers:<br />

… the Christian ought not to despair of acquiring any virtue since<br />

daily the divine voice from the Gospel re-echoes: “Ask and you<br />

shall receive….” It is no wonder, then, that pursuers of true virtue<br />

were rare among the pagans since they did not know the Lord, the<br />

Dispenser of virtue, of whom it is written: “The Lord of hosts, he<br />

is the King of glory.” Indeed, through faith in him they were prepared<br />

to die for one another – I do not say three or four, but I offer<br />

you thousands of pairs of friends – although the ancients declared<br />

or imagined the devotion of Pylades and Orestes a great<br />

marvel. Were they not, according to the definition of Tullius,<br />

strong in the virtue of true friendship, of whom it is written: “And<br />

the multitude of believers had but one heart and one soul; neither<br />

did anyone say that aught was his own, but all things were common<br />

unto them?” 35<br />

The highest expression of Christian love is to lay down one’s life<br />

for one’s friend. Those who did so, the thousands of pairs mentioned<br />

by Aelred in the above passage, were weak human beings<br />

who, like everyone else in this fallen world, were hounded by<br />

doubts and temptations of various kinds. To enter into a spiritual<br />

friendship, one needs to be good – not perfect. It is the<br />

34 DSA 2:43 [CCCM 1:310(283-89); SF 80].<br />

35 DSA 1:27-28 [CCCM 1:293-94(154-66); SF 56-57]. For the theology of<br />

the kiss in monastic theology, see LECLERCQ, The Love of Learning, 226-28.


76 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

friendship itself which, rooted in Christ’s grace, leads a person<br />

along the way of purgation, illumination, and ultimate union<br />

with God.<br />

Application Two: The Three Kisses<br />

Aelred uses the metaphor of a kiss to point out what the<br />

process of growth in friendship precisely entails: “…in a kiss two<br />

breaths meet, and are mingled, and are united. As a result, a certain<br />

sweetness of mind is born, which rouses and binds together<br />

the affection of those who embrace.” 36 He extends the<br />

metaphor to demonstrate the different types of friendship that<br />

can be forged: “There is, then, a corporeal kiss, a spiritual kiss,<br />

and an intellectual kiss. The corporeal kiss is made by the impression<br />

of the lips; the spiritual kiss by the union of spirits; the<br />

intellectual kiss through the Spirit of God, by the infusion of<br />

grace.” 37<br />

Although the carnal kiss is supposed to be offered or received<br />

for definite and worthy reasons (e.g., as a sign of reconciliation<br />

or a mark of peace), Aelred points out that it can be<br />

misused for perverse and lustful ends. 38 The spiritual kiss, by<br />

way of contrast, is “…the kiss of friends who are bound by one<br />

law of friendship; for it is not made by contact with the mouth<br />

but by the affection of the heart.” 39 According to Aelred, Christ<br />

is already present in this friendship. His presence is not directly<br />

experienced, however, but mediated through another person: “I<br />

would call this the kiss of Christ, yet he himself does not offer it<br />

from his own mouth, but from the mouth of another, breathing<br />

upon his lovers that most sacred affection so that there seems to<br />

them to be, as it were, one spirit in many bodies.” 40 As the soul<br />

becomes accustomed to this kind of friendship, it tastes the<br />

sweetness that comes from Christ and eventually yearns for<br />

36 DSA 2:23 [CCCM 1:307(162-65); SF 75].<br />

37 DSA 2:24 [CCCM 1:307(165-68); SF 76].<br />

38 DSA 2:25 [CCCM 1:307(177-85); SF 76].<br />

39 DSA 2:26 [CCCM 1:307(185-87); SF 76].<br />

40 DSA 2:26 [CCCM 1:307-8(190-94); SF 76].


something more than a mediated encounter and sighs for direct<br />

contact with Christ through intellectual “kiss of grace.” 41 When<br />

this happens, “…all earthly affections have been tempered, and<br />

all thoughts and desires which savor of the world have been quieted,<br />

the soul takes delight in the kiss of Christ alone and rests<br />

in his embrace, exulting and exclaiming: ‘His left hand is under<br />

my head and his right hand shall embrace me.’” 42<br />

Friendship, for Aelred, is the “medicine of life” because it<br />

moves two people along this wide spectrum of relationships and<br />

enables them eventually to meet Christ face to face. It calms<br />

their disordered passions, enables their spirits to mingle, and<br />

eventually brings them to an intimate relationship with the Spirit<br />

of Christ. All of this is possible because of Christ’s redemptive<br />

suffering. By laying down his life for his friends, Jesus gives human<br />

beings the chance once again to become the friends of God.<br />

Because of Christ, charity and friendship are slowly coming<br />

back into harmony with one another. If they presently appear to<br />

still be in dissonance with each other, it is simply because the<br />

full effects of Christ’s redemption are not yet manifest. When<br />

they become so, “… this friendship, to which here we admit but<br />

few, will be outpoured upon all and by all outpoured upon God,<br />

and God shall be all in all.” 43<br />

Application Three: Practical Advice<br />

THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP 77<br />

Aelred’s interest in providing concrete measures to help others<br />

establish and develop strong friendships in Christ stems<br />

from his consciousness of the great caution and care that needs<br />

to be taken in an imperfect world still under the sway of the effects<br />

of Adam’s fall. Even though he firmly believes in the victory<br />

won for humanity by Christ suffering and death, he is still<br />

very conscious of the struggle with temptation and the tendency<br />

to sin that even good people must deal with in their daily lives.<br />

41 DSA 2:27 [CCCM 1:308(198); SF 77].<br />

42 DSA 2:27 [CCCM 1:308(199-203); SF 77].<br />

43 DSA 3:134 [CCCM 1:350(1116-18); SF 132].


78 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

Indeed, there would be no need for him to give such advice if the<br />

rages of concupiscence no longer had any hold over the human<br />

heart.<br />

It is for this reason that Aelred offers some very concrete and<br />

practical advice to his readers about forming spiritual friendships.<br />

In his mind, there are “…four stages by which one climbs<br />

to the perfection of friendship: the first is selection, the second<br />

probation, the third admission, and the fourth perfect harmony<br />

in matters human and divine with charity and benevolence.” 44 In<br />

the selection process, Aelred instructs his readers of the types of<br />

person who should (and should not) be chosen for friendship.<br />

He advises them to avoid strong ties with those who have a difficult<br />

time restraining the passions that lead a person to quarreling,<br />

anger, fickleness, suspicion, and talkativeness. 45 Friendships<br />

with those who can give love and affection, security and<br />

happiness, by way of contrast, should be actively pursued. 46 If<br />

one has already begun a friendship with someone who cannot<br />

withstand these tendencies, he reminds his readers that they are<br />

still bound by the law of charity and should unstitch the bond<br />

“little by little” rather than breaking it off immediately. 47 As far<br />

as the period of probation is concerned, Aelred says that a potential<br />

friend should be given a trial period where the qualities<br />

of loyalty, right intention, discretion, and patience are tested. 48<br />

Once these qualities have been carefully examined in a potential<br />

friend, that person can be admitted to be one’s closest confident,<br />

where a union of spirits will eventually take place and where one<br />

will discover “…how good and how pleasant it is for brethren to<br />

dwell together in unity.” 49 Aelred himself provides his reader<br />

with an example from his own experience of the gradual process<br />

whereby a person is admitted into the intimacy of spiritual<br />

friendship: “All this in a most wondrous way had bound him to<br />

me by the most intimate bounds, and so had brought him into<br />

44 DSA 3:8 [CCCM 1:319(64-68); SF 93].<br />

45 DSA 3:55 [CCCM 1:328(379-82); SF 104].<br />

46 DSA 3:51 [CCCM 1:327(346-47); SF 103].<br />

47 DSA 3:41 [CCCM 1:325(281-85); SF 101].<br />

48 DSA 3:61 [CCCM 1:329(418-19); SF 105].<br />

49 DSA 3:131[CCCM 1:349(1090-91); SF 131].


my affection, that from an inferior I made him my companion,<br />

from a companion a friend, from a friend my most cherished of<br />

friends.” 50<br />

The need for all of this practical advice arises out of Aelred’s<br />

keen awareness of the various pitfalls before anyone who seeks<br />

to enter into a friendship with another person that is rooted in<br />

Christ. It is also why Book Three (where this practical advice occurs)<br />

is the longest part of the treatise and generally the most<br />

widely read.<br />

Observations<br />

THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP 79<br />

Given the above literary and theological contexts, as well as<br />

accompanying applications to Aelred’s understanding of goodness,<br />

the kiss of friendship, and the need for practical advice<br />

about entering into and sustaining such a bond, a number of observations<br />

are in order.<br />

1. To begin with, Aelred’s teaching on friendship and his lively<br />

conversation with Ivo, Walter, and Gratian encourage the<br />

reader to examine the quality of his or her own personal relationships.<br />

Aelred adapts the dialogue form to suit his practical,<br />

experiential concerns for entering into the friendship of Christ.<br />

He does so by presenting his readers with a number of possibilities<br />

regarding the range of spiritual friendships available to<br />

them and by urging them, at least implicitly, to be aware of their<br />

own potential for entering into and maintaining such relationships.<br />

By engaging his own active imagination and helping the<br />

other characters of dialogue to do the same, Aelred raises questions,<br />

makes suggestions, and opens possibilities that may inspire<br />

the reader to embark on a similar process of reflection.<br />

2. When going through the treatise, one gets the strong sense<br />

that the written conversation reflects a conversation going on in<br />

Aelred’s mind which, in turn, has its roots in actual conversations<br />

with his friends. Aelred’s dialogue, in other words, is the<br />

fruit not only of his real-life friendships with Ivo, Walter, and<br />

50 DSA 3:122 [CCCM 1:346(1001-4); SF 127].


80 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

Gratian, but also of his reflection on the meaning of spiritual<br />

friendship with them in his mind. As such, it reminds readers<br />

that their thought processes are influenced by their relationships<br />

with others – and greatly depend on them. When going<br />

through the treatise, they should try to be aware as much as possible<br />

of the various influences on their own thought processes.<br />

The origin of the various questions and concerns that help to<br />

shape one’s convictions should be very helpful in this respect.<br />

3. Aelred is not only the author of the treatise, but also the<br />

principal character in the dialogue. Although it would be nice to<br />

imagine that the two are one and the same, careful reflection<br />

should lead the reader to conclude that they are not. In all probability,<br />

the “Aelred of the dialogue” is a “persona” projected onto<br />

the page by “Aelred the writer.” That is not to say that there<br />

are no continuities between the two; more continuities probably<br />

exist than discontinuities. Still, “Aelred the writer” is making<br />

only a selective representation of himself when he portrays himself<br />

in words for others to see. However small the gap between the<br />

“author” and his “persona,” it is important for readers to keep<br />

the discrepancy in mind as they go through the text. Reading the<br />

dialogue should encourage them to be aware of discrepancies in<br />

their own lives between the people they are and the “personae”<br />

they project for others to see.<br />

4. The dialogue form brings to the fore the dialogical dimension<br />

of spiritual friendship: the closer the friendship, the<br />

more intimate the dialogue. This holds true for one’s relationship<br />

with other human beings – both living and dead – and especially<br />

with Christ. Aelred’s dialogue encourages his readers to<br />

be conscious of the quality of the dialogue that they have with<br />

their friends and also of the quality of their prayer. The depth of<br />

these conversations provides them with a good gauge for determining<br />

the strength of the bonds that tie them. In his dialogue,<br />

Aelred feels free not only to discuss a serious subject with his<br />

friends, but also to root that discussion in his own experience.<br />

By presenting this dialogue to a wider audience, he is inviting<br />

those who read his words to do the same.<br />

5. For Aelred, the doctrine of creation provides his teaching<br />

with a focal point of paradisal innocence. He uses it to show that<br />

all creatures – inanimate, animate, human, and angelic – have<br />

an innate orientation to some kind of companionship and life in


THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP 81<br />

society. His beautiful description of the collateral relationship<br />

between man and woman, moreover, contrasts sharply with the<br />

predominant hierarchical view of the day. Aelred considers<br />

friendship before the fall to be coextensive with the life if charity.<br />

In this state, it is the “medicine of life” not in the sense of<br />

healing (since there is no need of it), but in the sense of bringing<br />

ongoing strength and sustenance to one’s life. Aelred uses the<br />

doctrine of creation to point to an original compatibility of the<br />

dual love of friendship (amicitia) and charity (caritas). Even today,<br />

this usage causes its readers to reflect upon the origins of<br />

these loves, the reasons for their present dissonance, and the<br />

orientation they have toward the future.<br />

6. Although Aelred does not devote a great deal of space to it<br />

in his treatise, the doctrine of the fall plays a significant role in<br />

his understanding of friendship as the “medicine of life.” The fall<br />

of Adam disrupts the original relationship of harmony between<br />

charity and friendship within humanity. This fall from grace results<br />

in a corresponding disruption in the relationship between<br />

God and humanity and unleashes the powerful force of concupiscence<br />

in the heart of every human being. The doctrine of the<br />

fall provides an important part of the theological rationale for<br />

Aelred’s teaching on friendship. Deeply wounded by Adam’s fall,<br />

human nature is in desperate need of healing. Even after Christ’s<br />

redemptive action, humanity still suffers from the horrible effects<br />

of original sin. Spiritual friendship helps people to experience<br />

in their lives the concrete fruits of Christ’s redemption. Its<br />

curative powers tame the unruly emotions of the heart and enable<br />

people to live in one another – and with God.<br />

7. The healing of humanity’s wound, of course, comes primarily<br />

through the redemptive suffering of Christ, which<br />

reestablishes a basis for friendship between the human and the<br />

divine. Spiritual friendship is again made possible only because<br />

Jesus, out of loving obedience to the Father, has laid down his<br />

life for his friends (cf. Jn 15:13). Without this gratuitous act of<br />

self-offering, the harmony between charity and friendship would<br />

never be able to be brought back into harmony. For Aelred, the<br />

doctrine of the redemption creates the possibility for a renewed<br />

relationship of friendship between God and humanity. It is this<br />

renewed relationship with Jesus that heals humanity of its deadly<br />

wounds and gives it a new lease on life. In this respect, a per-


82 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

son’s friendship with Christ is the true “medicine of life.” All other<br />

spiritual friendships are of a participatory nature. Their curative<br />

powers flow from Christ and ultimately lead back to him.<br />

8. This participatory nature of spiritual friendships in Christ<br />

provides an important context for Aelred’s understanding of<br />

goodness. In God, goodness is a transcendental perfection (e.g.,<br />

the One, the True, the Good, the Beautiful) and possesses all the<br />

characteristics typically associated with it. In humanity, however,<br />

goodness is merely participatory and can never achieve the<br />

transcendental status reserved only to the divine. The distinction<br />

between the divine and the human, between the Creator and the<br />

created must always be strictly maintained. For Aelred, moreover,<br />

the participatory nature of human goodness differs greatly<br />

depending on which particular mode of human nature one is<br />

talking about at the time. Humanity’s participated goodness before<br />

the fall, for example, differs from what it is like after the fall<br />

and also after the Christ’s redemption has reached its full effect.<br />

Aelred’s practical concerns about the formation of spiritual<br />

friendship reflect this qualified understanding of the participatory<br />

nature of human goodness.<br />

9. The qualified participatory nature of human goodness allows<br />

Aelred to treat the healing of human nature as an ongoing<br />

process. Rooted in an allegorical interpretation of The Song of<br />

Songs 1:1 (the only such interpretation in the entire treatise) his<br />

metaphor of the three kisses – carnal, spiritual, and intellectual<br />

– allows him to describe spiritual friendship as a mingling of<br />

spirits that mediates one’s relationship with Christ and eventually<br />

leads to a direct mingling of one’s spirit with the Spirit of<br />

Christ. Spiritual friendship is likened to the exchange of breath<br />

that takes place in a kiss. Just as breathing is necessary for life,<br />

so too is friendship necessary for spiritual life. This necessity,<br />

however, comes not from the bond of friendship itself, but from<br />

the grace of Christ, who makes it possible and to whom the spiritual<br />

friendship ultimately leads. The medicinal powers of spiritual<br />

friendship, in other words, derive from their “graced capacity”<br />

to mediate Christ’s presence and to lead a person into an intimate<br />

relationship with Christ himself.<br />

10. All of the practical advice on spiritual friendship given in<br />

Book Three, the longest in the treatise, stems from Aelred’s sensitivity<br />

to the precarious nature of humanity’s present earthly ex-


istence. Even though Christ’s redemptive suffering has made it<br />

possible for human beings to enter once again into fellowship<br />

with God, the effects of original sin still influence the human<br />

heart and can easily get in the way. Concerned more with experience<br />

than with abstract doctrines, Aelred provides his readers<br />

with concrete suggestions about the precautions they should<br />

take when entering into spiritual friendships. It is for this reason<br />

that Aelred goes to great lengths to describe the various steps involved<br />

in the fourfold process of selection, probation, admission,<br />

and union. This practical advice helps to insure that genuine<br />

spiritual friendships can actually be established and bear<br />

fruit. Without it, the reader would be at a loss concerning the<br />

concrete ways of developing these important bonds.<br />

Conclusion<br />

THE HEALING ROLE OF FRIENDSHIP 83<br />

Spiritual friendship, for Aelred, has an important role to<br />

play in a person’s journey to God. The various literary and theological<br />

contexts of his treatise highlight this firm conviction.<br />

One might go so far as to say that Aelred’s use of the dialogue<br />

form and of the Christian doctrines of creation, fall, and redemption<br />

give shape to his teaching and cannot be separated<br />

from it without drastically changing it. To do so would be to<br />

overlook some of his most basic presuppositions about the present<br />

state of human nature and the remedies given by God for<br />

facilitating a person’s growth in holiness.<br />

In describing spiritual friendship as the “medicine of life,”<br />

Aelred highlights humanity’s present need for healing and<br />

strengthening. The literary form in which he casts his teachings<br />

reminds the reader of the various types of spiritual friendships<br />

possible and that dialogue itself is an essential element for the<br />

establishment and ongoing development of such relationships.<br />

The theological background of his teaching offers some helpful<br />

insights into his qualified understanding of participated goodness,<br />

his presentation of spiritual friendship as a process of<br />

growth reaching its perfection in intimate union with Christ,<br />

and his penchant for giving very concrete, practical advice about<br />

their care and maintenance.<br />

Aelred’s primary interest in his De spiritali amicitia is to help


84 DENNIS J. BILLY<br />

his readers to foster intimate friendships among themselves and<br />

with Christ. One does not journey long into the treatise, however,<br />

before discovering that the two kinds of relationships are intimately<br />

related – and in a circular way. Spiritual friendships<br />

lead those involved into an intimate relationship with Christ.<br />

Christ, in turn, makes such relationships possible and orients<br />

them from the very beginning toward himself. Spiritual friendships,<br />

in other words, “…begin in Christ, continue in Christ, and<br />

are perfected in Christ.” 51 They lie at the heart of Aelred’s spiritual<br />

doctrine and have much to offer those who enter into a critical<br />

yet constructive dialogue with their underlying literary and<br />

theological premises. Only by examining these contexts, will the<br />

reader discover the influence that Aelred’s own monastic background<br />

had on the shaping of his teaching. Only then will he or<br />

she be ready to begin to make appropriate adaptations of this<br />

teaching to the present day.<br />

—————<br />

DENNIS J. BILLY, C.SS.R<br />

The author is an Ordinary Professor at the Alphonsian Academy.<br />

El Autor es profesor ordinario de en la Academia Alfonsiana.<br />

—————<br />

51 DSA 1:10 [CCCM 1:29171-73); SF 53].


StMor 40 (2002) 85-114<br />

MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI<br />

Uno dei campi più affascinanti della ricerca biomedica<br />

odierna e uno fra gli ambiti più promettenti delle biotecnologie<br />

è quello legato alle ricerche sulle cellule staminali.<br />

Gli studi in corso per penetrarne le dinamiche differenziative<br />

e per poterle impiegare in ambito terapeutico hanno ormai<br />

raggiunto la ribalta dei mezzi di comunicazione di massa e sono<br />

destinati ad accendere un nuovo e appassionante dibattito pubblico.<br />

Accanto alle urgenti e delicate questioni etiche e legali<br />

connesse con la produzione e la manipolazione delle cellule staminali,<br />

si profilano infatti orizzonti inediti e forse rivoluzionari<br />

per la stessa comprensione del fenomeno della vita.<br />

Il presente articolo si propone di compiere una puntualizzazione<br />

dei più rilevanti problemi in gioco, avvisando che ci muoviamo<br />

in un terreno ancora magmatico e tumultuoso sia dal<br />

punto di vista scientifico sia, di conseguenza, almeno in qualche<br />

misura, dal punto di vista etico.<br />

1. La biologia delle cellule staminali<br />

Le cellule staminali (stem cells) sono cellule che hanno già<br />

compiuto alcuni passi sulla via della trasformazione da cellule<br />

embrionali del tutto indifferenti e ancora totipotenti in cellule<br />

specializzate. Le cellule staminali sono ovviamente tipiche degli<br />

embrioni, ma una quota di esse continua ad essere presente anche<br />

nei tessuti adulti.<br />

Le cellule staminali embrionali – studiate dapprima nel topo<br />

e da qualche anno nell’uomo 1 – provengono dalla blastocisti,<br />

1 Le prime esperienze nel topo all’inizio degli anni ’80 del xx secolo:<br />

EVANS M., KAUFMAN M., Establishment in culture of pluripotent cells from<br />

mouse embryos, “Nature” 292 (1981), 154-156.<br />

85


86 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

un embrione in fase immediatamente preimpiantatoria, prelevando<br />

con tecniche di immunochirurgia i singoli blastomeri della<br />

massa cellulare interna, quella – per intenderci – che darà origine<br />

al corpo del nuovo essere, o dalle cellule germinali primordiali,<br />

cellule fetali da cui in una fase successiva si formeranno<br />

spermatozoi ed ovociti 2 .<br />

Le cellule staminali embrionali sono cellule pluripotenti: esse<br />

mantengono, infatti, una grande flessibilità potendo dare origine<br />

praticamente a qualsiasi tipo cellulare e tessuto, esclusi solo<br />

quelli degli annessi. Una volte poste in coltura, anche se sono<br />

isolate dall’embrione di provenienza, mostrano una spontanea<br />

tendenza a differenziarsi e a formare strutture organizzate multicellulari<br />

note come corpi embrioidi (embryoid bodies) che contengono<br />

elementi riferibili ai tre foglietti embrionali, ectoderna,<br />

mesoderma ed endoderma: si possono riconoscere in essi una<br />

varietà di tipi cellulari e tissutali, talvolta presentando masse disorganizzate<br />

di tessuto nervoso o cartilagineo, talvolta evolvendo<br />

in miociti o anche in miocardiociti, cellule cardiache che ben<br />

presto mostrano la proprietà fisiologica di pulsare sincronicamente<br />

3 . Mentre, dunque, isolare cellule staminali da embrioni è<br />

relativamente agevole, mantenerle in coltura allo stato pluripotenziale<br />

impedendo la loro spontanea progressione verso la specializzazione<br />

è invece arduo, in accordo con la visione tradizionale<br />

e quasi intuitiva che afferma l’intrinseca tensione delle forme<br />

viventi a muoversi verso stadi evolutivi e maturativi sempre<br />

più definiti. Solo da pochi anni, dopo lunghe esperienze con gli<br />

animali, il 5 novembre 1998 la Geron Corporation ha annunciato<br />

che un gruppo di scienziati che lavoravano per la Geron stes-<br />

2 Nel topo: MATSUI Y., ZSEBO K., HOGAN B. L., Derivation of pluripotent<br />

embryonic stem cells from murine primordial germ cells in culture, “Cell” 70<br />

(1992), 81-87; SHAMBLOTT M. J., AXELMAN J., WANG S. et al., Derivation of pluripotent<br />

stem cells from cultured human primordial germ cells, “Proceedings<br />

of the National Academy of Science USA” 95 (1998), 13, 726-731.<br />

3 ITSKOVITZ-ELDOR J., SCHULDINER M., KARSENTI D. et al., Differentiation of<br />

human embryonic stem cells into embryoid bodies comprising the three embryonic<br />

germ layers, “Mol Med” 6 (2000), 88-95; KELLER G., In vitro differentiation<br />

of embryonic stem cells, “Current Opinions in Cell Biology” 7 (1995),<br />

862-869.


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 87<br />

sa era riuscito a stabilire linee di coltura di cellule staminali embrionali<br />

umane dando origine a cellule virtualmente immortali,<br />

capaci cioè di riprodursi indefinitamente 4 .<br />

Le cellule necessarie per queste manipolazioni sono prelevate<br />

da embrioni precoci provenienti da tecniche di procreazione<br />

artificiale, sia soprannumerari sia prodotti ad hoc (dove le<br />

leggi, come nel Regno Unito, lo permettono) o da embrioni e feti<br />

provenienti da aborti spontanei o indotti. Dal momento poi<br />

che le cellule staminali potrebbero meglio dispiegare il loro potenziale<br />

terapeutico, soprattutto in vista dei trapianti, se si potranno<br />

avere linee cellulari istocompatibili o addirittura identiche<br />

a quelle del ricevente, si sta prospettando di ottenere cellule<br />

staminali da embrioni umani prodotti per clonazione con questo<br />

scopo preciso (clonazione terapeutica) 5 .<br />

L’uso di embrioni non è l’unica via per ottenere queste cellule.<br />

Un’alternativa consiste nell’isolamento, dal contesto dei tessuti<br />

differenziati, di speciali cellule staminali adulte: si tratta di<br />

cellule non specializzate e non ancora idonee a svolgere le funzioni<br />

specifiche tipiche delle cellule dei diversi organi e tessuti,<br />

ma che – al bisogno – possono andare incontro a mitosi e dare<br />

origine a una progenie di cellule figlie, parte delle quali progredisce<br />

nel cammino differenziativo sino a uno specifico tipo cellulare,<br />

mentre un’altra parte permane indifferenziata e funge come<br />

da serbatoio.<br />

L’istologia tradizionale ben conosceva la presenza negli organismi<br />

adulti di cellule progenitrici o cellule stipite, cellule immature<br />

e solo parzialmente differenziate, la cui funzione era giustamente<br />

riportata al mantenimento dell’omeostasi tissutale 6 .<br />

4 THOMSON J. A., ITSKOVITZ-ELDOR J., SHAPIRO S. S., WAKNITZ M. A., SWIER-<br />

GIEL J. J. et al., Embryonic stem cell lines derived from human blastocysts,<br />

“Science” 282 (1998), 1145-1147.<br />

5 GEARHART J., New potential for human embryonic stem cells, “Science”<br />

282 (1998), 1061-1062; ODORICO J.S., KAUFMAN D. S., THOMON J. A., Multilineage<br />

differentiation from human embryonic stem cell lines, “Stem Cells” 19<br />

(2001), 193-204.<br />

6 HOLTZER H., Cell lineages, stem cells and the ‘quantal’ cell cycle concept,<br />

in LORD B. I., POTTEN C. S., COLE R. J. eds., Stem cells and tissue homeostasis,<br />

Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (N. Y.) 1978, 1-28.


88 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

Classicamente si ammetteva che le cellule progenitrici fossero<br />

presenti in quei tessuti adulti che vanno incontro a insulti e a rapida<br />

e fisiologica sostituzione (turn-over), come l’epidermide, la<br />

mucosa intestinale e il midollo osseo, detti per ciò tessuti labili<br />

o rinnovabili 7 . Le cellule progenitrici intestinali rigenerano di<br />

continuo il rivestimento interno dell’intestino, le progenitrici<br />

dell’epidermide producono incessantemente nuove progenie cellulari<br />

cutanee, le progenitrici emopoietiche del midollo osseo<br />

danno origine ad una vasta serie di cellule che si trovano nel sangue.<br />

Si avevano inoltre indizi per ritenere che le piccole cellule<br />

individuate fin dagli anni ’20 nel connettivo, spesso lungo il decorso<br />

dei piccoli vasi e dei capillari 8 , fossero cellule indifferenziate,<br />

dette cellule mesenchimali perché capaci di originare diversi<br />

tipi di derivazione mesenchimale 9 . In effetti, oltre alle cellule<br />

progenitrici, sono state ritrovate nei tessuti adulti vere e proprie<br />

cellule staminali, cellule non specializzate capaci di perpetuarsi<br />

indefinitamente e di dare origine a tipi cellulari maturi,<br />

passando attraverso lo stadio intermedio di cellule progenitrici.<br />

Le novità più interessanti sulle cellule staminali adulte riguardano<br />

la loro presenza in tessuti finora ritenuti non rinnovabili<br />

e la loro flessibilità differenziativa.<br />

Era convinzione generale che il tessuto nervoso dell’adulto<br />

fornisse un tipico esempio di tessuto non rinnovabile, “un tessuto<br />

ad elementi perpetui” come si esprimeva Bizzozero, in cui le<br />

7 LOEFFLER M., POTTEN C. S., Stem cells and cellular pedigrees – a conceptual<br />

introduction, in POTTEN C. S. ed., Stem Cells, Academic Press, Cambridge<br />

(MA) 1997, 1-27; SLACK J. M., Stem cells in epithelial tissues, “Science” 287<br />

(2000), 1431-1433.<br />

8 MARCHAND F., Der örtlichen reaktiven Vorgänge (Lehre von der Entzündung),<br />

in KREHL, MARCHAND F., Handbuch der allgemeinen Pathologie, Leipzig<br />

1924, vol. 4, part. 1, 78.<br />

9 Un noto manuale, negli anni ’60, si esprimeva così: “La convinzione<br />

che questi elementi non sono comuni fibroblasti, ma cellule indifferenziate<br />

è derivata da numerose osservazioni attestanti che sotto l’influenza di certi<br />

stimoli, come il mantenimento in coltura in vitro, l’infiammazione e l’iniezione<br />

di tossine, essi possono dar origine a nuovi tipi di cellule; probabilmente<br />

hanno proprietà molto simili alle cellule reticolari primitive dei tessuti<br />

emopoietici” (BLOOM W., FAWCETT D. W., Trattato di istologia, Piccin, Padova<br />

1970, 150).


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 89<br />

possibilità di moltiplicazione dell’elemento nobile del tessuto, il<br />

neurone, e quindi le possibilità di riparazione di eventuali danni<br />

fossero praticamente nulle. Queste caratteristiche del tessuto<br />

nervoso spiegavano a sufficienza perché, dopo la distruzione di<br />

aree più o meno vaste del sistema nervoso centrale per ictus o<br />

trauma, il recupero anatomico e funzionale è alquanto ridotto.<br />

Ora sappiamo, invece, che anche nel sistema nervoso centrale<br />

sono presenti cellule staminali le quali possono dare origine ai<br />

principali tipi cellulari del tessuto nervoso, le cellule gliali<br />

(astrociti e oligodendrociti) e i neuroni 10 . Esse sono state isolate<br />

dapprima dalla zona subventricolare nella parete del ventricolo<br />

laterale del cervello, dove costituirebbero una popolazione cellulare<br />

molto piccola (0.1-1% del totale) e relativamente quiescente,<br />

ma che, in particolari situazioni, possono dividersi e differenziarsi<br />

11 . Johansson ha dimostrato che nel ratto la sede delle<br />

cellule staminali neurali non è la zona sottoventricolare, ma<br />

l’ependima, il sottile rivestimento epiteliale monostratificato che<br />

ricopre la superficie ventricolare stessa. Frammiste fra le cellule<br />

ependimali mature, sono state infatti evidenziate cellule staminali<br />

che presentano i tipici marcatori delle cellule neurali immature<br />

e che, sebbene molto raramente, entrano in mitosi, come<br />

è dimostrato dall’incorporazione di un particolare vettore retrovirale<br />

iniettato nel ventricolo laterale che può essere incorporato<br />

solo dalle cellule che si dividono. Si pensa che le cellule staminali<br />

dell’ependima si dividano asimmetricamente per dare<br />

origine a due cellule figlie, una che rimane come cellula indifferenziata<br />

nell’ependima e una che si trasferisce nella sottostante<br />

zona sottoventricolare dove forma un pool di cellule progenitrici<br />

della glia e dei neuroni pronte a migrare dove sia necessario.<br />

La seconda novità è costituita – come si diceva – dalla sco-<br />

10 MCKAY R. D. G., Stem cells in the central nervous system, “Science” 276<br />

(1997), 66-71; MOMMA S., CHANDROSS K. J., HARTA G., et al., Get to know your<br />

stem cells, “Current Opinions in Neurobiology” 10 (2000), 45-49; STEINDLER<br />

D.A., PINCUS D.W. Stem cells and neuropoiesis in the adult human brain, “Lancet”,<br />

359 (2002), 1047-1054; TEMPLE S., ALVAREZ-BUYLLA A., Stem cells in the<br />

adult mammalian central nervous system, “Current Opinions in Neurobiology”<br />

9 (1999), 135-141.<br />

11 WEISS S., VAN DER KOOY D., J., CNS stem cells: Where’s the biology<br />

(a.k.a. beef)?, “Journal of Neurobiology” 36 (1998), 307-314.


90 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

perta di una flessibilità maggiore di quella che si era classicamente<br />

supposta. A differenza infatti delle cellule staminali embrionali,<br />

che sono pluripotenti, si è a lungo ritenuto che le cellule<br />

staminali dell’adulto fossero meno versatili e potessero differenziarsi<br />

entro un ambito alquanto più ristretto. Questa persuasione,<br />

che era in linea con la comprensione tradizionale della<br />

biologia sulla unidirezionalità del processo differenziativo<br />

normale, deve ora essere rivista 12 .<br />

Si è visto che le cellule progenitrici contenute nello stroma<br />

del midollo osseo, che sono di origine mesenchimale, possono<br />

differenziarsi non solo negli elementi del sangue e in altre cellule<br />

di analoga derivazione embriologica, come miociti, osteociti e<br />

condrociti, incluse le cellule della microglia del sistema nervoso<br />

centrale, ma perfino, sia pure in percentuale minore, in cellule<br />

di derivazione neuroepiteliale, quali gli astrociti 13 . La capacità<br />

delle cellule staminali di generare cellule differenziate di natura<br />

embriologica diversa da quella della staminale di origine è detta<br />

plasticità 14 o transdifferenziazione 15 .<br />

12 Non possiamo affrontare qui, per motivi di spazio, il tema delle ripercussioni<br />

culturali delle scoperte sulle cellule staminali, ma probabilmente esse<br />

ci porteranno a ripensare la nostra comprensione dello svolgersi unidirezionale<br />

dei processi vitali sia a livello del singolo organismo, sia a livello dei<br />

processi evolutivi generali.<br />

13 BIANCO P., RIMINUCCI P., GRONTHOS M., ROBEY P. G., Bone marrow stromal<br />

stem cells: Nature, biology, and potential applications, “Stem Cells” 19<br />

(2001), 180-192; DEANS R. J., MOSELEY A. B., Mesenchymal stem cells: biology<br />

and potential clinical uses, “Experimental Hematology” 28 (2000) 875-884;<br />

PITTENGER M. F., MACKAY A. M., BECK S. C. et al., Multilineage potential of<br />

adult human mesenchymal stem cells, “Science” 284 (1999), 143-147; WOOD-<br />

BURY D., SCHWARZ E. J., PROCKOP D. J., BLACK I. B., Adult rat and human bone<br />

marrow stromal cells differentiate into neurons, “Journal of Neuroscience Research”<br />

61 (2000), 364-370.<br />

Ricordiamo che fra le cellule deputate a funzioni trofiche e di sostegno<br />

nel sistema nervoso centrale, gli astrociti derivano, come i neuroni e le cellule<br />

ependimali, dal neuroepitelio ectodermico, mentre le cellule microgliali<br />

derivano dal mesenchima mesodermico circostante il tubo neurale.<br />

14 Cfr. KRAUSE D. S., THEISE N. D., COLLECTOR M. I. et al., Multi-organ,<br />

multi-lineage engraftment by a single bone narrow-derived stem cell, “Cell” 105<br />

(2001), 369-377.<br />

15 Cfr. ANDERSON D. J., GAGE F. H., WEISSMAN I. L., Can stem cells cross li-


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 91<br />

Ancora più sorprendente, sempre tenendo conto della tradizionale<br />

stabilità del tessuto nervoso, è l’osservazione che le cellule<br />

staminali del sistema nervoso centrale sono capaci di differenziarsi<br />

in tipi cellulari che non condividono la stessa origine<br />

ectodermica 16 . Nel gennaio del 1999 Cristopher Bjornson e Angelo<br />

Vescovi con il loro gruppo hanno riferito di aver osservato<br />

che alcune cellule staminali nervose prelevate dal cervello di topo,<br />

una volta trasferite in topi il cui midollo osseo emopoietico<br />

era stato distrutto per irradiazione, potevano evolvere in cellule<br />

ematiche 17 . La possibilità di poter avere colture di cellule staminali<br />

neurali per lunghi periodi di tempo e l’osservazione che tali<br />

cellule possono naturalmente evolvere – in determinate circostanze<br />

– sia in senso neurogliale sia in senso ematico, fa sperare<br />

con fondamento che “le cellule staminali nervose umane possano<br />

fornire una fonte rinnovabile e caratterizzata di cellule che<br />

potrebbero essere usate in approcci tesi alla ricostituzione ematopoietica<br />

in varie malattie e disordini del sangue” 18 . L’anno seguente<br />

lo stesso gruppo ha mostrato come le cellule staminali<br />

cerebrali umane, al pari di quelle murine, sono in grado di dare<br />

origine a cellule di muscolo scheletrico 19 .<br />

neage boundaries?, “Nature Medicine” 7 (2001), 393-395; SNYDER E. Y., VE-<br />

SCOVI A. L., The possibilities/perplexities of stem cells, “Nature Biotechnology”<br />

18 (2000), 827-828. Il gruppo di E. Lagasse, dopo aver descritto la transdifferenziazione<br />

di cellule staminali del tessuto emopoietico midollare in epatociti,<br />

si chiede se il fenomeno non sia da attribuirsi alla presenza nell’adulto<br />

di cellule pluripotenti più primitive (e quindi più simili alle staminali embrionali):<br />

LAGASSE E., CONNORS H., AL-DHALIMY M. et al., Purified hematopoietic<br />

stem cells differentiate into hepatocytes in vivo, “Nature Medicine” 6<br />

(2000), 1229-1234.<br />

16 VESCOVI A. L., GALLI R., GRITTI A., The neural stem cells and their trans<br />

differentiation capacity, “Biomedical Pharmacotherapy” 55 (2001), 201-205.<br />

17 BJORNSON C. R. R., RIETZE R. L., REYNOLDS B. A., MAGLI M. C., VESCO-<br />

VI A. L., Turning brain into blood: A hematopoietic fate adopted by adult neural<br />

stem cell in vivo, “Science” 283 (1999), 534-537.<br />

18 Ibidem, 537.<br />

19 GALLI R., BORELLO U., GRITTI A., MINASI M. G. et al., Skeletal myogenic<br />

potential of human and mouse neural stem cells, “Nature Neuroscience” 3<br />

(2000), 986-991.


92 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

2. Uso terapeutico e fonti delle cellule staminali<br />

Le potenziali applicazioni terapeutiche delle cellule staminali<br />

sono entusiasmanti 20 .<br />

Le speranze più forti riguardano l’impiego delle cellule staminali<br />

per la sostituzione di cellule e tessuti danneggiati. Sulla<br />

base di esperimenti compiuti su animali, si possono prevedere<br />

molteplici applicazioni in una vasta gamma di affezioni umane<br />

per esempio nell’infarto miocardico, o in processi degenerativi,<br />

come nel diabete insulinodipendente, in cui si ha esaurimento<br />

delle beta cellule pacreatiche, o nel Parkinson, in cui sono implicate<br />

particolari vie neuronali dopaminergiche 21 .<br />

Nel morbo di Parkinson sono già stati sperimentati trapianti<br />

di cellule dopaminoproduttrici prelevate da feti umani e si va<br />

studiando la possibilità di trapianti a partire da cellule staminali<br />

neuronali prelevate dal cervello fetale o addirittura dall’embrione,<br />

messe in coltura e fatte sviluppare, con gli opportuni fattori<br />

di crescita e di differenziazione, verso il tipo neuronale desiderato<br />

22 . In base alle nuove acquisizioni sulle cellule staminali<br />

dell’adulto, si pensa però che “in futuro si potrebbero utilizzare<br />

cellule staminali provenienti dallo stesso individuo maturo (che<br />

ancora ne possiede) per un autotrapianto. Questo risolverà tutta<br />

20 KELLER G., SNODGRASS R. H., Human embryonic stem cells: The future<br />

is now, “Nature Medicine” 5 (1999), 151-152; SNODGRASS H. R., GRAHAM D. K.,<br />

STANFORD W. L., LICATO L. L., Embryonic stem cells: Research and clinical potential,<br />

in SMITH M. D., SACHER R. A. (eds), Peripheral blood stem cell transplantation,<br />

Bethesda, Maryland 1993, 65-82.<br />

21 MCDONALD J. W., LIU X. Z., QU Y., LIU S., et al., Transplanted embryonic<br />

stem cells survive, differentiate and promote recovery in injured rat spinal<br />

cord, “Nature Medicine” 5 (1999), 1410-1412; KLUG M. G., SOONPAA M. H.,<br />

KOH G. Y., FIELD L. J., Genetically selected cardiomyocites from differentiating<br />

embryonic stem cells from stable intracardiac grafts, “Journal of Clinical Investigations”<br />

98 (1996), 216-224; POTOCNIK A. J., KOHLER H., EICHMANN K.,<br />

Hematolymphoid in vitro reconstitution potential of subpopulations derived<br />

from in viro differentiated embryonic stem cells, “Proceedings of the Academy<br />

of Science U.S.A.” 94 (1997), 10295-10300.<br />

22 FREED C. R., GREENE P. E., BREEZE R. E. et al., Transplantation of embryonic<br />

dopamine neurons for severe Parkinson’s disease, “New England Journal<br />

of Medicine” 344 (2001), 710-719.


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 93<br />

la problematica etica connessa con l’uso di materiale fetale” 23 .<br />

Una forma singolare di combinazione di terapia genica e autotrapianto<br />

potrebbe essere realizzata in soggetti affetti da gravi<br />

malattie genetiche: le cellule stipite di un certo tipo cellulare o<br />

anche cellule staminali diverse, un volta estratte dal soggetto ed<br />

opportunamente manipolate, potrebbero essere corrette dall’anomalia<br />

genica e poi reintrodotte nel soggetto di provenienza<br />

per costituire una nuova popolazione sana 24 .<br />

Un campo nel quale si ha una esperienza clinica ormai consolidata<br />

è quello del trapianto di cellule staminali ematopoietiche,<br />

indicata in soggetti incapaci di normale emopoiesi o di normale<br />

produzione di cellule immunocompetenti, come nell’aplasia<br />

midollare, in diverse sindromi di immunodeficienza, nella<br />

Thalassemia maior, e in soggetti con neoplasie a carico del sistema<br />

emopoietico e in alcuni tumori solidi. Nell’ambito della terapia<br />

di malattie ematologiche congenite meritano di essere segnalati<br />

i tentativi di trapianto in utero di cellule staminali che offrono,<br />

rispetto ai tradizionali trapianti post-natali, almeno tre<br />

vantaggi: essendo il sistema immunitario del ricevente ancora<br />

immaturo, sono meglio tollerate; la rapida espansione del compartimento<br />

emopoietico fetale permette alle cellule trasferite di<br />

trovare più facilmente spazio per attecchire; la correzione precoce<br />

della disfunzione permette uno sviluppo più soddisfacente<br />

del feto 25 . Le cellule staminali necessarie per questi interventi<br />

provengono da donatori e vengono ottenute generalmente dal<br />

midollo delle ossa del bacino, ma si sta perfezionando il prelievo<br />

dal sangue periferico con la centrifugazione e la staminoaferesi,<br />

previa stimolazione con opportuni fattori di crescita 26 .<br />

23 FARIELLO R. G., Argomenti di discussione per un consenso allargato, in<br />

DULBECCO R. et al., Clonazione: problemi etici e prospettive scientifiche, Le<br />

Scienze, Milano 1997, 45.<br />

24 HALENE S., KOHN D. B., Gene therapy using hematopoietic stem cells:<br />

Sisyphus approaches the crest, “Human Gene Therapy” 11 (2000), 1259-1267.<br />

25 FLAKE A. W. et al., Treatment of X-linked severe combined immunodeciciency<br />

by in utero transplantation of paternal bone marrow, “New England<br />

Journal of Medicine” 335 (1996), 1806-1810; FLAKE A. W., ZANJANI E. D., In<br />

utero hematopoietic stem cell transplantation. A status report, “Journal of the<br />

American Medical Association” 278 (1997), 932-937.<br />

26 La premedicazione del donatore desta alcune perplessità etiche, non


94 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

Una ulteriore fonte, ancora da valorizzare adeguatamente, è<br />

costituita dal sangue del cordone ombelicale: le cellule fetali hanno<br />

mostrato di essere meglio tollerate immunologicamente dai<br />

riceventi rispetto a quelle dei donatori adulti e, anche se in scarsa<br />

quantità rispetto alle necessità di un organismo adulto, hanno<br />

il vantaggio di essere facilmente e largamente disponibili,<br />

senza danneggiare né le madri né i neonati da cui proviene la<br />

placenta 27 . E. Gluckman ha sottolineato sul New England Journal<br />

of Medicine la necessità di non disperdere un capitale biologico<br />

così ingente ed è stata perciò <strong>propos</strong>ta la creazione di vere<br />

e proprie banche di sangue ombelicale 28 . Per il trapianto in utero<br />

– stante la piccola quantità di cellule necessaria – si sono impiegate<br />

anche cellule fetali ematopoietiche estratte dal fegato o<br />

dal timo di feti abortiti, per lo più aborti procurati, con tutte le<br />

intuibili implicazioni etiche e legali.<br />

Un altro settore dei trapianti in cui si può prevedere in futuro<br />

un utile impiego del potenziale biologico delle cellule staminali<br />

è quello della produzione di tessuti ed organi bioartificiali.<br />

La produzione di organi bioartificiali che fino a poco tempo fa<br />

pareva un miraggio, negli ultimi anni ha conosciuto un notevole<br />

progresso e la possibilità di poter disporre di una fonte sicura<br />

di cellule umane ha dischiuso orizzonti nuovi per questa branca<br />

della bioingegneria 29 . Analogamente alle cellule staminali embrionali<br />

di topo, oggi sappiamo che anche le cellule staminali<br />

embrionali umane possono formare vari tipi cellulari e tessuti<br />

semplici, ma la loro capacità di costruire organi complessi in<br />

coltura è pressoché inesplorata. Un saggio impiego di interazio-<br />

essendo ancora del tutto accertata la assenza di conseguenze a lungo termine:<br />

d’altra parte un margine di rischio, purché conosciuto e liberamente accettato,<br />

fa parte della logica della donazione (criterio della lesività ragionevole).<br />

27<br />

ERICES A., CONGET P., MINGUELL J. J., Mesenchymal progenitor cells in<br />

human umbilical cord, “British Journal of Hematology” 109 (2000), 235-242;<br />

LAUGHLIN M. J., Umbilical cord blood for allogeneic transplantation in children<br />

and adults, “Transplantation” 27 (2001), 1-6.<br />

28<br />

GLUCKMAN E., The therapeutic potential of fetal and hematopoietic stem<br />

cells, “New England Journal of Medicine” 335 ( 1996), 1839-1840.<br />

29<br />

LANGER R., VACANTI J. P., Tissue Engineering, “Science” 260 (1993),<br />

920-926.


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 95<br />

ni cellulari e tissutali e l’uso di matrici extracellulari potrebbe<br />

permetterci in futuro di produrre organi complessi come rene o<br />

polmone, per esempio ricorrendo a organi preesistenti, umani o<br />

no, come base, e rimpiazzando le cellule originali con quelle derivate<br />

dalle cellule staminali.<br />

Ovviamente, ogniqualvolta si parla di trasferimento di materiale<br />

istologico fra individui diversi, si profilano il grande ostacolo<br />

della medicina dei trapianti, il rigetto.<br />

Una prima possibilità per superare il rigetto è quella di produrre<br />

embrioni per clonazione con trasferimento di materiale<br />

nucleare prelevato dalle cellule somatiche degli stessi individui<br />

che hanno bisogno di cellule staminali e dei loro derivati: si potrebbero<br />

prelevare dagli embrioni così clonati tutti i materiali<br />

biologici necessari 30 . Oltre al trasferimento nucleare in ovociti<br />

umani denucleati, si è sperimentato anche il trasferimento in<br />

ovociti di altri mammiferi: il 12 novembre 1998 J. Cibelli e J. Robl<br />

hanno annunciato alla stampa di aver ottenuto con questa tecnica<br />

un embrione chimerico, incrocio fra uomo e vacca 31 . Una<br />

terza possibilità allo studio, consiste nella riprogrammazione<br />

del nucleo cellulare (carioplasma) di un certo soggetto fondendolo<br />

con il citoplasma di una cellula staminale embrionale di<br />

specie diversa e ottenendo così un cybrid (ibrido nucleo-citoplasma).<br />

Senza considerare i gravi ostacoli morali presentati da<br />

queste metodiche qualora portassero a ibridi uomo-animale, dal<br />

punto di vista pratico il passaggio obbligato attraverso la clonazione<br />

costituisce una tappa limitante per tutta la procedura e aggiunge<br />

a una tecnica già delicata ulteriori difficoltà.<br />

Altre possibilità per ovviare al problema del rigetto e, nello<br />

stesso tempo, per avere fonti facilmente accessibili di cellule staminali<br />

è quella di produrre e conservare in apposite banche una<br />

larga quantità di stipiti cellulari da cui scegliere quelli maggiormente<br />

compatibili con i riceventi, magari intervenendo sugli antigeni<br />

di istocompatibilità per via genetica o rimuovendo dalla<br />

30<br />

SOLTER D., GEARHART J., Putting stem cells to work, “Science” 283<br />

(1999), 1468-1470.<br />

31<br />

MARSHALL E., Claim of human-cow embryo greeted with skepticism,<br />

“Science” 282 (1998), 1390-1391. Cfr. MARINELLI M., Etica delle biotecnologie.<br />

Clonando & clonando, “Anime e corpi” 36 (1999), 89-90.


96 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

superficie cellulare le sostanze proteiche che causano il riconoscimento<br />

da parte dell’organismo ricevente ovvero mascherando<br />

gli antigeni di istocompatibilità sulla superficie delle cellule staminali<br />

così da creare linee cellulari donatrici universali anche di<br />

provenienza animale 32 .<br />

Oltre alle diverse applicazioni nella medicina dei trapianti,<br />

le cellule staminali potranno essere utilmente impiegate per lo<br />

studio della biologia dello sviluppo e chiarire lati oscuri dell’embriologia<br />

umana ed animale, in riferimeno al funzionamento dei<br />

geni, alla regolazione dei rapporti fra i tessuti, all’azione dei fattori<br />

di crescita, con benefiche ricadute in campo clinico e terapeutico.<br />

Si può prevedere anche l’utilità pratica delle cellule staminali<br />

come sistemi di riferimento per valutare la tossicità e l’efficacia<br />

di nuovi farmaci e sostanze chimiche 33 .<br />

Per conseguire questi e altri risultati c’è ancora molto lavoro<br />

da fare per l’isolamento e la moltiplicazione in vitro di linee<br />

pure di cellule staminali e per usare a nostro piacere il loro enorme<br />

potenziale. Sarà necessario, in particolare, imparare a spingere<br />

le cellule staminali di una cultura a differenziarsi lungo un<br />

percorso prestabilito per diventare, ad esempio neuroni adrenergici<br />

o beta-cellule pacreatiche, e insegnar loro a farlo in modo<br />

simultaneo, armonioso e controllato. Le nostre conoscenze<br />

sulle cellule staminali sono ancora largamente frammentarie,<br />

anche se – come si è visto – non mancano promettenti esperienze<br />

nel topo e perfino nell’uomo: conosciamo ancora in modo insufficiente<br />

i segnali biochimici che determinano differenziazione<br />

dei blastomeri embrionali totipotenti in cellule pluripotenti e<br />

infine nei vari tipi di cellule specializzate, né sappiamo ancora<br />

abbastanza sui markers biologici che le contraddistinguono e le<br />

fanno riconoscere, né sappiamo molto sui meccanismi fisiologici<br />

che presiedono al funzionamento e al ciclo vitale delle cellule<br />

32 La tecnica del mascheramento è quella che per ora sembra più avanzata,<br />

essendo già stata sperimentata dalla società Diacrin di Charlestown, nel<br />

Massachussets, per ottenere cellule di fegato di maiale da impiegare in xenotrapianti<br />

nell’uomo e, sempre negli Stati Uniti, essendo stato permesso<br />

l’impiego sperimentale sull’uomo di cellule mascherate di fegato umano nel<br />

trattamento di alcune forme di insufficienza epatica.<br />

33 KELLER G., SNODGRASS R. H., Human embryonic stem cells, 152.


staminali nell’organismo adulto 34 .<br />

Non possiamo infine sottacere i pericoli e i rischi che può<br />

comportare l’uso terapeutico di cellule staminali, in particolare<br />

quelle di derivazione embrionale. Le cellule staminali embrionali<br />

murine si sono dimostrate tumorigeniche, sviluppandosi in<br />

teratomi o teratocarcinomi, quando sono state inoculate in topi<br />

adulti e non c’è motivo per ritenere che le cellule staminali embrionali<br />

umane non si rivelino tumorigeniche negli esseri umani,<br />

anche tenendo conto del fatto che la maggior lunghezza della<br />

vita umana può costituire un fattore facilitante l’insorgere di<br />

patologie neoplastiche 35 . Qualunque mezzo si usasse per separare<br />

le cellule staminali indifferenziate dalla progenie cellulare desiderata<br />

differenziata per essere inoculate, dovremo essere assolutamente<br />

sicuri che la separazione sia completa. Finora noi non<br />

sappiamo il numero minimo di cellule staminali embrionali necessario<br />

per causare un tumore o il tempo necessario per lo sviluppo<br />

tumorale stesso. Le risposte definitive a queste domande<br />

non potranno venire dai topi perché, a parte le diverse caratteristiche<br />

immunologiche, la durata della loro vita è troppo esigua<br />

per poter costituire un modello adeguato<br />

3. Questioni morali e legali<br />

LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 97<br />

Sono da ritenersi in generale eticamente corretti i prelievi di<br />

cellule e tessuti staminali provenienti da organismi umani viventi<br />

che, rispettata la dignità e la libertà della persona, non comportano<br />

danni per la loro integrità e per la loro sussistenza. Né<br />

sarebbe sostanzialmente diverso il discorso se, per migliorarne le<br />

prestazioni o per meglio aggirare il problema del rigetto, si dovesse<br />

ricorrere a interventi manipolativi (come la trasduzione di<br />

particolari geni) sulle cellule stesse. In particolare, il prelievo e<br />

l’uso terapeutico o sperimentale di staminali provenienti da un<br />

34<br />

VOGEL G., Harnessing the power of stem cells, “Science” 283 (1999),<br />

1432-1434.<br />

35<br />

ANDREWS P. W., Teratocarcinomas and human embryology: Pluripotent<br />

human EC cell lines, “Acta Pathologica, Microbiologica et Immunologica<br />

Scandinavica” 10 (1998), 158-17.


98 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

adulto, a parte i consueti problemi clinici legati alla incompatibilità<br />

genetica e al rigetto, non pone questioni morali sostanzialmente<br />

diverse da quelle poste da qualsiasi prelievo di materiale<br />

biologico a fini di trapianto o di sperimentazione.<br />

Quando il donatore è un bambino (situazione non infrequente<br />

nel caso di cellule da midollo osseo) si propone invece la<br />

questione – non facile – della eticità della decisione o del consenso<br />

da parte dei genitori nei confronti di un prelievo da figli<br />

minorenni che non sia motivato dal bene del minore stesso, ma<br />

dal bene di un consanguineo del donatore, di solito un fratellino<br />

con grave patologia di natura linfoematica. Ancora più incresciosa<br />

la situazione del concepimento in vitro e della selezione<br />

di un potenziale donatore per il fratellino o la sorellina bisognosi<br />

di un trapianto di cellule staminali: il caso è accaduto in California<br />

e la piccola Molly di otto anni, affetta dall’anemia di Fanconi,<br />

grave malattia genetica, si è salvata grazie al sangue del<br />

cordone ombelicale del fratellino Adam, concepito in vitro e selezionato<br />

in base alla compatibilità tissutale con Molly 36 .<br />

Riguardo all’uso di cellule staminali ricavate dal sangue del<br />

cordone ombelicale non esistono problemi morali insuperabili,<br />

ma sono stati evidenziati alcuni aspetti etico-deontologici peculiari<br />

che hanno condotto alla compilazione di apposite linee-guida<br />

37 . Prima di tutto c’è da considerare il consenso all’uso di un<br />

organo, il cordone, appunto, che alla nascita viene tagliato e poi<br />

distrutto insieme alla placenta, ma sul quale la madre del bambino<br />

può rivendicare diritti di possesso, in quanto pertinente all’unità<br />

materno-fetale: l’uso terapeutico o scientifico delle cellule<br />

staminali del cordone in favore di terze persone richiede perciò<br />

l’esplicitazione di un consenso libero ed informato. Non è<br />

36<br />

EZZELL C., Ma è etico?, in Medicina per il futuro, “Le Scienze quaderni”<br />

122, ottobre 2001, 26-27.<br />

37<br />

DAME L., SUGARMAN J., Blood money: Ethical and legal implications of<br />

treating cord blood as property, “American Journal of Pediatric Oncology”, 23<br />

(20001), 409-410; SUGARMAN J., KAALUND V., KODISH E., MARSHALL M. F. et al.,<br />

Ethical issues in umbilical cord blood banking, “Journal of the American Medical<br />

Association” 278 (1997), 938-943. Cfr. SPAGNOLO A. G., Trapianto in utero<br />

di cellule ematopoietiche staminali e “banca” del sangue ombelicale, “Medicina<br />

e Morale” 48 (1998), 1073-1077.


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 99<br />

corretto – a nostro avviso – presumere il consenso, accampando<br />

la ragione che il cordone è destinato all’incenerimento, né sarebbe<br />

rispondente alla logica della libertà, chiedere il consenso<br />

mentre il travaglio è in corso e la donna non è normalmente nelle<br />

condizioni psico-fisiche più adatte per ricevere un’informazione<br />

ed esprimere un consenso, ma si dovrà provvedere ad<br />

informare e raccogliere l’eventuale consenso in antecedenza. In<br />

secondo luogo possono emergere situazioni conflittuali fra la tutela<br />

della privacy del donatore e del ricevente e la tutela della salute<br />

del ricevente stesso: nel caso, per esempio, che una malattia<br />

infettiva o genetica comparisse nel donatore, sarebbe necessario<br />

risalire al ricevente per prendere le precauzioni necessarie. L’impossibilità<br />

di garantire il completo anonimato fra donatore e ricevente,<br />

così come i modi e i motivi dell’impiego delle notizie,<br />

devono essere ben precisati all’atto di richiesta del consenso.<br />

Il dibattito etico si concentra sul ricorso a embrioni o feti come<br />

fonte di cellule staminali e questo aspetto particolare si inscrive<br />

nel più vasto problema del prelievo di organi e tessuti fetali<br />

a scopo di trapianto. Senza entrare nello specifico della questione,<br />

è chiaro che, nella prospettiva del personalismo cattolico,<br />

la soppressione diretta di una vita umana in fase iniziale, sia<br />

embrionale sia fetale, per ridonare la salute ad un’altra o per far<br />

progredire le conoscenze a vantaggio dell’umanità, è una prassi<br />

palesemente irragionevole perché contraddittoria e moralmente<br />

inaccettabile 38 .<br />

Nel caso del ricorso a embrioni e feti uccisi con aborto procurato,<br />

anche se l’aborto non è stato praticato da chi poi preleverà<br />

o trapianterà i tessuti, il ricorso a cellule staminali di siffatta<br />

provenienza configurerebbe o potrebbe facilmente configurare<br />

– a nostro avviso – una forma di complicità lato sensu inaccettabile,<br />

anche se non si può parlare stricto sensu di cooperazione<br />

all’atto abortivo. Diverso è ovviamente il discorso se l’aborto<br />

è avvenuto spontaneamente, ma sarebbe ipocrita giustificare<br />

l’impiego di tessuti di dubbia origine – come potrebbe esse-<br />

38 Vedere, per esempio: SPAGNOLO A. G., SGRECCIA E., Prelievi di organi e<br />

tessuti fetali a scopo di trapianto. Aspetti conoscitivi ed istanze etiche, in BOM-<br />

PIANI A., SGRECCIA E. curr., Trapianti d’organo, Vita e Pensiero, Milano 1989,<br />

47-84 (soprattutto 69-81).


100 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

re per i tessuti fetali di una banca – con l’impossibilità morale di<br />

venire a conoscere con certezza le circostanze dell’interruzione<br />

di gravidanza, essendo a tutti noto che la fonte principale di tali<br />

tessuti sono gli aborti procurati. Il sospetto di una possibile relazione<br />

fra induzione dell’aborto e uso dei tessuti embrionali o<br />

fetali non è certo infondato dal momento che in un documento<br />

ufficiale del Comité Consultatif National d’Èthique francese, per<br />

esempio, si raccomanda di realizzare gli aborti in modo da evitare<br />

il più possibile la lacerazione dei tessuti da avviare a scopi<br />

terapeutici o scientifici 39 . Non sembra davvero troppo lungo il<br />

passo fra la semplice accortezza nello scegliere il metodo abortivo<br />

così da non rendere inutilizzabili i tessuti degli embrioni e<br />

dei feti, alla raccolta sistematica e commercializzazione dei prodotti<br />

abortivi.<br />

Ancora più acceso è il dibattito a livello scientifico, etico e<br />

giuridico sulle cellule staminali provenienti da embrioni precoci,<br />

ottenuti tramite tecniche di fecondazione in vitro o tramite clonazione.<br />

A questo <strong>propos</strong>ito, è significativo è il fatto che, prima<br />

ancora di dare l’annuncio ufficiale dei successi ottenuti nel campo<br />

delle cellule staminali embrionali, nel novembre del 1998, la<br />

Geron aveva creato un gruppo di lavoro per elaborare linee guida<br />

che fornissero il necessario supporto o – se si preferisce – la<br />

necessaria copertura bioetica alle ricerche sulle cellule staminali<br />

umane di derivazione embrionale. Questo Comitato Consultivo<br />

di Etica (Ethics Advisory Board), lavorando su una bozza preparata<br />

da Karen Lebacqz nel settembre 1998, è giunto ben presto<br />

al documento definitivo, intitolato A Statement on Human<br />

Embryonic Stem Cells ovvero Dichiarazione sulle cellule staminali<br />

embrionali umane il 20 ottobre dello stesso anno. Il testo del<br />

documento e le spiegazioni che lo accompagnano si possono<br />

trovare in Hastings Center Report 40 , insieme con alcuni interes-<br />

39 COMITÉ CONSULTATIF NATIONAL D’ÈTHIQUE, Opinion on the establishment<br />

of collections of human embryo cells and their use for therapeutic or scientific<br />

purposes, 11-3-1997 (http://www.ccne-ethique.org). Cfr. DI PIETRO M. L., MI-<br />

NACORI R., Cellule staminali: una questione aperta, “Vita e Pensiero” 84 (2001),<br />

65-66.<br />

40 GERON ETHICS ADVISORY BOARD, Research with human embryonic stem<br />

cells: Ethical considerations, “Hastings Center Report” 29 (1999), 2, 31-36.


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 101<br />

santi commenti. Può essere utile, prima di procedere nella discussione,<br />

offrire qui una nostra traduzione del Documento.<br />

“Il Comitato Consultivo di etica della Geron è unanime nel<br />

suo giudizio che la ricerca sulle cellule staminali embrionali<br />

umane può essere condotta in modo etico. Perché tale ricerca<br />

sia condotta eticamente nell’attuale contesto, devono soddisfarsi<br />

alcune condizioni. Inoltre, sarà necessario un ulteriore dibattito<br />

pubblico su una gamma di questioni eticamente complesse<br />

generate da questa ricerca. Le condizioni sono:<br />

1. La blastocisti deve essere trattata con il rispetto dovuto<br />

(“appropriate”) a tessuto embrionale umano precoce.<br />

2. Le donne o le coppie che donano blastocisti prodotte nel<br />

processo di fecondazione in vitro devono dare un consenso pieno<br />

ed informato per l’uso delle blastocisti nella ricerca e nello<br />

sviluppo di linee cellulari da quel tessuto.<br />

3. La ricerca non includerà nessuna clonazione finalizzata a<br />

riproduzione umana, nessun trasferimento in utero e nessuna<br />

creazione di chimere.<br />

4. L’acquisizione e lo sviluppo del terreno di coltura (“feeder<br />

layer”) necessario per la crescita in vitro delle linee cellulari di<br />

cellule staminali embrionali umane non deve violare le norme<br />

accettate per la ricerca umana o animale.<br />

5. Ogni ricerca di questo tipo deve essere svolta in un contesto<br />

di attenzione per la giustizia globale.<br />

6. Ogni ricerca dovrebbe essere approvata da un Comitato<br />

Consultivo di Etica in aggiunta al Comitato Istituzionale di Revisione”<br />

41 .<br />

Il Documento rileva correttamente che il problema cardine<br />

sta nello status ontologico e assiologico conferito alla blastocisti<br />

umana e, più in generale, all’embrione precoce o pre-embrione<br />

umano e quindi nella considerazione etico-giuridica dell’embrione<br />

ottenuto per clonazione. Dal momento infatti che il prelievo<br />

di cellule staminali dall’embrione ne prevede la distruzione,<br />

la questione di fondo ci riporta al valore della vita embrionale<br />

soprattutto quando sono in gioco gli interessi e i progetti<br />

degli esseri umani, intendendo l’aggettivo umano in senso forte.<br />

41 Ibidem, 36.


102 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

In un impianto utilitarista – per esempio – sarà piuttosto<br />

agevole ammettere che, qualunque sia la risposta alla domanda<br />

sullo statuto ontologico dell’embrione, possano darsi situazioni<br />

nelle quali sia socialmente vantaggioso permettere la sua manipolazione<br />

e che, di contro, sia irrazionale proibire la destinazione<br />

di embrioni a studi e applicazioni che potrebbero migliorare<br />

la vita e la salute di molte persone. La distinzione, cara ai neocontrattualisti,<br />

fra le persone e le non persone umane fornisce<br />

ulteriori eleganti, per quanto speciose legittimazioni a queste<br />

pratiche e insinua all’interno dell’unità del genere umano pericolose<br />

e arbitrarie discriminazioni in base alle quali gli agenti<br />

morali in senso proprio possono accordarsi per disporre secondo<br />

i loro progetti gli esseri umani incapaci di essere membri attivi<br />

dell’impresa morale, come gli embrioni e i feti. La posizione<br />

della bioetica personalista sul valore della vita dell’embrione e<br />

quindi sulla distruzione diretta di embrioni per qualsiasi scopo<br />

è notoriamente negativa e le ragioni sono state più volte esposte<br />

con dovizia di argomentazioni, né qui pare necessario entrare<br />

nel merito della discussione 42 .<br />

Mentre a livello legislativo, esclusa le legge inglese, esiste<br />

una certa convergenza sul divieto di produrre embrioni per scopi<br />

diversi da quello riproduttivo, aumentano le incertezze e i cedimenti<br />

per l’uso sperimentale e terapeutico degli embrioni soprannumerari,<br />

provenienti cioè dalla fecondazione in vitro e rimasti<br />

inutilizzati in situazione di crioconservazione 43 . Il Parlamento<br />

europeo si è dichiarato contrario all’uso strumentale degli<br />

embrioni soprannumerari 44 , ma organismi altrettanto presti-<br />

42 Una raccolta di studi di grande interesse in: PONTIFICIA ACADEMIA PRO<br />

VITA, Identità e statuto dell’embrione umano, Città del Vaticano 1998. Nel volume<br />

segnaliamo l’articolo: SERRA A., COLOMBO R., Identità e statuto dell’embrione<br />

umano: il contributo della biologia, 106-158.<br />

43 Per tutta la questione degli embrioni soprannumerari e della loro<br />

crioconservazione rimandiamo ad un nostro status quaestionis: FAGGIONI M.<br />

P., Embrioni congelati. Situazione e problemi emergenti, “<strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong>” 34<br />

(1996), 351-387.<br />

44<br />

PARLAMENTO EUROPEO, Risoluzione sulla clonazione umana, 7-9-2000<br />

(http://www.col.fr./oviedo/).


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 103<br />

giosi si sono mostrati alquanto più aperti a soluzioni di questo<br />

genere, come la National Bioethics Advisory Commission degli<br />

Stati Uniti e questa opinione sta guadagnando favori anche in<br />

Francia ed in Germania 45 .<br />

In Italia il Comitato Nazionale per la Bioetica, benché in modo<br />

non unanime, e la Commissione Ministeriale istituita ad hoc<br />

dal ministro U. Veronesi nel 2000 si sono pronunciati a favore<br />

del ricorso agli embrioni soprannumerari altrimenti destinati alla<br />

distruzione 46 . Sorvolando sul presupposto ideologico implicito<br />

che la vita dell’embrione precoce non abbia valore o ne abbia<br />

comunque meno di quella dell’essere umano nato, la ragione più<br />

spesso addotta per usare gli embrioni soprannumerari è che essi<br />

sono certamente destinati alla morte e che, quindi, impiegarli<br />

per fini utili alle persone non muta il loro destino, mentre procura<br />

benefici ad altri. Si dimentica che la vita dell’essere umano<br />

non può mai essere strumentalizzata e diventare un mezzo per<br />

il conseguimento di fini anche buoni e che, dal punto di vista etico,<br />

esiste una grande differenza tra il lasciar morire, quando non<br />

è possibile impedire la morte, e causare la morte, quando il decesso<br />

dipende direttamente da un atto volontario non inevitabile.<br />

L’ineluttabile destino di morte verso cui sono avviati gli embrioni<br />

soprannumerari non toglie gravità a una loro soppressione<br />

diretta, ma anzi dovrebbe portare ad impedire – come di fatto<br />

è previsto in diverse legislazioni – la loro stessa formazione.<br />

45 NATIONAL BIOETHICS ADVISORY COMMISSION, Ethical Issues in Human<br />

Stem Cell Research, “National Bioethics Advisory Commission”, Rockville<br />

(Maryland), September 1999, vol. I, 85-86 (http://bioethics.gov/pubs.html). Il<br />

9 agosto 2001 il presidente Bush ha annunciato che potranno essere finanziate<br />

con fondi federali ricerche con cellule staminali provenienti da embrioni<br />

formati per motivi riproduttivi e non richiesti dai genitori.<br />

46 I lavori della Commissione in: BOMPIANI A., I. I lavori della commissione<br />

ministeriale per lo studio della utilizzazione delle cellule staminali, “Medicina<br />

e Morale” 51 (2001), 101-125 (sugli embrioni soprannumerari 113-114);<br />

ID., II. I lavori della commissione ministeriale per lo studio della utilizzazione<br />

delle cellule staminali. La relazione di minoranza e le <strong>propos</strong>te emendative finali,<br />

“Medicina e Morale”, 51 (2001), 299-340 (sugli embrioni soprannumerari<br />

325-326). Il testo ufficiale, diffuso il 28-12-2000, in: http: //www.sanità.it/<br />

sanità/bacheca/cellstami/relazione-conclusiva. pdf.


104 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

Quanto si è detto circa la produzione di embrioni come fonte<br />

di cellule staminali non cambia sostanzialmente quando si<br />

parla di embrioni umani ottenuto per clonazione: le modalità attraverso<br />

le quali viene chiamato alla vita un nuovo essere umano<br />

non cambiano la qualità ontologica ed etica di questa esistenza.<br />

Come abbiamo visto nel primo paragrafo, è stata tentata sia<br />

la clonazione con trasferimento di nucleo da cellula umana in<br />

ovocita umano denucleato sia quella con trasferimento in ovocita<br />

di altro mammifero sia riprogrammando il nucleo di una cellula<br />

attraverso la fusione con il citoplasma di una cellula staminale<br />

embrionale. In ogni caso si tratta della produzione di nuove<br />

unità biologiche, nel secondo caso addirittura di un individuo<br />

chimerico, attraverso la clonazione di un intero individuo.<br />

È stata introdotta una distinzione fra clonazione terapeutica e<br />

clonazione procreativa e si è anzi <strong>propos</strong>to di riservare il termine<br />

clonazione alla sola clonazione riproduttiva per evitare le difficoltà<br />

morali e l’istintiva ripulsa connessa con la clonazione umana, indicando<br />

la clonazione terapeutica come cell nuclear replacement o<br />

sostituzione del nucleo della cellula 47 . Ovviamente dal punto di vista<br />

etico, le finalità perseguite nel dare la vita ad un essere umano<br />

siano esse finalità procreative o strumentali, non mutano il<br />

giudizio sulle tecniche di clonazione applicate all’uomo.<br />

Le perplessità intorno alla clonazione umana sono molteplici<br />

e non possiamo qui addentrarci nell’intricata discussione 48 .<br />

47 SOLTER D., GEARHART J., Putting stem cells to work, 1470: “To avoid these<br />

difficulties, it would be much better to reserve the term cloning to describe<br />

reproductive cloning”. La terminologia alternativa si riferisce all’evento<br />

cruciale della clonazione, cioè il trasferimento del nucleo di una cellula somatica<br />

in una cellula uovo denucleata e la successiva attivazione dello zigote<br />

o embrione unicellulare così ottenuto.<br />

48 Per un esame dei termini del dibattito: RUSSO G., La clonazione di soggetti<br />

umani. Uno studio bioetico per sperimentatori e animatori della società.<br />

Parte I, “Itinerarium” 4 (1996), 153-180; ID., La clonazione di soggetti umani.<br />

Riflessioni bioetiche, norme sociali e giuridiche. Parte II, “Itinerarium” 5<br />

(1997), 125-151; SCHOCKENHOFF E., L’uomo come la pecora? Riflessioni teologico-etiche<br />

sull’utilizzo della tecnologia genetica, “Concilium” 34 (1998), 2,<br />

129-139; SERRA A., Verso la clonazione dell’uomo? Una nuova frontiera della<br />

scienza, “Civiltà Cattolica” 149/1 (1998), 224-234; ID., La clonazione umana


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 105<br />

Pur dichiarandoci contrari a qualsiasi forma di clonazione umana<br />

per qualsivoglia scopo, non abbiamo dubbi ad affermare che,<br />

se una forma di clonazione può vantare ancora qualche giustificazione<br />

razionale, si tratterebbe della clonazione procreativa.<br />

Nella riproduzione per clonazione si nega il legame antropologico<br />

fra la trasmissione della vita e la relazionalità umana, singolarmente<br />

espressa dal legame matrimoniale, e si occulta, a livello<br />

intenzionale, anche se non a quello ontologico, l’unicità irripetibile<br />

o – se si vuole – la libertà esistenziale della persona: il<br />

figlio non si configura più come l’incarnarsi di una relazione interpersonale<br />

intima e totalizzante e quindi come il raggiungimento<br />

della propria perpetuazione attraverso un superamento<br />

dell’onnipotenza narcisistica nella comunione coniugale, ma diventa<br />

proiezione grandiosa del sé in un infinito gioco di specchi<br />

e di autoreferenze. Nonostante questa radicale stortura, la clonazione<br />

procreativa mantiene una qualche connessione con l’atto<br />

umano del generare perché tende a porre in essere un creatura<br />

affinchè esista e quindi ne ammette, sia pure in modo oscuro<br />

e contraddittorio, la autonomia e ne riconosce, pur nella innaturalità<br />

antropologica del processo tecnologico impiegato, la dignità<br />

personale.<br />

La clonazione terapeutica, invece – come si legge nel Documento<br />

del Centro di Bioetica dell’Università Cattolica – “stravolge<br />

il significato umano della generazione, non più pensata ed attuata<br />

per scopi riproduttivi, ma programmata per finalità medico-sperimentali<br />

(e perciò anche commerciali)”. In essa la negazione<br />

del senso umano della generazione è radicale: nella generazione,<br />

comunque avvenga, si vuole porre in atto un’esistenza<br />

umana, nella clonazione terapeutica e in ogni forma di procreazione<br />

finalizzata ad analoghi scopi strumentali si vuole distruggere<br />

un’esistenza dopo averle conferito una vita effimera. Perciò<br />

“a fronte di questo atto clonatorio – si legge in un recente Documento<br />

della Pontificia Academia Pro Vita – e delle sue conseguenze<br />

sull’embrione umano, il giudizio morale è di assoluta<br />

inaccettabilità… La generazione per clonazione di un individuo<br />

in prospettiva “sapienziale”, “Civiltà Cattolica” 149/1 (1998), 329-339. Vedere,<br />

inoltre: PONTIFICIA ACADEMIA PRO VITA, Riflessioni sulla clonazione, 25-6-1997,<br />

“Medicina e Morale” 47 (1997), 978-983.


106 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

umano al fine di utilizzarlo come fonte di cellule staminali… è<br />

un’azione indegna della persona umana perché si oppone al suo<br />

bene e nessuna intenzione buona o circostanza particolare è capace<br />

di cancellarne la malizia” 49 .<br />

Anche potendosi escludere la soppressione del clono, il discendente<br />

per clonazione di un soggetto “sarà un individuo<br />

umano a pieno titolo, e non è lecito farlo venire al mondo con il<br />

fine primario di essere un donatore d’organi. Pertanto – conclude<br />

il Comitato Nazionale per la Bioetica italiano – anche volendo<br />

ipotizzare una clonazione di individui umani a fini terapeutici,<br />

questa non appare in generale moralmente ammissibile” 50 .<br />

L’universale contrarietà alla clonazione umana, sancita in documenti<br />

pubblici di notevole rilievo e autorità 51 , mostra segni di cedimento<br />

quando si passa a considerare separatamente il caso della<br />

clonazione terapeutica. Nel sopra citato Documento della Consulta<br />

della Geron, per esempio, si esclude con forza la clonazione riproduttiva,<br />

ovviamente per poter introdurre l’idea della legittimità di<br />

quella terapeutica 52 . Nel Regno Unito, dove già è permessa la produzione<br />

di embrioni al solo scopo di ricerca, il Rapporto della<br />

Commissione Donaldson ha aperto la strada alla clonazione terapeutica<br />

di esseri umani per ricavarne cellule staminali 53 .<br />

49 PONTIFICIA ACADEMIA PRO VITA, Cellule staminali umane autologhe e trasferimento<br />

di nucleo, Osservatore Romano 5-1-2001, 6 (anche “Medicina e<br />

Morale”, 2001,1, 141-142). Cfr. GIOVANNI PAOLO II, Discorso al XVIII International<br />

Congress of the Transplantation Society, Roma 29-8-2000, “Osservatore<br />

Romano”, 30-8-2000, 1); CONGR. DOTTR. FEDE, Istruzione Donum Vitae, 22-2-<br />

1987, I, 6, AAS 1988, 80, 84-85.<br />

50 COMITATO NAZIONALE PER LA BIOETICA, La clonazione, Roma 1998, 35.<br />

51 OMS, Déclaration sur le clonage, 18-3-1997, “Medicina e Morale” 47<br />

(1997), 323-325; PARLAMENTO EUROPEO, Risoluzione sulla clonazione, 15-1-<br />

1998, “Medicina e Morale” 48 (1998), 167-168; UNESCO, Déclaration universelle<br />

sur le génome humain et les droits de l’homme, 11-11-1997, “Medicina<br />

e Morale” 48 (1998), 158-166.<br />

52 GERON ETHICS ADVISORY BOARD, Research with Human Embryonic Stem<br />

Cells, 36: “3. La ricerca non includerà nessuna clonazione finalizzata a riproduzione<br />

umana”.<br />

53 CHIEF MEDICAL OFFICIER’S EXPERT GROUP, Stem Cell Research: Medical<br />

Progress with Responsibility, Department of Health, London June 2000, 10:<br />

“Recommendation 1. Research using embryos (whether created by in vitro<br />

fertilisation or cell nuclear replacement) to increase understanding about


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 107<br />

È prevedibile che l’opinione pubblica, sotto la spinta dei<br />

mass media espressione degli enormi interessi economici che girano<br />

intorno all’affare delle cellule staminali 54 , si orienti a una<br />

maggiore condiscendenza verso la clonazione terapeutica e questo<br />

porti ad agggiustamenti legislativi in senso possibilista. La<br />

categoria di terapeuticità rappresenta l’usuale grimaldello retorico<br />

per sfondare sul versante emotivo le barriere etiche che risultano<br />

inespugnabili sul versante razionale e sottolineando la motivazione<br />

del progresso scientifico e delle applicazioni terapeutiche<br />

non sarà impossibile ammorbidire il divieto di clonazione<br />

umana, soprattutto se contenuta entro i limiti temporali dei fatidici<br />

quattordici giorni del pre-embrione. In secondo luogo si<br />

cerca di sviare la sensibilità del pubblico evitando semplicemente<br />

il termine clonazione e ricorrendo – come fa lo stesso Rapporto<br />

Donaldson – al criptico equivalente sostituzione di nucleo<br />

della cellula. A ciò si aggiunga che molti di coloro che sostengono<br />

la legittimità della produzione di cloni da tenersi in serbo come<br />

possibile banca tissutale per eventuali necessità future, sembrano<br />

implicare una persuasione alquanto discutibile che cioè il<br />

clono di un individuo ottenuto mediante trasferimento nucleare<br />

altro non sia che una espansione o una copia biologica dell’individuo<br />

stesso e che perciò la copia sia in qualche modo disponibile<br />

per l’originale. Sarebbe l’individuo di partenza che si continua<br />

nel suo clono e quindi usare il clono per curare una malattia<br />

del soggetto di partenza sarebbe del tutto legittimo, trattandosi,<br />

a ben guardare, di una forma sofisticata di autotrapianto.<br />

Purtroppo la realtà è ben diversa: anche restando su un piano<br />

puramente biologico, la condivisione di un comune patrimonio<br />

genetico non comporta l’indistinzione fra due oggetti biologici<br />

autonomamente viventi, così come la condivisione del patrimonio<br />

genetico non fa di due gemelli monozigoti un solo individuo.<br />

Il clono è un essere umano distinto dal suo originale genetico,<br />

pur condividendone il patrimonio genetico, e questo si realizza<br />

human disease and disorders and their cell-base treatments should be permitted”.<br />

Il testo del documento in: http:// www.doh.gov.uk./cegc.<br />

54 Gli interessi economici in gioco sono enormi e lo sfruttamento delle<br />

scoperte pone importanti questioni di giustizia. Cfr. CAHILL L., The New Biotech<br />

World Order, “Hastings Center Report” 29 (1999), 2, 45-48.


108 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

dal momento in cui il clono funziona come unità biologica autofunzionante,<br />

all’attivazione (con ioni Sr 2+ o con impulsi elettrici)<br />

dello zigote che è stato ottenuto con il transfer nucleare.<br />

In conclusione, il prelievo di cellule staminali da pre-embrioni,<br />

embrioni e feti, in quanto comporta la soppressione di<br />

una vita umana innocente, non è moralmente accettabile. La<br />

produzione di embrioni mediante clonazione per trarne cellule<br />

e tessuti (clonazione terapeutica) è moralmente illecita, aggiungendo<br />

al disordine della riproduzione per clonazione, la distruzione<br />

dell’esistenza così prodotta. Nel caso della clonazione attaverso<br />

la formazione di embrioni chimerici si ha l’aggravante<br />

della lesione dell’intregrità onto-biologica e della dignità propria<br />

dell’essere umano e della sua generazione. Non è neppure lecito<br />

per un ricercatore o un medico usare cellule staminali embrionali<br />

o cellule staminali adulte, ma derivate da queste, eventualmente<br />

fornite da altri ricercatori o reperibili in commercio perché<br />

“al di là della condivisione, formale o meno, dell’intenzione<br />

moralmente illecita dell’agente principale, nel caso in esame c’è<br />

una cooperazione materiale prossima da parte del produttore o<br />

fornitore” 55 .<br />

4. Lo statuto delle cellule staminali e la questione del<br />

TNSA<br />

Potrebbe stupire il netto confine che, implicitamente, abbiamo<br />

posto fra l’embrione precoce a partire dallo stadio monocellulare<br />

e la cellula staminale totipotente. Il fatto è che – secondo<br />

noi – l’embrione precoce sin dal concepimento deve essere rispettato<br />

come una persona, mentre una cellula staminale è e resta<br />

una cellula che non ha senso in sé, ma soltanto se riferita al<br />

tutto e che perciò non ha maggiore significato ontologico ed etico<br />

di una cellula, per esempio, dell’epidermide.<br />

Negli estenuanti dibattiti sullo status dell’embrione gli op-<br />

55 PONTIFICIA ACADEMIA PRO VITA, Dichiarazione sulla produzione e sull’uso<br />

scientifico e terapeutico delle cellule staminali embrionali umane, Libreria<br />

Editrice Vaticana, Città del Vaticano 2000, 17 (originale in “Osservatore Romano”,<br />

25-8-2000, 6).


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 109<br />

positori della tesi dell’individuazione biologica al concepimento<br />

– come il salesiano australiano N. Ford – sottolineano che, essendo<br />

tutte le cellule dell’embrione precoce totipotenti, esse possono<br />

subire l’embryo splitting e dare origine ad un altro embrione<br />

distinto dal primo e geneticamente identico e da questo deducono<br />

la indistinzione o mancata individualità del pre-embrione<br />

56 . I sostenitori dell’individualità al concepimento fanno notare<br />

che l’embrione precoce funziona come una unità vitale autorganizzata<br />

sin dal concepimento ed è quindi un individuo biologico,<br />

anche se conserva la possibilità di dare origine, per una<br />

forma di generazione asessuata che ricorda la gemmazione, un<br />

nuovo embrione inclusi gli annessi embrionali a partire da un<br />

blastomero totipotente che si rende autonomo dall’insieme ed<br />

inizia un proprio percorso esistenziale 57 . Ogni cellula embrionale<br />

totipotente, nel momento in cui si rende, per natura o per artificio,<br />

funzionalmente autonoma rappresenta l’inizio di una<br />

nuova individualità biologica.<br />

Una situazione strettamente affine è quella della cellula staminale<br />

embrionale ricavata dall’embrioblasto che però è totipotente<br />

solo nel senso che può dare origine virtualmente a tutti i<br />

tessuti embrionali, ma non a quelli degli annessi e che perciò<br />

meglio si direbbe pluripotente. Derivando dalle cellule dell’embrioblasto,<br />

che sono già orientate ad evolversi nel soma embrionario,<br />

esse da sole, infatti, non riescono a dare origine a un embrione<br />

completo dei suoi annessi. Gli studi più approfonditi in<br />

questo campo sono stati compiuti sulle cellule murine. È stato<br />

dimostrato che le cellule staminali embrionali di topo possono<br />

formare tutti i tipi cellulari dell’organismo, ma non sembra che,<br />

56 FORD N. M., When did I begin? Conception of the human individual in<br />

history, philosophy and science, Cambridge 1988 (trad. it. Quando comincio<br />

io? Il concepimento nella storia, nella filosofia e nella scienza, Milano 1997).<br />

Una analisi molto critica del volume in: SERRA A., “Quando è iniziata la mia<br />

vita?”, “Civiltà Cattolica” 140/4 (1989), 575-585.<br />

57 Sul problema della gemellarità: BATTISTON F., Lo statuto dell’embrione<br />

e il principio di potenzialità in bioetica, “<strong>Studia</strong> Patavina” 40 (1993), 603-604;<br />

CASPAR P., Individualisation génétique et gémellité: l’objection des jumeaux monozygotes,<br />

“Ethique” 4 (1992), 81-90; ZATTI M., Quando un pre-embrione esiste,<br />

si tratta di un altro embrione, “Medicina e Morale” 41 (1991), 781-788.


110 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

in condizioni normali, possano formare anche tutti i tessuti extraembrionari.<br />

Se però noi trasferiamo in una blastocisti tetraploide,<br />

che non può evolvere in un embrione maturo, cellule staminali<br />

embrionali normali di topo, queste danno origine a un<br />

embrione normale 58 . In altre parole, le cellule staminali embrionali<br />

derivate da blastocisti se sono lasciate a se stesse non hanno<br />

la capacità di evolvere verso un organismo completo, ma possono<br />

farlo se vengono poste in un ambiente che può fornire i necessari<br />

supporti biometabolici e influire sui regolatori intrinseci<br />

della pluripotenzialità 59 .<br />

La qualifica di totipotente viene dunque usata con due sfumature<br />

diverse: si applica sia alla cellula embrionale precoce<br />

che, staccata per fissione naturale o artificiale dalla massa embrionaria,<br />

può dare origine a un embrione completo (gemellazione<br />

o clonazione per embryo splitting); sia alla cellula embrionaria<br />

che, staccata dalla massa embrionaria, può dare origine a<br />

tutti i tessuti embrionari, ma non quelli extraembrionari, a meno<br />

di non essere inserita in una blastocisti funzionante. In attesa<br />

di nuovi e più precisi dati, le cellule embrionali totipotenti comunque<br />

ottenute, sia da clonazione per trasferimento nucleare<br />

in ovocita, sia dalla massa embrionaria di una blastocisti, sembrano<br />

presentare sufficienti caratteri di autonomia biologica e<br />

di potenzialità evolutiva da far pensare a nuovi esseri in atto e<br />

come tali devono essere trattate, sino a evidenza contraria 60 .<br />

Ben diverso il caso di cellule staminali sia embrionali sia derivate<br />

da organismi post-natali che hanno le caratteristiche di<br />

essere pluripotenti, ma senza la capacità di dare spontaneamente<br />

origine – in condizioni normali - ad un nuovo essere autonomo.<br />

Nonostante la grande versatilità, si tratta di cellule ricondu-<br />

58<br />

NAGY A., ROSSANT J., NAGY R. et al., Derivation of completely cell culture-derived<br />

mice from early-passage embryonic stem cells, “Proceedings of the<br />

National Academy of Science U.S.A” 90 (1993), 8424-8428.<br />

59<br />

ROSSANT J., Stem cells from the Mammalian blastocyst, “Stem Cells” 19<br />

(2001), 477-482.<br />

60 Ci sembra interessante l’ipotesi interpretativa che potrebbe trattarsi<br />

viventi umani in condizioni di non viabilità. Cfr. SPAGNOLO A. G., SGRECCIA E.,<br />

Prelievi di organi e tessuti fetali a scopo di trapianto. Aspetti conoscitivi ed<br />

istanze etiche, 53.


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 111<br />

cibili ad un organismo pluricellulare e non di entità biologiche<br />

autonome e autoorganizzate.<br />

Per comprendere il nostro pensiero su questo punto, a scopo<br />

esemplificativo si potrebbe fare un esperimento mentale. Immaginiamo<br />

che si riescano a dominare completamente le dinamiche<br />

differenziative delle cellule e che sia possibile far regredire<br />

una cellula somatica verso lo stadio di cellula staminale e poi,<br />

indietro, allo stadio di cellula embrionale pluripotente e quindi<br />

allo stadio di cellula zigotica e da qui ricominciare l’avventura di<br />

una nuova vita individuale. Ci si domanda: se è lecito manipolare<br />

un cellula somatica sino a renderla pluripotente, perché dovrebbe<br />

essere illecito spingere il processo di sdifferenziazione sino<br />

a una cellula massimamente totipotente dalle potenzialità zigotiche?<br />

Dove collocare lo spartiacque etico della manipolazione<br />

sdifferenziativa delle cellule staminali?<br />

Lo spartiacque etico fra manipolazione lecita e illecita di cellule<br />

staminali umane si trova – teoricamente parlando – nella produzione<br />

di una unità biologica svincolata e autonomizzata rispetto<br />

all’organismo di provenienza. Sarà quindi lecito procedere a<br />

manipolazioni sdifferenziative che aumentino la plasmabilità<br />

delle cellule staminali, ma senza giungere ad originare uno zigote<br />

caratterizzato da intrinseche qualità autopoietiche, cioè<br />

senza giungere a porre in atto una nuova esistenza. A questo<br />

<strong>propos</strong>ito esiste un’illuminante analogia fra le cellule staminali<br />

e i gameti: il fatto che, attraverso interventi particolari una cellula<br />

staminale possa dare origine a uno zigote, non significa che<br />

quella cellula debba essere identificata biologicamente ed ontologicamente<br />

con uno zigote, così come i gameti che sono destinati<br />

a dare origine a una nuova vita, ma che, in quanto cellule<br />

isolate, non hanno la potenzialità di originare un nuovo individuo;<br />

analogamente alle cellule staminali, i gameti non sono infatti<br />

unità biologiche autoorganizzate e, come ogni cellula in un<br />

organismo pluricellulare, non hanno senso biologico se non in<br />

riferimento al tutto organico. Queste qualità biologiche sono invece<br />

possedute dallo zigote e, via via, dalla morula e poi blastocisti<br />

e così avanti.<br />

Sullo sfondo di queste riflessioni si colloca l’ipotesi di una<br />

via alternativa alla clonazione terapeutica che non comporti in<br />

nessun momento la formazione di embrioni, sia pure di embrioni<br />

monocellulari, ma che permetta di avere cellule stamina-


112 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

li autologhe, cioè con lo stesso patrimonio genetico del ricevente<br />

e quindi perfettamente istocompatibili. Si è parlato a questo<br />

<strong>propos</strong>ito di clonazione incompleta, in cui si ha la produzione di<br />

cellule staminali geneticamente identiche alle cellule somatiche<br />

di un soggetto adulto, ma senza passare attraverso la produzione<br />

di embrioni clonati 61 . Tale clonazione incompleta potrebbe<br />

essere ottenuta o prelevando da un tessuto del soggetto cellule<br />

idonee, staminali o somatiche, che verrebbero sottoposte in coltura<br />

a un processo di sdifferenziamento e che poi sarebbero<br />

orientate a differenziarsi nella direzione voluta con l’impiego di<br />

opportuni fattori di differenziamento 62 o trasferendo il nucleo di<br />

una cellula somatica in una cellula staminale denucleata, per ottenere<br />

una cellula staminale con i caratteri genetici del donatore<br />

del nucleo 63 .<br />

Potrebbe non essere immediatamente perspicua la differenza<br />

fra il trasferimento di un nucleo da una cellula somatica in un<br />

ovocita denucleato, come si ha nella clonazione, e il trasferimento<br />

del medesimo nucleo in una cellula staminale denucleata.<br />

Nel primo caso – come la clonazione ha ormai ampiamente<br />

dimostrato – si dà inizio ad una nuova esistenza biologica autonoma,<br />

si pone in essere una nuova unità biologica autopoietica<br />

del tutto indistinguibile, per quanto ci è dato di sapere, da uno<br />

zigote frutto della fertilizzazione di un ovocita da parte di uno<br />

spermatozoo. Ogni volta che ci troviamo di fronte ad una vita riferibile<br />

alla sottospecie Homo sapiens sapiens, biologicamente<br />

autoorganizzata e autofinalizzata, comunque essa sia stata originata,<br />

essa esige la nostra attenzione etica e il nostro rispetto.<br />

Nel secondo caso abbiamo invece la produzione di una cellula<br />

staminale modificata, con i caratteri genetici della cellula da cui<br />

61 Traggo l’espressione clonazione incompleta da R. Dulbecco che la usa<br />

in riferimento ai protocolli di sdifferenziamento cellulare: DULBECCO R., Fermare<br />

o regolare il processo?, in DULBECCO R. et al., Clonazione: problemi etici<br />

e prospettive scientifiche, 41<br />

62 All’inizio del 2001 è stata data notizia dalle Agenzie di stampa della<br />

scoperta, fatta a Cambridge, di una procedura che permette la retrodifferenziazione<br />

di globuli bianchi adulti nelle corrispondenti cellule staminali.<br />

63 In questo senso: COLMAN A., KIND A., Therapeutic cloning: Concepts<br />

and practicalities, “Trends in Biotechnology” 18 ( 2000), 192-196.


LAVORARE CON LE CELLULE STAMINALI 113<br />

proviene il nucleo, ma con le caratteristiche biologiche delle cellule<br />

staminali che, per quanto versatili, si è visto che non hanno<br />

la capacità di dare origine ad un embrione e che non gode del<br />

medesimo statuto ontologico ed etico.<br />

Rimane invece oscuro in che modo il trasferimento nucleare<br />

per la produzione di cellule staminali autologhe (TNSA) possa differire<br />

da una comune clonazione. Secondo la Commissione Ministeriale<br />

Italiana – che ha <strong>propos</strong>to questa “via italiana alla clonazione”<br />

– è possibile riprogrammare il nucleo di cellule somatiche<br />

prelevate dal paziente tramite il contatto con un oocita enucleato<br />

ed il risultato dell’operazione non sarebbe uno zigote capace<br />

di maturare in embrione, ma un oocita ricostituito capace di<br />

evolvere, sotto stimoli opportuni, in sfere embrioidi ricche in cellule<br />

staminali. Non è chiaro in base a quali evidenze empiriche<br />

un oocita ricostituito non sia del tutto analogo a un embrione<br />

monocellulare o zigote prodotto artificialmente, né come si possano<br />

formare sfere embrioidi senza passare per embrioni più<br />

semplici, dato che, fino ad oggi, per ottenere in vitro corpi embrioidi<br />

e isolare da essi specifiche linee cellulari si è sempre dovuti<br />

passare attraverso cellule staminali derivate dall’embrione.<br />

Allo stato attuale delle conoscenze la TNSA resta pertanto<br />

una ipotesi seducente non rafforzata da certezze sperimentali e<br />

non ben inquadrabile nelle attuali conoscenze sulle cellule staminali.<br />

Nel dubbio di trovarsi di fronte a una forma di vera clonazione<br />

umana, è doveroso astenersi da applicarla all’uomo, nell’attesa<br />

che nuovi dati e acquisizioni possano fornire la necessaria<br />

sicurezza pratica.<br />

Per ora, la vera alternativa all’uso di cellule embrionali sta<br />

nel ricorso alle cellule del cordone ombelicale e soprattutto alle<br />

cellule staminali da soggetto adulto. Secondo una letteratura<br />

scientifica che si fa ogni giorno più imponente, le speranze offerte<br />

dalle cellule staminali adulte sono ormai paragonabili a<br />

quelle offerte dalle cellule staminali embrionali, se non forse superiori<br />

64 e ci sono notizie di varie ditte farmaceutiche che hanno<br />

64 Cfr. CHIEF MEDICAL OFFICIER’S EXPERT GROUP, Stem Cell Research: Medical<br />

Progress with Responsibility, 19: “Par. 2.14. In may be that the long term<br />

promise of stem cells derived from adult tissue will equal or even surpass<br />

that of embryonic stem cells”.


114 MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI<br />

in corso importanti sperimentazioni cliniche con esse 65 . La Pontificia<br />

Accademia per la Vita indica tale via come “la più ragionevole<br />

e umana da percorrere per un corretto e valido progresso in<br />

questo campo che si apre alla ricerca e a promettenti applicazioni<br />

terapeutiche” 66 .<br />

Commentando questo testo la dottoressa Di Pietro saggiamente<br />

conclude:<br />

La via più ragionevole e umana: questo non significa, come<br />

qualcuno si ostina a scrivere, chiudere la porta di fronte alla sofferenza<br />

di chi, essendo malato, aspetta una risposta dalla scienza,<br />

ma far sì che la speranza diventi realtà senza il sacrificio di<br />

altre vite umane 67 .<br />

PROF. MAURIZIO PIETRO FAGGIONI, OFM<br />

—————<br />

The author is associate Professor of Bioethics at the Alphonsian<br />

Academy.<br />

El autor es profesor asociado de Bioética en la Academia<br />

Alfonsiana.<br />

—————<br />

65<br />

MARSHALL E., The business of stem cells, “Science” 287 (2000), 1419-<br />

1421.<br />

66<br />

PONTIFICIA ACADEMIA PRO VITA, Dichiarazione sulla produzione e sull’uso<br />

scientifico e terapeutico delle cellule staminali embrionali umane, 17.<br />

67<br />

DI PIETRO M. L., MINACORI R., Cellule staminali: una questione aperta,<br />

67.


StMor 40 (2002) 115-141<br />

JOHN BERKMAN<br />

THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS<br />

IN LIGHT OF DONUM VITAE<br />

In at least some instances, the choice by Catholic women to<br />

adopt cryopreserved human embryos who have been abandoned<br />

by their biological parents is compatible with current Catholic<br />

teaching on assisted reproduction, on surrogate motherhood,<br />

and on the family. While a variety of potential circumstances<br />

may rule out this practice in some situations, the view that it is<br />

morally acceptable in some circumstances and morally praiseworthy<br />

in others is consonant with current Catholic teaching on<br />

the appropriate reverence and respect for human life from conception<br />

until natural death.<br />

The most extensive and authoritative evaluation of the status<br />

of and protection to be accorded to early embryos from the<br />

teaching office of the Catholic church is to be found in the<br />

Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith’s (CDF) Instruction<br />

on Respect for Human Life in its origin and on the Dignity of<br />

Procreation, more widely referred to as Donum vitae (DV). 1 Near<br />

the beginning of DV, the CDF notes that it makes free use of a<br />

variety of biological terms (e.g. “zygote”, “pre-embryo”,<br />

“embryo” and “foetus”) to refer to the embryo in its various<br />

stages of development. However, it sees no relevant moral distinction<br />

between these stages, as all “designate the result<br />

(whether visible or not) of human generation, from the first<br />

1 Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Instruction on Respect for<br />

Human Life in its origin and on the Dignity of Procreation, February 22, 1987:<br />

Acta Apostolicae Sedis 80 (1988), 70-102. Henceforth cited as DV with section<br />

numbers. English translations of DV are taken from Origins, vol. 16, no. 40<br />

(March 19, 1987), 697-711, unless otherwise noted.


116 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

moment of its existence until birth.” 2 At all stages of life from<br />

conception on, human life is deserving of absolute protection.<br />

As DV puts it:<br />

From the moment of conception, the life of every human<br />

being is to be respected in an absolute way … Human life is sacred<br />

because from its beginning it involves “the creative action of God”<br />

and it remains forever in a special relationship with the Creator,<br />

who is its sole end. God alone is the Lord of life from its beginning<br />

until its end: no one can, in any circumstance, claim for himself the<br />

right to destroy directly an innocent human being. 3<br />

Since the publication of DV, there has been a vigorous<br />

debate in Catholic theology on the status of the embryo in the<br />

earliest stages after conception, and the further implications of<br />

the alternative viewpoints. 4 While an important debate, an<br />

extended discussion of the various viewpoints is beyond the<br />

scope of this paper. At present, the embryological and theological<br />

arguments articulated in DV find numerous credible defenders.<br />

Since this paper is an evaluation of embryo adoption in the<br />

2 DV, Foreword, footnote #1. The full footnote reads as follows: “Voces<br />

‘zygotum’, ‘prae-embryon’, ‘embryon’, ‘fetus’, iuxta usum in disciplina biologica<br />

receptum, indicare possunt succedentia tempora in viventis humani processu<br />

ad suam maturitatem assequendam. Haec Instructio libere his vocibus utitur,<br />

eis tribuens eandem ethicam aestimationem ad significandum fructum,<br />

vitae autonomae capacem vel non, generationis humanae, a primo eius vitae<br />

momento usque ad nativitatem. Ratio huius ex ipso textu patebit.”<br />

3 DV, Introduction, 5. “Inde a conceptionis momento, vita cuiusvis<br />

humanae creaturae omnino est observanda … Humana vita pro re sacra<br />

habenda est, quippe quae inde a suo exordio ‘Creatoris actionem postulet’ ac<br />

semper peculiari necessitudine cum Creatore, unico fine suo, perstet conexa.<br />

Solus Deus vitae Dominus est ab exordio usque ad exitum: nemo, in nullus<br />

rerum adiunctis, sibi vindicare potest ius mortem humanae creaturae innocenti<br />

directe afferendi.”<br />

4 Questions have been raised about the ontological and moral status of<br />

the embryo in its earliest stages in e.g. Shannon and Wolter (1990). Their<br />

embryological arguments are analyzed in Johnson (1995). Johnson’s views<br />

are evaluated in Porter (1995). The embryological views of DV are defended<br />

by e.g. Doerflinger (1999) and Ashley and Moraczewski (2001).


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 117<br />

light of DV, DV’s embryological views will be presumed without<br />

further argumentation.<br />

1. Does Donum Vitae directly prohibit embryo adoption?<br />

In the last seven years, there have been a number of analyses<br />

regarding whether married couples (and in some cases<br />

unmarried women) can licitly “adopt” a frozen embryo. Prior to<br />

the widespread publicity generated by the destruction of<br />

embryos in the U.K. in 1996, one Catholic theologian had<br />

already examined the morality of embryo adoption in relation to<br />

his understanding of DV. In a question-and-answer section of<br />

his monthly column of the October 1995 issue of the Homiletic<br />

and Pastoral Review, William Smith responded to a question<br />

from a Catholic couple who wished to consider the possibility of<br />

adopting a frozen embryo who had been abandoned. 5 Smith<br />

argued, albeit tentatively, that it was not licit for a couple to “rescue”<br />

a frozen embryo, and his response was drawn for the most<br />

part from his interpretation of the teaching of DV. 6 More specifically,<br />

Smith’s response hinged on his interpretation of what I<br />

will refer to as the “cannot be licitly pursued” sentence from DV.<br />

That sentence from DV reads as follows:<br />

In consequence of the fact that they have been produced in<br />

vitro, those embryos which are not transferred into the body of the<br />

mother and are called “spare” are exposed to an absurd fate [sorti<br />

absurdae obnoxii permanent], with no possibility of their being<br />

offered safe means of survival which can be licitly pursued.” 7<br />

5 In this case, it is clear that the embryo is not of the couple’s own making<br />

and that the couple oppose in vitro fertilization (IVF). It is also fairly<br />

clear that the couple were not in any other way party to the creation and<br />

abandonment of the embryo, but enter the situation as people trying to<br />

respond in a morally appropriate way to what they see to be an ongoing<br />

morally problematic situation.<br />

6 See also Smith’s comments in Caulfield (1998), pp. 1, 15.<br />

7 DV, I, 5. “Eo quod in vitro producti sunt, hi embryones, qui in matris<br />

corpus non translati ‘supranumerarii’ vocantur, sorti absurdae obnoxii per-


118 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

Smith concluded from the final phrase of this sentence –<br />

“can[not] be licitly pursued” – that Donum vitae ruled out the<br />

possibility of embryo adoption.<br />

In order to evaluate whether one can reasonably conclude<br />

that the “cannot be licitly pursued” sentence in DV is referring<br />

to the adoption of embryos, it is necessary to note the sentence’s<br />

context, especially its intended audience. The sentence occurs in<br />

Part I of DV, the goal of which is to articulate the respect due to<br />

human embryos in general. More specifically, the section in<br />

which it occurs (i.e. the fifth section of Part I) is discussing a<br />

rather specific sub-group of embryos. This particular section is<br />

addressed to researchers who experiment on human embryos<br />

that have been created through in vitro fertilization (IVF). 8 In<br />

the sentences immediately prior to the “cannot be licitly pursued”<br />

sentence, DV condemns two specific kinds of acts: first,<br />

the production in vitro of embryos that have been created specifically<br />

for the purpose of experimentation; second, the destruction<br />

of these embryos.<br />

It is immoral to produce human embryos destined to be exploited<br />

as disposable “biological material.”<br />

In the usual practice of in vitro fertilization, not all of the<br />

embryos are transferred to the woman’s body; some are destroyed.<br />

Just as the Church condemns induced abortion, so she also forbids<br />

acts against the life of these human beings. It is a duty to condemn<br />

the particular gravity of the voluntary destruction of human embryos<br />

obtained ‘in vitro’ for the sole purpose of research … By acting in this<br />

way the researcher usurps the place of God; and, even though he<br />

may be unaware of this, he sets himself up as the master of the destiny<br />

of others inasmuch as he arbitrarily chooses whom he will<br />

allow to live and whom he will send to death and kills defenceless<br />

manent, quippe quibus securae viae non pateant ad superstitem vitam, quas<br />

ingredi liceat.”<br />

8 After the introductory section, Part I of DV is entitled “Respect for<br />

Human Embryos.” Section 5 of Part I, a section of about ten sentences and<br />

the one from which Smith quotes, is entitled “ How is one to evaluate morally<br />

the use for research purposes of embryos obtained by fertilization ‘in<br />

vitro’?”


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 119<br />

human beings …. It is therefore not in conformity with the moral law<br />

deliberately to expose to death human embryos obtained ‘in vitro’. 9<br />

Through an evaluation of this section of DV, one thing<br />

becomes clear. The actions and intentions being condemned in<br />

this section are those of researchers who create, experiment on,<br />

and destroy human embryos. There is no evidence that this section<br />

is referring to the actions and intentions of persons who<br />

wish to protect or aid already existing cryopreserved human<br />

embryos.<br />

Misunderstanding as to what DV claims “cannot be licitly<br />

pursued” arises from confusion with regards to the meaning of<br />

“spare” in the key sentence. Whereas Smith seems to assume<br />

that “spare” refers to cryopreserved embryos that could be<br />

implanted in a mother’s womb, this is not the meaning of<br />

“spare” in DV. Although the first live birth from a cryopreserved<br />

human embryo had occurred in Australia in 1984, thus three<br />

years previously, DV is silent on the subject of the implantation<br />

and gestation of cryopreserved embryos. In fact, DV gives no<br />

indication that it recognizes that previously frozen embryos can<br />

– in a technical sense – be successfully implanted and gestated. 10<br />

By “spare” embryo DV is rather referring to embryos destined<br />

not to be implanted into the womb of a woman. Since the<br />

9 DV I, 5. Italics in original.<br />

“Morum igitur honestati contraium est embryones humanos gignere ad<br />

abutendum, scilicet ut efficiantur ‘materia biologica’, quae praesto sit ad<br />

usum.<br />

Modus, quo communiter fecundatio in vitro obtinetur, non sinit ut<br />

omnes embryones in corpus mulieris transferantur; eorum nonnulli interficiuntur.<br />

Quare Ecclesia, sicut abortum procuratum damnat, ita etiam prohibet,<br />

ne vita harum humanarum creaturarum attentetur. Conscientiae officium<br />

postulat, ut palam denuntietur peculiaris gravitas voluntariae interfectionis<br />

embryonum humanorum, qui in vitro obenti sunt ad solum investigationis<br />

finem… Hac agendi ratione investigator se in locum Dei substituit atque,<br />

licet inconscius, se efficit dominum aliorum sortis, quippe qui arbitratu suo<br />

decernat quis vivat et quis morte afficiatur, idemque creaturas humanas<br />

interficiat, quae defensione carent…<br />

Moralibus igitur normis contradicitur, si data opera embryones humani<br />

in vitro producti morti exponuntur.”


120 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

embryos are not being given an opportunity to be gestated by a<br />

human mother, they are being exposed to an “absurd fate.” For<br />

such embryos are destined to destruction, either immediately, or<br />

after being used for experimental purposes.<br />

That is the broad context of Donum vitae I, 5. But what of<br />

the reference to the embryos “not transferred into the body of<br />

the mother”? Here the difficulty arises from confusion between<br />

a descriptive declaration and a prescriptive claim. Whereas<br />

some interpret the passage as having a prescriptive intent (i.e.<br />

prohibiting the transfer of embryos), the sentence in fact presumes<br />

that the embryos being discussed are not being (as<br />

opposed to “should not be”) transferred into the body of a<br />

woman. 11 In other words, the point of this section is to assert<br />

that if there is not a human womb to gestate the embryo, there<br />

is no morally licit means by which the embryo can be gestated.<br />

What alternatives to implanting embryos in the wombs of<br />

human mothers does the document have in mind? In the sentence<br />

immediately following the “cannot be licitly pursued” sentence,<br />

DV rejects “attempts or plans for fertilization between<br />

human and animal gametes and the gestation of human<br />

embryos in the uterus[es] of animals, or the hypothesis or project<br />

of constructing artificial uteruses for the human embryo.” 12<br />

10 DV does refer explicitly at two points to issues surrounding the cryopreservation<br />

of human embryos. In the context of a discussion of experimental<br />

manipulations of the embryo, DV condemns the act of freezing<br />

embryos (DV I, 6). DV’s only explicit reference to frozen embryos refers to<br />

those which are not transferred into the genital tracts of the woman and<br />

which are “utiliz[ed] for different purposes to the detriment of their integrity<br />

and life,” i.e. frozen for non-therapeutic experimental purposes (DV, II).<br />

Also, when DV calls for legislation prohibiting “embryo banks” (DV, III), the<br />

embryos being kept in such banks are presumably cryopreserved, and presumably<br />

kept in such banks to be made available for experimental purposes.<br />

11 DV uses the term “mother,” but it is unclear what that term signifies,<br />

for once ET takes place, the woman is a mother or mother-to-be, whether or<br />

not she is also the biological mother, a surrogate mother, a gestational mother,<br />

and/or an adoptive mother.<br />

12 A few sentences later, DV articulates its objection to the cryopreservation<br />

of human embryos. Situated as it is in this particular context, this<br />

objection should not be taken to be a general objection to the cryopreserva-


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 121<br />

DV is ruling out the crossing of human gametes with those of<br />

other mammals – “genetic bestiality” so to speak – and attempts<br />

to gestate human embryos outside of a human womb.<br />

Thus, we may conclude that the fifth section of Part I of DV<br />

analyzes and morally evaluates the <strong>propos</strong>ed actions of<br />

researchers who see human embryos as mere means for attaining<br />

knowledge, and not as human beings who deserve unconditional<br />

respect for their lives and their physical integrity. This section<br />

is not addressing the morality of embryo transfer (ET) with<br />

regard to already-existing and abandoned cryopreserved<br />

embryos. As such, it cannot be legitimately interpreted as directly<br />

prohibiting the possibility of adopting a cryopreserved<br />

embryo. Furthermore, the question of what can be done with<br />

already created and cryopreserved embryos is nowhere else<br />

addressed in DV. 13<br />

tion of human embryos in all situations. Once one acknowledges that<br />

embryo cryopreservation could, in some circumstances, be undertaken for<br />

therapeutic benefit of the embryo itself, it is clear that there can be no principled<br />

rejection of this technique.<br />

13 The possibility of cryopreserving embryos is only mentioned in two<br />

places in DV (i.e. I,6 and II, 1). In I, 6, DV says that cryopreservation of<br />

embryos “even when carried out in order to preserve the life of an embryo …<br />

constitutes an offence against the respect due to human beings” because of<br />

(at least what was in 1987 likely to be) grave harm or death to them through<br />

this procedure. However, this passage should not be interpreted as ruling out<br />

the possibility of such cryopreservation in circumstances where it would<br />

likely be of therapeutic benefit and enhance the possibility of the embryo<br />

being gestated to term. For DV also says “In the case of experimentation that<br />

is clearly therapeutic, namely, when it is a mattter of experimental forms of<br />

therapy used for the benefit of the embryo itself in a final attempt to save its<br />

life, and in the absence of other reliable forms of therapy, recourse to … procedures<br />

not yet fully tested can be licit.” (I,4) Furthermore, I take it that the<br />

sentence from DV I, 6 quoted above presumes that the cryopreserved<br />

embryos of which it is speaking are not going to be gestated, and such cryopreservation<br />

only extends their dying and subjects them to “further<br />

offences and manipulation.”


122 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

2. Is Embryo Adoption wrong in principle?<br />

If Donum vitae neither prohibits nor even addresses the<br />

morality of adopting frozen embryos, one can still ask whether<br />

the adoption of previously frozen embryos would be ruled out by<br />

the principles articulated in DV. To begin with, it is worth noting<br />

that DV does not rule out ET of already created embryos into<br />

the body of a woman – even when they are created with donor<br />

ova and/or sperm. This at least provides prima facie evidence<br />

that embryo adoption cannot be ruled out in advance as wrong<br />

in principle. 14 For while DV clearly prohibits the technological<br />

procedure known as IVF-ET as morally wrong in principle, its<br />

chief objection is not to the transfer of the already-created<br />

embryo into the body of the woman (i.e. the ET), but to the very<br />

creation of these embryos (i.e. the IVF). 15<br />

One can certainly imagine a variety of scenarios where ET<br />

would be morally unproblematic. For example, it would certain-<br />

14 For instance, a close reading of the critique of heterologous IVF (i.e.<br />

conception using gametes of at least one person other than the spouses) in<br />

DV (see II.A.2) reveals that the critique is always directed at the means of<br />

conception of the child. At no place does the critique rule out ET once<br />

embryos have been created. Presumably, some individuals might come to see<br />

the wrongfulness of seeking to bring a child into the world through the<br />

process of IVF after the embryos have been conceived, but prior to implantation<br />

of them into a woman’s womb. Nowhere is it stated that the embryos<br />

created at the request of a woman or a couple should be abandoned after<br />

they have been conceived. Furthermore, the various statements in DV which<br />

might be interpreted as prohibiting embryo transfer would seem to require<br />

one to draw the additional (reductio ad absurdum) conclusion that all adoptions<br />

must be rejected, whether ordinary (post-natal) or pre-natal.<br />

15 In its evaluation of homologous ‘in vitro’ fertilization, DV typically<br />

groups homologous IVF and ET together, typically referring to the process<br />

as “IVF and ET” (DV, II, B, 5 passim). However, at the end of this section, DV<br />

states its objection only to IVF as “in itself illicit.” Thus, “… the Church<br />

remains opposed from the moral point of view to homologous ‘in vitro’ fertilization.<br />

Such fertilization is in itself illicit and in opposition to the dignity of<br />

procreation and of the conjugal union, even when everything is done to avoid<br />

the death of the human embryo” (DV, II, B, 5. Italics in original). This is not<br />

to say that ET is always morally appropriate or acceptable, but that it is not<br />

ruled out as “in itself illicit,” as is IVF.


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 123<br />

ly be appropriate to seek to transfer an embryo lodged in the fallopian<br />

tube (i.e. in an ectopic pregnancy) to the lining of the<br />

uterus. Furthermore, it would seem morally unproblematic if it<br />

were technically possible to temporarily remove an embryo<br />

from the uterine lining while a woman received, e.g., radiation<br />

therapy for cervical cancer, and then transfer it back to the<br />

uterus to continue its gestation. 16 Such interventions in the normal<br />

process of gestation when done for the unambiguous good<br />

of the embryo are not called into question in the tradition.<br />

Such a conclusion regarding interventions on behalf of the<br />

embryo are not at all surprising, for DV’s fundamental principle<br />

for reflection upon the treatment of embryos, invoked repeatedly<br />

at key points, is: “Human life must be absolutely respected<br />

and protected from the moment of conception.” 17 Although DV<br />

argues that it is wrong in principle to create embryos in vitro,<br />

once created an embryo “must be treated as a person” and thus<br />

“tended and cared for, to the extent possible, in the same way as<br />

any other human being.” 18 On the basis of this principle, one fol-<br />

16 These are largely imaginary scenarios. However, there is at least one<br />

recorded case where it has been claimed that an embryo has been successfully<br />

transferred from the fallopian tube to the lining of the uterus. It is certainly<br />

possible that such transfers will become increasingly common as medical<br />

techniques continue to develop.<br />

17 DV, I, 1. DV quotes this sentence from the Holy See, Charter of the<br />

Rights of the Family, 4: L’Osservatore Romano, 25 November 1983.<br />

18 DV I, 1. The fifth section is to be read in the context of the first section,<br />

which articulates more generally the respect due to human embryos.<br />

The first section begins by stating “The human being must be respected – as a<br />

person – from the very first instant of his existence.” It then goes on to note<br />

that it is aware “of the current debates concerning the beginning of human<br />

life … and concerning the identity of the human person,” and that while “no<br />

experimental datum can be in itself sufficient to bring us to the recognition<br />

of a spiritual soul … how could a human individual not be a human person?”<br />

The section concludes by claiming that “[t]he human being is to be respected<br />

and treated as a person from the moment of conception; and therefore<br />

from that same moment his rights as a person must be recognized, among<br />

which in the first place is the inviolable right of every innocent human being<br />

to life. This doctrinal reminder provides the fundamental criterion for the<br />

solution of the various problems posed by the development of the biomedical<br />

sciences in this field: since the embryo must be treated as a person, it


124 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

lowing DV would have at least a prima facie basis for providing<br />

these cryopreserved embryos with an opportunity to be gestated<br />

and given birth to by morally acceptable means.<br />

But there have also been a number of arguments put forward<br />

claiming that embryo adoption is wrong in principle.<br />

Interestingly, all of those who raise these objections acknowledge<br />

that the embryos are in fact worthy of protection. The<br />

objections are that, for one reason or another, a woman cannot<br />

agree to gestate an (abandoned) embryo without consenting to<br />

an action that is morally wrong in principle. We will consider<br />

three arguments as to the nature of this wrong, namely, that it<br />

requires the woman (or the couple) to a) become a surrogate<br />

mother, b) sin against the virtue of chastity, or c) continue participation<br />

in the wrongfulness of IVF.<br />

(i) Is Embryo Adoption a Form of Surrogacy?<br />

While surrogacy is as old as Abraham, Sarah and Hagar, and<br />

has undoubtedly been a part of many cultures, it is at least today<br />

perceived as an affront both to the dignity of the surrogate, and<br />

to the best interests of the child. In order to evaluate whether<br />

embryo adoption is a form of surrogacy, we must understand<br />

what, morally speaking, constitutes surrogate motherhood.<br />

Donum vitae provides a precise definition, claiming that either<br />

of the following two scenarios constitutes surrogate motherhood:<br />

a) the woman who carries in pregnancy an embryo implanted<br />

in her uterus and who is genetically a stranger to the embryo<br />

because it has been obtained through the union of the gametes of<br />

“donors.” She carries the pregnancy with a pledge to surrender the<br />

baby once it is born to the party who commissioned or made the<br />

agreement for the pregnancy.<br />

b) the woman who carries in pregnancy an embryo to whose<br />

procreation she has contributed the donation of her own ovum,<br />

must also be defended in its integrity, tended and cared for, to the extent possible,<br />

in the same way as any other human being as far as medical assistance<br />

is concerned.”


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 125<br />

fertilized through insemination with the sperm of a man other<br />

than her husband. She carries the pregnancy with a pledge to surrender<br />

the child once it is born to the party who commissioned or<br />

made the agreement for the pregnancy. 19<br />

In both of these scenarios, an essential element of an action<br />

that can be said to constitute surrogacy is the making of “a<br />

pledge to surrender the child once it is born to the party who<br />

commissioned or made the agreement for the pregnancy.”<br />

Whether or not the woman is genetically related to the embryo<br />

does not determine whether the act is surrogacy. Nor, according<br />

to this definition, does the woman’s intent or lack thereof to<br />

raise the child. 20 Rather, the defining characteristic of becoming<br />

a surrogate mother is entering into a prior agreement or contract<br />

with another person or couple to gestate a baby for them<br />

and to give it to them upon birth. Thus, surrogate motherhood<br />

can be defined as the willingness to be impregnated (through<br />

e.g. sexual intercourse, artificial insemination, or embryo transfer)<br />

after having pledged in advance to give up that child to a<br />

particular person or persons.<br />

Though at present we tend to associate surrogacy with an<br />

agreement to gestate a baby in return for a sizable payment,<br />

such a payment merely signals a particularly problematic kind<br />

of surrogacy, rather than defining what constitutes surrogacy in<br />

itself. It is equally a case of surrogacy when a woman’s sister or<br />

mother or daughter or friend offers to gestate an embryo on her<br />

behalf without a fee. The woman who functions as a surrogate<br />

for a fee simply exacerbates the wrong that is done. 21<br />

19 DV, II, A, 3.<br />

20 It would seem that this allows for the possibility of “embryo fostering,”<br />

which is arguably not suttogacy, though it has certain similarities. An example of<br />

this is provided by and defended by Germain Grisez (1997). In the example he<br />

gives, a young single woman <strong>propos</strong>es to gestate an embryo to “rescue it” but<br />

does not intend to permanently raise the child, planning rather to give the child<br />

up for adoption. See Grisez (1997), 239-244. For a critique of Grisez’s “rescue”<br />

view, see JOHN BERKMAN, “Surrogacy? Rescue? Adoption? Gestating the Embryos<br />

of Others and Catholic Morality,” unpublished paper.<br />

21 That the exchange of a fee may make a wrong action worse, is of<br />

course not unique to surrogacy. For example, with prior agreement for a payment,<br />

what was fornication or adultery becomes prostitution.


126 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

In line with the definition of surrogacy offered in DV, the<br />

essence of surrogacy lies in the woman’s willingness to gestate a<br />

child on behalf of others. 22 Thus, in the situation in which a<br />

woman arranges to have an embryo implanted in her womb, and<br />

does so without a prior arrangement to give up the child to a specific<br />

couple upon delivery, she is not acting as a surrogate mother,<br />

strictly speaking. Whatever other criticisms may or may not<br />

be directed at what is being done, the woman is not, according to<br />

the definition offered by Donum vitae, a surrogate mother. 23<br />

When evaluated in a broader context, surrogacy can also be<br />

seen to contribute to the denigration of the moral significance of<br />

gestation, including that of the good and natural bond that<br />

develops between mother and child in the gestational period.<br />

While the contemporary discussion of IVF-ET, surrogacy, and<br />

embryo adoption seems to see little or no moral significance in<br />

the unique act of human gestation, it is what – in a profound<br />

sense – makes a woman a mother. In the next section on embryo<br />

adoption and the virtue of chastity, more will be said about the<br />

moral significance of gestation.<br />

(ii) Is Embryo Adoption Contrary to the Virtue of Chastity?<br />

If embryo adoption is not a case of surrogacy strictly speaking,<br />

some see it as analogous to surrogacy in that it involves a<br />

woman in actions that are incompatible with the nature of the<br />

marital commitment among Catholics. For example, Mary<br />

Geach has described embryo adoption as a “technological<br />

impregnation,” and concluded that it is wrong because all forms<br />

22 A religious form of surrogacy is illustrated in Margaret Atwood’s The<br />

Handmaid’s Tale.<br />

23 It may be argued that DV has an inadequate definition of surrogacy.<br />

It is certainly debatable as to whether a woman’s decision to “rescue” and<br />

“foster” a child to birth, with a general intention to give the child up for<br />

adoption, is a form of surrogacy. If this appeared to be done with a goal of<br />

financial gain, this would seem to reveal something about the nature of the<br />

woman’s intentions that would make the action closer to, if not in fact, a<br />

form of surrogacy.


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 127<br />

of technological impregnation are wrong. 24 According to Geach,<br />

any kind of technological impregnation is wrong because like<br />

adultery (for a married woman) or fornication (for an unmarried<br />

woman), it is against the virtue of chastity. That is, it is<br />

unchaste for a woman to allow herself to become impregnated<br />

with a baby who has come to be in any way other than through<br />

the act she performs in sexual intercourse with her spouse. 25<br />

At first glance, this last claim seems obviously wrong. For<br />

what could have less to do with a woman’s exercise of the virtue<br />

of chastity – the temperate exercise of her sexual desire – than a<br />

technological impregnation, the act of allowing a technician to<br />

implant an embryo in her womb? Furthermore, it does not even<br />

appear to have anything to do with the generative good (or telos)<br />

of an act of sexual intercourse, that of the conception of a<br />

human being. For in her act of allowing an embryo to be<br />

implanted in her womb, there is no goal of conception, since the<br />

embryo already exists. For these two reasons, this action<br />

appears to have nothing to do either with chastity understood as<br />

a form of temperance, or with the act that potentially conceives<br />

a human being.<br />

In response to the view that a technological impregnation<br />

has nothing to do with chastity traditionally understood (i.e. as<br />

a form of the virtue of temperance), Geach responds that the<br />

traditional understanding of chastity, while correct as far as it<br />

goes, is inadequate. Sexual temperance is only part (and not the<br />

most important part!) of the virtue of chastity that a woman<br />

exercises. Fundamentally, chastity for a woman lies in her maintaining<br />

her “reproductive integrity.” 26 According to Geach, a part<br />

of a woman’s reproductive integrity consists in her commitment<br />

24 See Geach (1999).<br />

25 Geach uses the term “marriage act” rather than sexual intercourse to<br />

indicate the kind of act through which a child is to come to be. This term has<br />

the consequence of collapsing different kinds of acts into the category of<br />

“marriage acts.”<br />

26 “So,” according to Geach, “the question about the woman who allows<br />

herself to be made pregnant by technology is whether she is doing this: is<br />

dis-integrating the marriage act by using a part of it out of context.” Geach<br />

(1999), p. 344.


128 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

to becoming pregnant only through acts of sexual intercourse<br />

between herself and her husband.<br />

If reproductive integrity is properly understood as being<br />

concerned with the means by which a woman “allows herself to<br />

be made pregnant,” then Geach is correct to insist that a woman<br />

engages in acts that impact upon her reproductive integrity both<br />

in her action in sexual intercourse and in her action when she<br />

allows a medical technician to implant an embryo into her<br />

uterus. Under this description, both acts are of the kind that<br />

leads to impregnation, and both are thus properly understood as<br />

marriage acts. The former – conjugal acts between a husband<br />

and wife – are appropriate marriage acts. The latter – acts by<br />

which a woman becomes pregnant which are not the result of a<br />

conjugal act between a husband and wife – are perversions of<br />

the marriage act, and as such are intrinsically immoral. 27<br />

However, Geach’s argument gains some of its force from an<br />

equivocation as to the nature of an act that leads to pregnancy.<br />

For to say that a woman’s reproductive integrity lies in her<br />

allowing the conception of a child only through marriage acts<br />

with her husband is not the same as to say that a woman’s reproductive<br />

integrity lies in her allowing herself to become pregnant<br />

only through marriage acts with her husband. 28 The former is<br />

27 “Now if these [orgasmic] sensations are ones which it is wrong to<br />

excite by acts of solitary vice, how much worse must it be to isolate the spiritual<br />

component of the marriage act, the giving up of the body to the<br />

impregnator, dissociating oneself from the parents of the child, and substituting<br />

for the relation to the father a mere arrangement with a technician.<br />

What is being asked of women is that they take a vital part of the marriage<br />

act, and perform it without the father. If solitary vice is objectionable as part<br />

of the marriage act taken out of context, much more so is this giving up of<br />

one’s body to an impregnating intromission.<br />

…To lay one’s womb open to an impregnating intromission which is not<br />

performed by the father, and is not generative, and is not expressive of a preexisting,<br />

sexually exclusive personal relationship, would be seriously to damage<br />

one’s ability to give oneself in marriage, and one’s sense of oneself as a<br />

psychophysical unity, and one’s understanding of the human animal as an<br />

image of the creator.” Geach (1999), p. 345. For Geach’s claim that having an<br />

orphan embryo implanted in one’s womb is intrinsically immoral, see Geach<br />

(1999), p. 341.<br />

28 On the question of the appropriate context for conception, DV says


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 129<br />

concerned specifically with conception (the proper way in which<br />

one may bring into being a new human life) along with the nurture<br />

necessary to bring the child to birth. The latter is not concerned<br />

with conception, but only with a particular form of nurturing<br />

an existing life up until birth. Thus, some argue that the<br />

latter kind of act – i.e. the act by which a woman accepts an<br />

existing embryo into her womb – is not a kind of marriage act<br />

(which requires it to be like the kind of act which normally leads<br />

to a conception of a new human life), but a particular, and a particularly<br />

significant, kind of maternal nurturing. 29<br />

Formulating an accurate description of a decision by a<br />

woman to have an orphaned embryo implanted in her womb is<br />

thus of utmost importance. The most adequate description is not<br />

that she is participating in a perversion of the marriage act (i.e.<br />

not that she is participating in an act which is per se open to the<br />

conception of new life in the wrong kind of way). Rather, the<br />

most adequate description of what she is doing (in having an<br />

orphaned embryo implanted in her womb with the commitment<br />

to raise the child if it survives to birth) is consenting to become<br />

a mother through adoption. In adopting the orphan embryo she<br />

is offering a uniquely important, intimate, and necessary form of<br />

nurturing. Furthermore, it can be argued that the consent<br />

involved in the woman’s choosing to adopt a frozen embryo and<br />

gestating it up to birth makes her the mother of the child in a<br />

more profound way than she would be if she adopted the child at<br />

“The moral relevance of the link between the meanings of the conjugal act<br />

and between the goods of marriage, as well as the unity of the human being<br />

and the dignity of his origin, demand that the procreation of a human person<br />

be brought about as the fruit of the conjugal act specific to the love<br />

between spouses.” (DV, II, B, 4)<br />

29 This view is argued by Watt (1999). While a conjugal act is the kind<br />

of act by which, under certain circumstances, a woman may become pregnant,<br />

it is not, per se, an impregnating act. Granted, as Geach notes, it is the<br />

kind of act that requires no additional human acts for pregnancy to occur.<br />

But it is not the kind of act that necessarily leads to pregnancy. Impregnation<br />

is an event that follows in some cases from a conjugal act. On the other hand,<br />

embryo transfer is an act by which a woman is made pregnant simpliciter<br />

(at the very least for a short period of time).


130 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

birth. On this view, the appropriate (albeit limited) analogy for<br />

the woman’s decision to gestate an embryo is to be drawn, not<br />

with the decision to participate in an act of sexual intercourse,<br />

but rather with the decision to nurture a child by nursing.<br />

Of course, this possibility of separating genetic motherhood<br />

from gestational motherhood is fundamentally new. This paper<br />

can only gesture towards a few of the many implications that<br />

can be drawn about either the good or bad implications of this<br />

new possibility. However, it can at least be noted that at present,<br />

greater significance, morally speaking, is typically given to<br />

genetic parenthood, but the opportunity is presented at this<br />

point in time to reevaluate this prevalent assumption.<br />

In the current debate regarding the adoption of frozen<br />

embryos, it is typical to equate (or almost equate) genetic parenthood<br />

with parenthood per se. Of course, in the normal and<br />

ideal course of events the genetic, gestational, and “raising” elements<br />

of parenthood all go together. But since it is now clear<br />

that genetic and gestational “motherhood” can be separated,<br />

why is it so readily assumed that providing an ovum qualifies<br />

one as the mother of a child, even after the created embryo has<br />

been implanted in the womb of another woman? On the contrary,<br />

a woman’s consenting to gestate a child, to give a child life<br />

that it otherwise could not have, can certainly be argued to be at<br />

least as biologically significant in terms of what is necessary for<br />

the child to actually be born. And if one does separate the act of<br />

consent to the creation of an embryo and the act of consent to<br />

gestate a child, it can certainly be argued that the latter is more<br />

morally significant in terms of a choice to become a human<br />

mother. While this is a subject that will require much more evaluation,<br />

it is certainly possible to make a case that, by the very act<br />

of gestation, the woman becomes the child’s mother in the most<br />

important and profound sense. The unquestioned priority that is<br />

typically given to the genetic element of parenthood must begin<br />

to be questioned. 30<br />

30 On the one hand, it is no doubt a very good thing to recognize the natural<br />

bond between children and their biological parents, so that e.g. nationstates<br />

or other governmental institutions cannot wrest control of children


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 131<br />

(iii) May a Couple Who Have Commissioned Embryos<br />

Through IVF Freeze them for the Purpose of Later Implantation?<br />

Having argued that the decision of a couple to adopt an<br />

embryo neither constitutes surrogacy (they are not contracted to<br />

give the child up at birth), nor constitutes an act incompatible<br />

with the virtue of chastity, we now examine the objection that in<br />

some instances the decision to implant an embryo in one particular<br />

kind of situation would constitute wrongful participation<br />

in IVF-ET. One recent proponent of embryo adoption in some<br />

instances has concluded that, according to DV, a couple in the<br />

middle of the IVF-ET process, who have already created and<br />

perhaps cryopreserved numerous embryos, have no morally<br />

acceptable course of action with regard to their frozen embryos.<br />

They continue to do wrong even if they seek eventually to gestate<br />

the rest of their embryos. Geoffrey Surtees writes:<br />

In other words, for those who choose the methods of in vitro<br />

fertilization, it is in fact true that there are no licit means of handling<br />

the “spares” begotten from the IVF procedure: this is because<br />

any action the parties choose to adopt with respect to the “spares”<br />

would be to deny the fundamental rights of the embryo(s) to enjoy<br />

gestation and birth in his natural mother; and, after birth, to be<br />

raised and educated by the same. Even if the couple were to envision<br />

giving up their spares for adoption, this too would be wrong,<br />

and for the same reason: it would deny the children the parental<br />

love they are by natural justice entitled to from their original parents.<br />

It is never licit to reject one’s own child; and it is a further<br />

injustice to give [the embryo] over to the “absurd fate” of spending<br />

the rest of his existence confined in deep freeze, all the while susceptible<br />

to experimentations and further inhumane treatment. 31<br />

from their parents without very strong reason (e.g. child abuse, serious<br />

neglect, and so forth). On the other hand, in a world where children have<br />

been orphaned through a variety of tragic circumstances (including abandonment),<br />

those who commit themselves to the raising of a child through<br />

adoption are in the most important sense the true parents of that child.<br />

31 Surtees (1996), 8.


132 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

Thus, according to Surtees, those who choose to undergo<br />

the IVF-ET treatment are enmeshed in an irresolvable moral difficulty.<br />

Once a couple commissions the embryos, there is no<br />

moral choice they can make with regard to the leftover embryos.<br />

While I will challenge shortly the conclusions drawn in the<br />

above quoted passage, Surtees does draw out some seemingly<br />

logical conclusions in a very puzzling situation. On the logic of<br />

the Catholic tradition discussed thus far, it has been noted that<br />

it is wrong in principle for a couple to commission the creation<br />

of embryos (using either their own gametes or donor gametes)<br />

through IVF. Thus, according to Catholic teaching, there would<br />

seem to be no situation in which a couple could intend a process<br />

by which they would have embryos which are their genetic children<br />

implanted in the womb of the woman. On the other hand,<br />

the adoption of embryos that are unrelated to the couple has not<br />

been ruled out as wrong in principle. If this is indeed the case, it<br />

produces the rather odd consequence that Catholic teaching<br />

seems to allow ET which separates genetic parenthood from<br />

gestational and “raising” parenthood, but prohibits ET that<br />

would maintain the bond between genetic, gestational, and<br />

“raising” parenthood.<br />

Now it can be argued that the situation about which Surtees<br />

is arguing is not in fact a case of embryo adoption, as a couple<br />

cannot “adopt” their own biological children. Rather, it is about<br />

the morality of implanting too many embryos, or relinquishing<br />

one’s embryos for adoption, or freezing one’s embryos. While<br />

this is true, Surtees’ example sheds light on issues relevant to the<br />

question of the morality of embryo adoption that is at the heart<br />

of this essay.<br />

Central to Surtees’ response to this question is his interpretation<br />

of the “cannot be licitly pursued” sentence in Donum vitae<br />

which has been extensively discussed in section one of this<br />

paper. According to Surtees, this sentence is directed towards<br />

“persons who have freely adopted by choice the intelligible,<br />

though illicit, <strong>propos</strong>al of artificial reproduction.” 32 Unfor-<br />

32 See Surtees (1996), 8. He completes that sentence by adding “and,<br />

hence, not at those who would wish to “rescue” these embryos through adoption.”


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 133<br />

tunately, Surtees also fails to note adequately the context of that<br />

sentence in DV and mistakenly takes it to be directed towards<br />

couples who seek a pregnancy through “artificial procreation.”<br />

However, this section is in fact directed to researchers, and the<br />

issue of the morality of artificial procreation will not be raised<br />

until the following section of DV. 33<br />

As can be seen from the quote above, Surtees believes that a<br />

couple who have commissioned the creation of more embryos<br />

than can be implanted in the uterus of the woman at the time of<br />

their creation are in a position where there is no morally acceptable<br />

solution. This is because neither of the two alternatives to<br />

their immediate implantation is, according to Surtees, morally<br />

acceptable. It is not permissible either to give them up for adoption<br />

or to cryopreserve them for future implantation.<br />

Let us first examine Surtees’s claim regarding the impermissibility<br />

of cryopreservation. He claims that the couple cannot<br />

choose to cryopreserve an excess embryo because an embryo<br />

has a right to be gestated, and freezing the spare embryo consigns<br />

it to “the ‘absurd fate’ of spending all the rest of his existence<br />

confined in deep freeze, all the while susceptible to experimentation<br />

and further inhumane treatment.” 34 However, while<br />

33 The first mention of artificial procreation comes in the opening lines<br />

of Part 2 of DV, which is entitled “Interventions upon Human Procreation.”<br />

The term “artificial procreation” is the term used by DV to refer to the<br />

combination of the fertilization of an ovum in a test-tube (i.e. in vitro) along<br />

with the transfer of the fertilized ovum (i.e. the embryo) in utero, all of which<br />

is done for the purpose of human procreation other than via the sexual<br />

union of man and woman. Surtees uses a different term – “artificial reproduction”<br />

– and while that term is ambiguous in that it could be a reference<br />

merely to artificial conception, Surtees clearly has in mind what DV calls<br />

artificial procreation, as is evident from the sentences that follow.<br />

Furthermore, Surtees also seems to overlook the descriptive thrust of<br />

DV I, 5, and is thus, like Smith, confused as to what DV means by “spare”<br />

embryos. Whereas DV is referring to those embryos which are destined<br />

never to find a human womb for a home, Surtees thinks “spare” simply<br />

refers to those embryos which are not implanted in what is typically referred<br />

to as the “first” cycle or round of IVF treatment<br />

34 Surtees (1996), 8. Note the oddity of this claim by Surtees, which he<br />

derives from DV I, 6. One could simply say that the cryopreservation will


134 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

the claim here involves the assumption that cryopreserving the<br />

embryo is permanent or alternatively leads to experimentation<br />

by a researcher, that is clearly not necessarily the case. If there<br />

is something inherently wrong with cryopreservation of an<br />

embryo, it cannot be because it is always permanent.<br />

Furthermore, if, for example, the couple had a kind of moral<br />

conversion right after they had created ten embryos through IVF<br />

and wanted to do the best thing in that situation, what should<br />

they do? The thing that would be most respectful of those<br />

nascent lives would be to implant two or three, and freeze the<br />

rest with the plan of gestating the rest in small groups as well. 35<br />

Alternatively, one can imagine a scenario of a woman simultaneously<br />

diagnosed with an ectopic pregnancy and with a form of<br />

cancer requiring radiation. She might seek to preserve the life of<br />

her embryo by having it removed from the fallopian tube and<br />

cryopreserved, with the hope that following the radiation treatment<br />

she would be able to have the embryo reimplanted in her<br />

uterus and gestate it to term. While a variety of circumstances<br />

only be temporary, the embryo will be implanted later, and that there is no<br />

intention of allowing the embryo to be experimented on. This uncited appeal<br />

to DV I, 5 only makes sense if one understands that by “spares” DV I, 5 is<br />

referring to those embryos which are definitely not destined for future<br />

implantation (as argued in section one of this paper). Thus DV’s objection<br />

to cryopreservation in DV I, 6 reads as follows: “The freezing of embryos,<br />

even when carried out in order to preserve the life of an embryo - cryopreservation<br />

- constitutes an offence against the respect due to human beings<br />

by exposing them to grave risks of death or harm to their physical integrity<br />

and depriving them, at least temporarily, of maternal shelter and gestation,<br />

thus placing them in a situation in which further offences and manipulation<br />

are possible.”<br />

35 For a similar kind of argument, see Watt (1999), p. 352. “I can even<br />

imagine cases in which it might be morally obligatory [to adopt particular<br />

frozen embryos], because one was morally responsible for the embryo’s (sic)<br />

being conceived. The woman who commissions the production of embryos<br />

from her husband’s sperm and another woman’s ova bears considerable<br />

responsibility for the fate of any embryos left on ice. If the ovum donor is<br />

unwilling or unable to gestate, a woman who regrets the commission might<br />

rightly consider she herself has a duty to gestate, in groups of two or three,<br />

all remaining frozen embryos.”


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 135<br />

might make these decisions imprudent or even morally wrong,<br />

they are not wrong in principle.<br />

Let us next examine Surtees’s objection to giving up the<br />

embryo for adoption, namely, that such an action denies “the<br />

children the parental love they are by natural justice entitled to<br />

from their original parents. It is never licit to reject one’s own<br />

child…” 36 From this Surtees draws a principle that it is never<br />

permissible to create a child with the intent to give it up for<br />

adoption. This claim finds support in DV, which in the context<br />

of a critique of surrogate motherhood speaks of the “right of the<br />

child to be conceived, carried in the womb, brought into the<br />

world and brought up by his own parents.” 37 However, interpreted<br />

in one way, the claims made by Surtees and DV regarding<br />

what biological parents owe their children could be interpreted<br />

as ruling out not only giving up an embryo for adoption, but also<br />

giving up a child for adoption. For both actions would seem to<br />

contravene the rights due to a child on one understanding of<br />

these rights. On this view, it would thus seem to be wrong for<br />

any Catholic agency to ever counsel a woman in crisis pregnancy<br />

to consider giving up a baby for adoption and then find an<br />

adoptive home for him or her. Again, perhaps both DV and<br />

Surtees should be understood to be making the more modest<br />

claim stated above, that one should not bring into existence children<br />

whom one does not intend to gestate and raise. In other<br />

words, perhaps the principle is something like the following: one<br />

should not seek to conceive and/or gestate a child one does not<br />

intend to raise. This would seem to be a reasonable moral principle,<br />

indicating the wrongfulness of bringing children into existence<br />

while planning in advance to abandon those children.<br />

However, couples who have embryos created in vitro do not<br />

typically set out to give up some of their embryos for adoption.<br />

Typically, it is only after a successful pregnancy that they consider<br />

offering some of their embryos for adoption. For those<br />

who plan in advance to leave this option open, this is a kind of<br />

36 Surtees (1996), 8. Surtees later elaborates and further specifies what<br />

he means by “reject” (p. 14, n. 4). However, that qualification, if taken seriously,<br />

vitiates the force of the argument he is making at this point in the<br />

paper.


136 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

conditional abandonment. However, many others simply fail to<br />

consider the implications of what they are doing in commissioning<br />

the creation of embryos in vitro. Finally, others may fully<br />

intend to implant all of their embryos, but through illness,<br />

death, or other misfortune simply become unable to fulfill the<br />

responsibilities they undertook.<br />

One can imagine untimely circumstances leading to a decision<br />

to give up one’s embryo for adoption similar to those that<br />

could be expected to lead to a regular adoption. In certain circumstances<br />

the decision by a biological parent to offer embryos<br />

up for adoption would not necessarily be any more an act of illicit<br />

abandonment than that of a birth mother who for a variety of<br />

reasons decides to give up her child for adoption. While in certain<br />

instances one would act in a gravely wrong manner to hand<br />

over one’s frozen embryos (or one’s birth child) to another couple<br />

for adoption, the wrongfulness does not lie in an “in-principle”<br />

requirement upon all those who procreate children to raise<br />

them.<br />

Finally, there is also the question of the woman who finds<br />

out after conception that her endometrium is unfit for implantation.<br />

If she flushed out her pre-implanted embryo, froze it, and<br />

looked for someone to gestate it, would that be acceptable?<br />

Mary Geach presents this case as something which would be<br />

wrong to do. 38 However, she assumes that the woman who<br />

would gestate the baby would pledge to return the child to the<br />

genetic mother at birth. Of course, that would be surrogacy.<br />

However, this is not the last word with this case. For<br />

instance, what if the woman engages in embryo flushing and<br />

freezes the embryo, not so that someone can gestate the embryo<br />

for her, but so that she can give it up for adoption? What if, like<br />

the mother of Moses, she will go to extraordinary means to give<br />

37 DV, II, A, 3. This line is repeated almost verbatim at DV III.<br />

38 This case can be found in Geach (1999), 341. Another analogous case<br />

is that of the rape victim, who, while recognizing the humanity of the<br />

embryo inside her, does not want to gestate and raise the child. Is it morally<br />

wrong for her, not wanting to abort the embryo, to have an embryo flush and<br />

cryopreservation done, and seek a person willing to adopt the child? Issues<br />

of self-defense complicate this example.


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 137<br />

her embryo a chance at life that she cannot provide, and is eager<br />

to give the child up to another woman who can both gestate and<br />

raise the child? Does she do wrong? This possibility, though<br />

fraught with moral, emotional and technical difficulties, does<br />

not seem to be ruled out in principle.<br />

3. Further Moral Concerns and Considerations<br />

In the previous section, we examined a number of arguments<br />

that have led some commentators to conclude that the<br />

adoption of human embryos is morally wrong in itself. Those<br />

arguments are not in the end convincing; the adoption of abandoned<br />

human embryos cannot be ruled out in principle.<br />

However, it would be a mistake to conclude from this that the<br />

choice to adopt an abandoned embryo is always a good thing. In<br />

fact, there are a number of further moral considerations that<br />

must be taken into account when a couple is considering such<br />

an adoption. Issues of cooperation with wrongdoing and scandal<br />

must be taken into account in evaluating the permissibility<br />

of embryo adoption in any particular situation. Furthermore, it<br />

is also important to acknowledge the limitations of the conceptual<br />

paradigm of adoption that has been central in this essay.<br />

For while a woman’s decision to have an embryo implanted in<br />

her uterus is certainly analogous to the ordinary notion of what<br />

it means to adopt a child, it is by no means identical, and the<br />

limits of this analogy must be noted. 39<br />

However, while moral difficulties involved in specific cases<br />

must be taken into account, one must not lose sight of the centrality<br />

of the good of adoption, whether it be of an embryo or a<br />

child. From the beginning of the Christian tradition, the Church<br />

has always been involved in the rescue and placement of<br />

foundlings. 40 The good of finding loving and stable homes for<br />

39 I have taken up a number of these issues in my article “The Morality<br />

of Adopting Frozen Embryos: Contemporary Context and Debate,” unpublished<br />

paper.<br />

40 On this question, see Amundsen (1996) and Boswell (1988).


138 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

infants and children whose parents are for whatever reason<br />

unable to raise them is not questioned. 41 Furthermore, the willingness<br />

of couples (or in some cases single persons) to open<br />

their hearts and homes through adoption to needy children is a<br />

great gift of Christian charity. While all persons of good will are<br />

able to see the great good in adopting needy children, the call to<br />

care for orphans will be particularly compelling to Christians, as<br />

part of their response to Christ’s call to care “for the least of<br />

these.”<br />

Likewise, reflection on the morality of adopting orphaned<br />

embryos must begin with the duty to care for “the least of these.”<br />

Abandoned frozen embryos do indeed qualify as being some of<br />

the most vulnerable and needy of human beings: “It is therefore<br />

not in conformity with the moral law deliberately to expose to<br />

death human embryos obtained ‘in vitro’.” 42 If the embryo is a<br />

human being as worthy of care and protection as any other<br />

human being, then the good involved in the rescue and adoption<br />

of such orphaned embryos make such adoption at least a prima<br />

facie good thing to do.<br />

However frozen embryos have come to be, the fundamental<br />

principle for evaluating the appropriateness of adopting them is<br />

that of the dignity of and protection to be given to innocent<br />

human life. Furthermore, Christians witness to this dignity most<br />

powerfully by promoting the dignity of the most marginalized<br />

and vulnerable in our society. Orphans, whether post-natal or<br />

41 Of course, this is not to deny those particular instances of adoption or<br />

certain kinds of adoption (e.g. some international or inter-racial adoptions)<br />

which have been questioned morally. These questions are usually raised<br />

because of concerns of perceived and/or actual injustices done to the birth<br />

parent(s) and/or child. That such concerns should arise is not at all surprising<br />

considering that the very necessity of adoption arises from a pre-existing<br />

evil (i.e. that the child cannot be raised by its birth parents, either because<br />

of some tragedy (i.e. death, disability, etc.), or because of irresponsibility, or<br />

by due consideration of the best interests of the child).<br />

42 DV, I, 5. While this sentence from DV is also directed specifically<br />

towards embryos created for research purposes, it is merely an elaboration<br />

of the principles outlined in DV I, 1 on the respect due to the human life,<br />

namely, that “Human life must be absolutely respected and protected from<br />

the moment of conception.”


pre-natal, have always had a particular claim on the charity of<br />

Christians. With regard to these most helpless and abandoned of<br />

human beings in our day, who are given no status whatsoever by<br />

much of our society, one cannot but be reminded of a similar situation<br />

in another age and the response of Christians at that<br />

time. The early Christians were both famous and infamous for<br />

their giving shelter to Roman infants who were left exposed.<br />

This odd behavior marked them as different in that society.<br />

While Christians should not seek to be “different” for its own<br />

sake, the commitment to rescue and raise the children “exposed”<br />

in our society is, as it was then, an odd behavior that will worthily<br />

mark those who offer such hospitality. 43<br />

Bibliography<br />

THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 139<br />

JOHN BERKMAN<br />

Amundsen, Darrel (1996), Medicine, Society, and Faith in the<br />

Ancient and Medieval Worlds. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins<br />

University Press, 1996, pp. 50-69.<br />

Ashley, Benedict, O.P., and Albert Moraczewski, O.P. (2001),<br />

“Cloning, Aquinas, and the Embryonic Person,” National<br />

Catholic Bioethics Quarterly, Summer 2001, pp. 189-201.<br />

Boswell, John (1988), The Kindness of Strangers: The<br />

Abandonment of Children in Western Europe From Late<br />

Antiquity to the Renaissance. New York: Pantheon Books,<br />

1988.<br />

Caulfield, Brian (1998), “‘Souls on Ice’: With Frozen Embryo<br />

Technology, Life’s Sanctity is Lost,” The National Catholic<br />

Register, January 4 - 10, 1998, pp. 1, 15.<br />

Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith (1987), Instruction on<br />

Respect for Human Life in its origin and on the Dignity of<br />

Procreation, February 22, 1987: Acta Apostolicae Sedis 80<br />

(1988), 70-102.<br />

43 I am grateful for the comments of W Barbieri, C Crysdale, D Ferris, N<br />

Ford, J Grabowski, J Komonchak, F Moloney, J Utz, and H Watt on previous<br />

drafts of this paper. Thanks also to the CUA Grant-in-Aid program for financial<br />

support of my research.


140 JOHN BERKMAN<br />

[N.B. This document is typically referred to by its Latin title<br />

Donum vitae (DV), and cited according to its outline divisions.<br />

An English translation is available under Respect for<br />

Human Life (Boston: St Paul Editions, n.d.); See also<br />

Origins, vol. 16, no. 40 (March 19, 1987), 697-711. It is also<br />

to be found at www.vatican.va/roman_curia/congregations.]<br />

Doerflinger, Richard (1999), “The Ethics of Funding Embryonic<br />

Stem Cell Research: A Catholic Viewpoint,” Kennedy<br />

Institute of Ethics Journal (9:2) June 1999, pp. 137-150.<br />

Geach, Mary (1999), “Are there any circumstances in which it<br />

would be morally admirable for a woman to seek to have an<br />

orphan embryo implanted in her womb? – 1,” Issues for a<br />

Catholic Bioethic, ed. Luke Gormally, London: The Linacre<br />

Centre, 1999, pp. 341 - 346.<br />

Grisez, Germain (1997), “Should a woman try to bear her dead<br />

sister’s embryo?” The Way of the Lord Jesus volume 3:<br />

Difficult Moral Questions. Chicago: Franciscan Herald Press,<br />

1997, pp. 239 - 244.<br />

Johnson, Mark, “Reflections on Some Recent Catholic Claims<br />

for Delayed Hominization,” Theological Studies 56 (1995),<br />

pp. 743-763.<br />

Porter, Jean, “Individuality, Personal Identity, and the Moral<br />

Status of the Preembryo,” Theological Studies 56 (1995), pp.<br />

763-770.<br />

Shannon, Thomas A. and Alan B. Wolter, “Reflections on the<br />

Moral Status of the Pre-Embryo,” Theological Studies 51<br />

(1990), pp. 603-626.<br />

Smith, William B. (1995), “Rescue the Frozen?” Homiletic and<br />

Pastoral Review. 96:1, October 1995, pp. 72-74.<br />

Smith, William B. (1996), “Response,” Homiletic and Pastoral<br />

Review. 96:11-12, August-September 1996, pp. 16 - 17.<br />

Surtees, Geoffrey (1996), “Adoption of a frozen embryo,”<br />

Homiletic and Pastoral Review. 96:11-12, August-September<br />

1996, pp. 7 - 16.<br />

Watt, Helen (1999), “Are there any circumstances in which it<br />

would be morally admirable for a woman to seek to have an<br />

orphan embryo implanted in her womb? - 2.” Issues for a<br />

Catholic Bioethic, ed. Luke Gormally, London: The Linacre<br />

Centre, 1999, pp. 347 - 352.


THE MORALITY OF ADOPTING FROZEN EMBRYOS 141<br />

—————<br />

The autor is a visiting professor at Duke Divinity School and currently<br />

a visiting scholar at the Duke Institute on Care at the End of<br />

Life.<br />

El autor es professor invitado en Duke Divinity School y actualmente<br />

estudioso invitado en el Duke Institute on Care at the End of<br />

Life.<br />

—————


StMor 40 (2002) 143-169<br />

EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R<br />

L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE<br />

E L’ETICA DELL’INCONTRO<br />

Dall’esigenza ontologica all’imperativo etico nella filosofia<br />

dell’uomo in cammino di Gabriel Marcel<br />

“Ricoeur è consapevole come sia inutile cercare in Marcel<br />

un sistema morale – afferma giustamente Franco Riva – o una<br />

collocazione esatta rispetto alle prospettive di un Heidegger –<br />

l’ontologia senza l’etica – o di Lévinas – l’etica senza ontologia.<br />

Ciò non toglie che, secondo Ricoeur, Marcel non ponga di fronte<br />

a delle esperienze forti che danno a pensare, a uno stile filosofico<br />

che si configura in una approssimazione crescente, e al<br />

valore di universalità concreta dato a certe esperienze, trascurate<br />

in filosofia morale” 1 . Per comprendere a pieno il rapporto tra<br />

etica e ontologia in Marcel, la direzione indicata da Ricoeur per<br />

tracciare a grandi linee un’etica marceliana, occorre collocare<br />

infatti l’implicazione di G. Marcel sia ad un livello ontologico di<br />

partecipazione d’essere, sia ad un livello etico di decisione per<br />

l’interrelazione (Etre et Avoir, L’Homme problematique, Homo<br />

Viator, Le Mystère de l’Etre). Il rapporto tra etica e ontologia in<br />

Marcel acquista in Entre éthique et ontologie: la disponibilité un<br />

rilievo più marcato 2 . L’analisi etica di Marcel si nutre della dialettica<br />

tra l’essere e l’avere che apre all’orizzonte ontologico. Il<br />

rapporto tra l’etica e l’ontologia tocca in particolare i temi del-<br />

1 P. RICOEUR, G. MARCEL, Per un’etica dell’alterità. Sei colloqui (a cura di<br />

Franco Riva), Edizioni Lavoro, Roma 1998, 133. (Je n’ai jamais pensé à écrire<br />

une éthique – dice G. Marcel in un’intervista con Pierre Boutang – pour cette<br />

simple raison que je me suis toujours senti éloigné du formalisme, in: P. BOU-<br />

TANG, Gabriel Marcel, J. M. Place, Paris 1977, 93).<br />

2 G. MARCEL, Entre éthique et ontologie: la disponibilité, in: Aa. Vv., Gabriel<br />

Marcel (Colloque organisé par la Bibliothèque National et l’association<br />

“ Présence de Gabriel Marcel ”, 28-30 settembre 1988), Bibliothèque National,<br />

Paris 1989, 157-165.


144 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

l’esistenza, della soggettività e dell’interpersonalità 3 . “In una visione<br />

itinerante della vita umana, per cui l’essere è dinamismo<br />

operante e l’agire è attestazione ontologica, ontologia ed etica –<br />

afferma Mauro Cozzoli – sono in intima e solidale compenetrazione:<br />

l’indicativo ontologico è imperativo etico” 4 .<br />

Perché ho scelto questo tema? Prima di tutto vorrei continuare<br />

la ricerca relativa alla bioetica nell’ottica del personalismo<br />

francese 5 . Poi, due considerazioni di Sandro Spinsanti, fatte durante<br />

il II Convegno nazionale sul personalismo comunitario di<br />

E. Mounier a Teramo nel 1990 hanno determinato la scelta del<br />

tema e del contenuto di questo articolo: la prima, che “all’area<br />

dei problemi di bioetica il personalismo deve la sua seconda giovinezza”,<br />

la seconda riguarda “l’uso improprio e strumentale del<br />

personalismo come etichetta, da utilizzare per condurre vecchie<br />

battaglie e da contrapporre ad altre concezioni” 6 . In questo articolo,<br />

tuttavia, non vorrei utilizzare il personalismo di G. Marcel<br />

per condurre vecchie battaglie oppure per la sua contrapposizione<br />

ad altre concezioni, ma, al contrario, per mettere in rilievo:<br />

in primo luogo, la dimensione ontologica dell’essere umano,<br />

in secondo luogo, la dimensione etica della persona in quanto<br />

norma normativa, in terzo luogo, le implicazioni ontologiche,<br />

antropologiche ed etiche nel campo della bioetica.<br />

1. Il mistero dell’essere – una dimensione ontologica<br />

dell’essere umano<br />

L’opera di G. Marcel nasce da una reazione critica e polemica<br />

al razionalismo oggettivistico che caratterizza gran parte del-<br />

3 P. RICOEUR, G. MARCEL, Per un’etica dell’alterità. Sei colloqui, op. cit.,<br />

139-148.<br />

4 M. COZZOLI, L’uomo in cammino verso… L’attesa e la speranza in Gabriel<br />

Marcel, Abete, Roma 1979, 267.<br />

5 Cfr E. KOWALSKI, CSsR, Quale uomo e quale etica per la bioetica. Una<br />

<strong>propos</strong>ta di umanizzazione della riflessione bioetica, StM, 39/2001/1, 175-195.<br />

6 S. SPINSANTI, Quale personalismo per la bioetica, in: A. DANESE (a cura<br />

di), Persona e sviluppo. Un dibattito interdisciplinare, Edizioni Dehoniane,<br />

Roma 1991, 265-268.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 145<br />

le istanze antimetafisiche del pensiero moderno, in particolare<br />

al razionalismo di tipo cartesiano, kantiano e positivista 7 . Inoltre,<br />

Marcel non volle mai costruire una metafisica sistematica<br />

(si pensi a Kant, Schelling o Hegel); perciò accettò che la sua filosofia<br />

si chiamasse neo-socratismo 8 ; egli stesso, invece, si riconosce<br />

un pensatore esistenziale 9 mentre rifiuta l’etichetta di esistenzialista<br />

10 . Marcel come filosofo esistentivo – secondo Dario<br />

Composta – “non dipende né da Kierkegaard né da Jaspers, né<br />

da Heidegger; tanto meno da J. P. Sartre o da Maurice Merleau<br />

Ponty ai quali non volle assimilarsi nemmeno attraverso una polemica<br />

camuffata, ma da cui anzi volle tenersi distante coraggiosamente<br />

per il loro pensiero ateo” 11 . “La mia situazione filosofica<br />

– dice Marcel in Il mistero dell’essere – mi si presenta come<br />

se io avessi seguito finora molte piste in un paese in gran<br />

parte inesplorato e voi mi chiedeste ora di indicarvi una strada<br />

al posto di quelle piste o mi invitaste a tracciare un itinerario, il<br />

che, sostanzialmente, è la stessa cosa. Questa metafora può sollevare<br />

almeno due tipi di obiezioni: innanzi tutto potreste osservare<br />

che il concetto di strada implica quello spazio, da cui una<br />

ricerca metafisica, come vuole essere la nostra, deve astrarre…<br />

Mi potreste allora presentare l’obiezione in un’altra forma, assai<br />

più imbarazzante: ricostruire un cammino là ove non c’erano<br />

che alcune piste, equivale a prestabilire una meta, già precisata<br />

7 G. MARCEL, Etre et Avoir, Aubier, Paris 1935, 319 [EA]; En Chemin, vers<br />

quel Eveil?, Gallimard, Paris 1971, 81 [ECE].<br />

8 G. MARCEL, L’uomo problematico, Borla, Torino 1964, 58 [UP]; Présence<br />

et immortalité, Flammarion, Paris 1959, 184; La dignité humaine et ses assises<br />

existentielles, Aubier, Paris 1964, 217 [DH]; R. DAVIGNON, Le mal chez Gabriel<br />

Marcel. Comment affronter la souffrance et la mort?, Cerf-Bellarmin, Paris-Montréal<br />

1985, 161-164; D. COMPOSTA, Intersoggettività e morale, Edizioni<br />

Scientifiche Italiane, Napoli 1999, 65.<br />

9 ECE, 97.<br />

10 G. MARCEL, Le Mystère de l’Etre, vol. I Réflexion et Mystère, vol. II Foi et<br />

réalité, Aubier, Paris 1951, 5 [MEI][MEII]; L’Homme Problématique, Aubier,<br />

Paris 1955, 72 [HP]; [DH], 10; ECE, 228, 230; da: M. COZZOLI, L’uomo in cammino<br />

verso, op. cit., 17; UP, 58.<br />

11 D. COMPOSTA, Intersoggettività e morale, op. cit., 67; cfr G. MARCEL, Remarques<br />

sur l’irreligion contemporaine, in: EA, 259-297.


146 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

e determinata, alla quale s’intende giungere” 12 . Nell’ambito della<br />

ricerca filosofica – secondo Marcel – non si possiede un pre-concetto<br />

in forma schematica, l’equivalente della pre-nozione del<br />

tecnico. Nella ricerca filosofica marceliana, infatti, non esistono<br />

né pregiudizi sociali, politici, etici o religiosi, né “risultati” del<br />

genere e “il filosofo spesso va alla ventura” 13 . La sua ricerca filosofica<br />

è il passaggio da una “situazione di disagio ad una situazione<br />

di distensione”, da una situazione-domanda ad una situazione-risposta.<br />

Questa prospettiva deve essere considerata come<br />

“ciò in cui io mi trovo implicato” (io-sono-in-situazione, io-vivola-situazione)<br />

e in qualsiasi modo si debba interpretare questo<br />

“io”, questo “me stesso”. La situazione non tocca l’io solo dal di<br />

fuori, ma lo qualifica interiormente, o meglio, l’opposizione tra<br />

interno ed esterno perde a questo <strong>propos</strong>ito il suo significato.<br />

L’io non può mai essere considerato un qualcosa in quanto io.<br />

Se l’io esisto è una certezza esistenziale, lo è soltanto a condizione<br />

che sia preso nella sua inscindibile unità 14 .L’io esisto, l’io<br />

vivo è il puro immediato nell’ambito d’intelligibilità. L’io esistovivo<br />

fonda, precede e supera io penso (cogito cartesiano). In oltre<br />

parole, l’io esisto compie ed esaurisce totalmente l’essere<br />

umano in quanto io, cioè io è sempre io esistente, vivente e personale<br />

anche se non è ancora, già o non evidentemente io pensante<br />

(si pensi allo stato embrionale oppure allo stato vegetativo<br />

persistente). L’io esisto ha di mira - per Marcel – l’altro fatto “che<br />

io non sono solo per me, ma che mi manifesto, sarebbe anzi meglio<br />

dire che ‘sono manifesto’; il prefisso ‘e’ nella parola ‘esistere’<br />

è infatti della massima importanza perché esistere vuol dire: farmi<br />

conoscere, o riconoscere, sia dagli altri, sia da me stesso, in<br />

tanto che ostento un’alterità presa a prestito” 15 . In altre parole<br />

Marcel vorrebbe rispondere alla domanda fondamentale: “Chi<br />

sono io?” Questa problematica indirizza la sua indagine filosofi-<br />

12 G. MARCEL, Il mistero dell’essere, Borla, Roma 1987, 9-10 [ME].<br />

13 ME, 12, 18-20; G. Marcel, Essai de philosophie concrète, Gallimard,<br />

Paris 1940, 21-61, 92-126 (Quest’opera è stata pubblicata originariamente<br />

con il titolo Du refus à l’invocation da Editions Gallimard, nel 1940); M. M.<br />

DAVY, Un philosophe itinérant. Gabriel Marcel, Flammarion, Paris 1959.<br />

14 ME, 89-90.<br />

15 ME, 90-91.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 147<br />

ca e allo stesso tempo costituisce l’inizio della sua ontologia esistenziale.<br />

Parlando del senso e della natura della ricerca intrapresa, si<br />

tratta – spiega Marcel – “di esigenza del trascendente” 16 . Trascendere,<br />

in questo caso, non significa semplicemente superare<br />

un limite, spaziale oppure temporale, come si vede nel caso del<br />

“progetto” sartriano. Facendo riferimento all’antitesi tradizionale<br />

fra immanente e trascendente, Marcel propone la sua distinzione<br />

fra “superamento orizzontale e superamento verticale” in<br />

quanto il suo metodo fenomenologico “salire-scendere-risalire”:<br />

dalla vita al pensiero e ridiscendere dal pensiero alla vita, per<br />

tentare di chiarire le relazioni precise fra esperienza e vita 17 .<br />

“L’esigenza della trascendenza si presenta essenzialmente, ed è<br />

essenzialmente sperimentata, come insoddisfazione” 18 . L’insoddisfazione<br />

possiede un duplice dinamismo, da una parte, essa è<br />

determinata dalla mancanza di un qualcosa (il valore) che in<br />

realtà è esteriore all’io (“un’esperienza del trascendente”), dall’altra<br />

parte, l’io può assimilarlo e per conseguenza farlo mio<br />

(“un’esperienza dell’immanente”, l’autocreazione della libera decisione).<br />

La dinamica dell’insoddisfazione assicura all’io la libertà<br />

di movimento di cui ha bisogno: “il trascendente è immanente<br />

all’esperienza”. L’esperienza del trascendente è fondamentalmente<br />

il riferimento intimamente vissuto all’io nell’intimo<br />

della sua coscienza 19 . Si può far notare a questo <strong>propos</strong>ito che<br />

Marcel ha voluto aggiungere – seguendo la via tracciata dalla fenomenologia<br />

husserliana – che “la coscienza è essenzialmente<br />

coscienza di qualcos’altro da sé” 20 . Allora, l’esigenza di trascendenza,<br />

presa nel suo significato metafisico come esperienza del<br />

trascendente, indica essenzialmente un’alterità: la relazione-comunicazione<br />

fra me e gli altri (tu, Dio come il Tu supremo) ed<br />

anche fra me e me. L’alterità, infatti, suppone l’apertura, in vista<br />

di una teoria della verità: adaequatio rei et intellectus. La definizione<br />

della verità di Tommaso d’Aquino prende in considerazio-<br />

16 ME, 41.<br />

17 ME, 41-43.<br />

18 ME, 43.<br />

19 ME, 47-49.<br />

20 ME, 53.


148 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

ne – secondo Marcel – un processo conoscitivo che si svolge partendo<br />

da me stesso e fa ritorno a me stesso per constatare ciò<br />

che semplicemente “è” (la realtà, il fatto), e non ciò che “è vero”<br />

(la verità), sulla base della tradizionale opposizione fra attività<br />

(intellectus) e passività (res). Il ragionamento (intellectus) instaura<br />

nei confronti dell’oggetto (res) la particolare relazione<br />

dell’esattezza (adaequatio). L’essenza di questa relazione è chiamata<br />

da Heidegger – in Dall’essere alla verità – “appresentazione”<br />

e “appresentare” significa: “Lasciar sorgere davanti a noi la cosa<br />

in quanto è quell’oggetto, ma in modo che il ragionamento si lasci<br />

guidare dalla cosa e la renda tale e quale essa si presenta. La<br />

condizione di ogni appresentazione è che l’essente che appresenta<br />

sia illuminato da una luce in modo che la cosa possa apparirgli,<br />

rendersi manifesta. Questa cosa deve presentarsi e rivelarsi<br />

in un campo aperto al nostro incontro” 21 . Marcel non soltanto cita<br />

queste parole di Heidegger, ma soprattutto le prende come<br />

sue. Nell’ambito dell’incontro la tradizionale opposizione fra attività<br />

e passività perde la sua ragion d’essere. Secondo Marcel<br />

non si tratta soltanto di una certa “zona” d’incontro, ma essenzialmente<br />

di “comunicazione e di volontà di comunicare” 22 .<br />

Questa affermazione investe la prima comunicazione tra “corpo”<br />

e “mio”. Per Marcel non esiste la distinzione fra “il mio corpo”,<br />

considerato un corpo qualunque, ed il mio “io”. Sia la riflessione<br />

primaria-diretta-comune (il piano dell’esistenza immediata)<br />

che la riflessione di secondo grado (la relazione oggettiva<br />

ed ontologica: partecipazione, comunione) confermano che<br />

“questo corpo” è e non può essere che “il mio corpo”. Ambedue<br />

le riflessioni prendono come punto d’appoggio l’inseparabilità<br />

esistenziale tra il mio “io” e “il mio corpo”. La questione essenziale<br />

riguarda la nozione di avere: io non ho “corpo” come ho il<br />

mio cane, ma io sono corporeo. L’io del possesso non può mai<br />

essere ridotto – secondo Marcel – “ad un io del tutto smaterializzato”<br />

23 . L’unità sui generis che costituisce “il mio corpo” in<br />

quanto mio è l’unità perfetta ed esistenziale. Dire “il mio corpo”<br />

21 ME, 71-72.<br />

22 ME, 78; cfr E. SOTTIAUX, Gabriel Marcel. Philosophe et dramaturge,<br />

Nauwelaerts, Louvain 1956, 29-82 (La communion ontologique).<br />

23 ME, 96-97.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 149<br />

significa negare il dualismo cartesiano e l’interpretazione del parallelismo<br />

di tipo spinoziano. Neppure posso concepire “il mio<br />

corpo” come un mio strumento o come il mezzo con cui agisco<br />

nel mondo, inserendomi così in esso, come ha voluto per esempio<br />

H. Bergson. Io non mi servo del mio corpo, ma invece “io sono<br />

il mio corpo” 24 . Inoltre, è legittimo dire “io sono il mio corpo”<br />

solo in quanto io riconosco che questo corpo non è oggettivabile,<br />

non è “qualcosa”, ma “corpo-soggetto” (“l’io in carne ed ossa”)<br />

perché io ho con lui un certo tipo di relazione-comunicazione-legame<br />

che non si può oggettivare. Io posso, infatti, identificarmi<br />

con il mio corpo. A questo <strong>propos</strong>ito Marcel preferisce<br />

parlare dell’incarnazione perché questo termine “indica la situazione<br />

di un essere legato fondamentalmente e non accidentalmente<br />

al ‘suo corpo’” 25 .<br />

Per stabilire ciò che ha di specifico “il mio corpo” in quanto<br />

“mio”, si deve affrontare il problema della sensazione. “La sensibilità<br />

è indissolubilmente legata al fatto che questo corpo è il<br />

mio corpo e non un corpo fra altri” 26 . Per comprendere la natura<br />

essenziale della sensibilità si deve parlare di una specie di comunicazione<br />

tra due poli: uno che emette un messaggio e un altro<br />

che registra, traduce ed interpreta questo messaggio, chiamato<br />

da Marcel la “sensazione”. La sensibilità è immediata e<br />

non disgiungibile dal mio corpo. Il suo contenuto “qui” ed “adesso”<br />

sentito è l’immediato esistenziale, cioè una realtà che io sono<br />

veramente. Non si tratta affatto di un contenuto del pensiero<br />

deduttivo e ricostruttivo, ma della “partecipazione immersa”<br />

sulla base dell’esistenza stessa della sensibilità, significa ricevere<br />

in sé con l’atto dinamico ed attivo di accogliere – chiamato da<br />

Marcel “responsività”, che si oppone radicalmente all’inerzia interiore<br />

che è l’insensibilità o l’apatia – significa partecipare all’esistenza<br />

stessa 27 . Per ben esporre il dualismo irriducibile tra ciò<br />

24 ME, 99.<br />

25 ME, 100; cfr G. MARCEL, Homo Viator, Aubier, Paris 1945, 97 [HV];<br />

DH, 70.<br />

26 ME, 103; cfr G. MARCEL, Giornale metafisico (1915-1923), Abete, Roma<br />

1966, 219-226 [GM]; Esistenza ed oggettività, in: Giornale metafisico. Esistenza<br />

e oggettività, Abete, Roma 1980, 213-219.<br />

27 ME, 115-116.


150 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

che è insensibile, non-responsivo e ciò che invece è sensibile, responsivo<br />

e partecipa all’esistenza stessa, Marcel usa un esempio<br />

fornito dall’embriologia. Due persone, lo scienziato e l’artista,<br />

osservano un processo embrionale che si effettua nel tempo come<br />

un film – che ci permette solo di sintetizzare in modo intuitivo<br />

una evoluzione di una certa struttura che si complica progressivamente<br />

– perché “non esistono ancora mezzi di osservazione<br />

capaci di cogliere l’essenza del dinamismo interno, di cui<br />

ciò che noi vediamo è solo la manifestazione”. Lo scienziato ha<br />

l’ambizione di riprodurre quella realtà, di fabbricare cioè la vita.<br />

L’artista, lungi dall’essere affascinato dal processo di formazione<br />

che assorbe l’attenzione del biologo, guarda alla forma realizzata<br />

e trova in se stesso le capacità di farla rivivere, di ricrearla<br />

col pennello o con lo scalpello. “Questi due richiami –<br />

conclude Marcel – non possono comporsi in unità, anzi sono inversi:<br />

quello dell’artista, lo si può captare ed attuare solo nell’ambito<br />

di una partecipazione, l’altro invece implica proprio la<br />

negazione della partecipazione, in quanto presuppone un atteggiamento<br />

che, in una visuale religiosa, o meglio sacrale, del<br />

mondo potrebbe essere considerato sacrilego… Per una strana e<br />

singolare contraddizione, egli riesce a convincersi, e cerca di<br />

convincere gli altri, di essere riuscito a riprodurre l’origine autentica<br />

del processo, e vuole dimostrare in tal modo che la vita<br />

si crea da sé senza l’intervento di una potenza creatrice” 28 .<br />

La partecipazione supera considerevolmente i limiti della<br />

sensibilità nella contemplazione da parte dell’io. La contemplazione<br />

in quanto atto intelligibile non si esaurisce nello sguardo<br />

o nel guardare, ma come la ricerca tende a conoscere l’oggetto<br />

nella sua unicità per raccoglierlo. Contemplare – afferma Marcel<br />

– significa “raccogliersi in presenza di” al punto che la realtà alla<br />

cui presenza ci si raccoglie entra a far parte del raccoglimento<br />

stesso 29 . Raccogliersi non significa isolarsi, abbandonare. “Il<br />

raccoglimento è invece innanzi tutto un atto con cui ci si rivolge<br />

‘verso’ senza abbandonare nulla” 30 . Rivolgersi “verso” signifi-<br />

28 ME, 116-117.<br />

29 ME, 122.<br />

30 ME, 124.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 151<br />

ca “rientrare in sé” per esaminare la situazione da un altro angolo<br />

di visuale (un atto creativo) e poi “uscire da sé” trasformato<br />

interiormente. Il raccoglimento a livello metafisico comporta<br />

immediatamente la chiarificazione dei rapporti fra me e la mia<br />

vita: accogliere la verità del reale e ricomporre l’unità personale<br />

dell’io (ricevere se-stesso, accogliere in se stesso). In altre parole<br />

si tratta di “essere in una situazione” 31 . L’essere in una situazione<br />

e l’essere in cammino (essere-viaggiante) sono – secondo Marcel<br />

– i modi inseparabili, i due aspetti complementari della nostra<br />

condizione umana 32 . Nel primo caso si tratta del rapporto<br />

tra l’io e il dato circostanziale (la mia vita vissuta, la mia situazione,<br />

la mia esperienza concreta) 33 . Secondo Marcel quest’ultimo<br />

interviene solo in rapporto ad una attività libera da parte<br />

dell’io, perché il dato non possiede nessuna autorità (“la noncontingenza<br />

del dato circostanziale”) 34 . Ma Marcel non si ferma<br />

al livello della riflessione primaria del dato, cioè alla riflessione<br />

di primo grado dell’esistenza immediata alla luce delle categorie<br />

del vedere e dell’avere, dove c’è un mondo neutro, asettico e<br />

spersonalizzato. Nella riflessione seconda, quella del sapere metafisico<br />

(ontologico), egli ricupera l’immediatezza dell’esistenza<br />

per ristabilire l’unità del dato con il resto del reale (la totalità<br />

dell’essere) e dell’io pensante con la realtà pensata, per realizzare<br />

in questo modo il rapporto di partecipazione ontologica: la<br />

comunione con me stesso, con gli altri e con la realtà 35 . L’articolazione<br />

stessa di “riflessione prima” e “riflessione seconda” riflette<br />

non tanto un diverso modo di conoscere-comprendere la<br />

realtà, ma una diversità di partecipazione a questa realtà: dalla<br />

partecipazione pre-cosciente alla partecipazione oggettiva (“partecipazioni<br />

immerse”) e poi alla partecipazione ontologica, chia-<br />

31 ME, 126.<br />

32 ME, 128; cfr S. PLOURDE, Gabriel Marcel. Philosophe et témoin de l’espérance,<br />

Les Presses de l’Université du Québec, Montréal 1975, 129-223<br />

(L’Etre en marche).<br />

33 G. MARCEL, Les Hommes contre l’Humain, Fayard, Paris 1968, 7<br />

[HCH].<br />

34 ME, 128-130.<br />

35 EA, 166, 171, MEI, 97-98, 108, 130-131; HCH, 198.


152 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

mata la “partecipazione emersa” o la “comunione ontologica” 36 .<br />

I tre livelli di partecipazione: pre-cosciente dell’esistere (io esisto),<br />

oggettiva dell’avere (io ho) ed ontologica dell’essere (io sono),<br />

corrispondono ai tre piani di intelligibilità che sono quelli<br />

dell’esistenza immediata (io sento), dell’astrazione (io penso) e<br />

della “fede” (io credo) 37 .<br />

Quando il dato presenta un valore positivo, contribuisce<br />

cioè ad uno sviluppo creativo dell’io nell’intimità del raccoglimento<br />

al livello ontologico dell’essere, la creazione dell’interiorità,<br />

dell’io passa attraverso le posizioni prese da parte dell’io di<br />

fronte alla sua vita. L’io dovrebbe dunque vivere la sua vita, che<br />

porta in sé, per essere veramente se stesso in nome della sua vocazione.<br />

Essa s’impone all’io non come necessità da parte dei<br />

fatti, oppure come una fatalità, ma come una chiamata 38 . L’io<br />

sono nell’io so ciò che sono e ciò che posso-devo diventare è chiamato<br />

ad autorealizzare, autocreare essenzialmente l’io in cammino<br />

verso la pienezza di verità 39 . “Una persona viva si rivela<br />

sempre come essenzialmente creatrice. Da questo punto di vista<br />

si può capire meglio come la creatività sia legata originariamente<br />

all’esistenza, benché quest’ultima abbia sempre in sé la possibilità<br />

di decadere, di diventare torpore, malinconica ripetizione,<br />

routine mortale. Forse queste semplici osservazioni hanno in sé<br />

un autentico significato etico che permette di conferire ad una<br />

persona una dignità, senza ricorrere ad un formalismo spesso<br />

sterile, portato a misconoscere ciò che vi è di irriducibile nelle<br />

situazioni e nelle azioni umane” 40 . La constatazione marceliana<br />

è chiara: la libertà e la creatività sono alla base dell’etica. “L’essere<br />

è l’attesa che si compie e questa opera di compimento è l’esperienza<br />

dell’essere” 41 . La scoperta dell’indicativo ontologico di<br />

36 ME, 78-101, 102-120; J. DELHOMME, Témoignage et dialectique, in: AA.<br />

VV., Existentialisme chrétien: Gabriel Marcel, Plon, Paris 1947, 117-201.<br />

37 R. TROISFONTAINES, De l’Existence à l’Etre. La philosophie de Gabriel<br />

Marcel, I-II vol., Nauwelaerts, Louvain-Paris 1968, 206; M. COZZOLI, L’uomo<br />

in cammino verso, op. cit., 32-35.<br />

38 ME, 128-131.<br />

39 ME, 234.<br />

40 ME, 132.<br />

41 ME, 235.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 153<br />

essere-in-cammino e di essere-sempre-più, come cammino dall’esistere<br />

all’essere e come intensificazione progressiva nell’essere,<br />

diventa – attraverso gli atti liberi-creativi - la conoscenza personale,<br />

eticamente orientata e impegnata 42 . L’esigenza ontologica<br />

dell’essere uomo è sempre in Marcel la dimensione etica dell’essere<br />

più uomo-persona. La dimensione etica dell’essere fondata<br />

sull’intensificazione ontologica nell’essere, come cammino<br />

di crescita, di maturazione e di realizzazione 43 , non può svolgersi<br />

– secondo Marcel – “se non nella direzione di una comunità<br />

aperta”. L’io si crea attraverso gli altri e con gli altri. L’intersoggettività,<br />

allora, sta alla base dell’ontologia marceliana 44 ed anche,<br />

secondo me, essa fonda l’etica dell’incontro di G. Marcel.<br />

2. L’etica dell’incontro – una dimensione etica della persona<br />

Prima di esporre il tema della intersoggettività e dell’etica,<br />

occorre ancora chiarire e qualificare la categoria della soggettività,<br />

da cui si stacca la stessa intersoggettività. La soggettività si<br />

polarizza intorno all’essere-uomo-persona come risulta dall’interrogativo<br />

metafisico marceliano: “Chi sono io?”. Nella sua metafisica<br />

esistenziale G. Marcel non cerca oggetti e la loro intelligibilità,<br />

ma si accosta a ciò che cade direttamente sotto la nostra<br />

personale esistenza storica, cioè la realtà-presenza delle cose che<br />

ad essa appartengono: la sensazione, il corpo e l’esistere. La sensazione<br />

è una partecipazione esistenziale immediata, nella quale<br />

l’oggetto è accolto in me, esso entra in mio possesso e perde la<br />

sua oggettività: l’avere è il mio essere. L’oggetto, prendendo contatto<br />

con il mio corpo, vi si assimila: l’esistenza perde l’avere e<br />

diviene essere. L’essere è un riconoscere attraverso il mio corpo<br />

ciò che è dato nella sensazione. L’esistenza immediata del mio<br />

42 EA, 26; M. COZZOLI, L’uomo in cammino verso, op. cit., 268-271.<br />

43 EA, 123.<br />

44 ME, 209, 248; UP, 57; cfr D. COMPOSTA, Intersoggettività e morale, op.<br />

cit., 76-83; M. COZZOLI, L’uomo in cammino verso, op. cit., 280-282; D. A. JO-<br />

SEPH, Self Realization and Intersubjectivity in Gabriel Marcel (A Doctoral Dissertation),<br />

Pontifical Urban University, Roma 1988, 128-158, 159-199.


154 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

essere è legata alla sensazione e mediante la sensazione, al mondo.<br />

La mia partecipazione al mondo – chiamata da Marcel l’engagement<br />

– invoca una “fede” e una riflessione. Il credere è l’impegno<br />

nell’esistenza e aderenza alla concretezza del vivere in<br />

una situazione come fatto interiore alla volontà (libertà). Al contrario,<br />

il pensare è oggettivazione formalista, astratta e indeterminata.<br />

Inoltre, credere è libertà personale creativa 45 . Non basta<br />

affermare che la persona è soggetto – secondo Marcel – essa è libera.<br />

La libertà, infatti, individua e differenzia la persona dalle<br />

altre persone, essa è personale e coinvolge la decisione. Questa<br />

decisione non è che un atto con cui la persona si sceglie, si impegna,<br />

si progetta e infine si crea. L’essere uomo presuppone il<br />

dinamismo dell’agire umano come autotrascendenza, autorealizzazione<br />

ed autocreazione. L’autocreazione non è che il ricupero<br />

e la riconquista di ciò che già è nell’essere-più. La mia libertà<br />

– in quanto processo di liberazione 46 e mai come produzione<br />

47 , perché è creata per la coscienza 48 – è chiamata a compiersi<br />

nelle molteplici situazioni-scelte (l’engagement), da cui è<br />

segnato il mio cammino di homo viator. L’agire a sua volta si dinamizza<br />

come attuazione coerente e libera della verità dell’essere.<br />

Essere e agire, allora, non sono due espressioni autonome e<br />

neppure contigue di una stessa esistenza incarnata, ma due<br />

realtà dinamiche che si implicano e si compenetrano fra loro. In<br />

Marcel, infatti, non si può parlare di ontologia eticamente neutra,<br />

come non si trova in lui l’etica ontologicamente autonoma:<br />

ontologia ed etica sono in intima e solidale compenetrazione.<br />

L’ontologia marceliana è nel contempo etica e viceversa l’etica è<br />

ontologica 49 .<br />

L’ontologia etica esistenziale – più significativa in Marcel –<br />

non soltanto si svolge nella sua etica ontologica, ma traccia anche<br />

le dimensioni etiche della sua antropologia: la crescita tota-<br />

45 MEI, 137-140; ME, 102-120, 216-226; D. COMPOSTA, Intersoggettività e<br />

morale, op. cit., 68-74.<br />

46 G. MARCEL, Du Refus à l’invocation, Gallimard 1940, 73.<br />

47 MEII, 140.<br />

48 MEII, 117; cfr J. P. BAGOT, Connaissance et Amour. Essai sur la philosophie<br />

de Gabriel Marcel, Beauchesne, Paris 1958, 190-199.<br />

49 M. COZZOLI, L’uomo in cammino verso, op. cit., 267-271.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 155<br />

le dell’uomo al suo essere è la realizzazione etica della persona.<br />

L’intensificazione ontologica nell’essere si trasfigura nel processo<br />

di personalizzazione: un processo che è progredire, trascendersi<br />

e compiersi. L’io diventa persona umana nella misura stessa<br />

in cui impegna la sua libertà nel cammino dall’esistenza all’essere:<br />

dall’io esisto all’io sono 50 . La conoscenza filosofica incarnata<br />

dell’essere-in-situazione è sempre in Marcel la conoscenza-coscienza<br />

eticamente orientata e impegnata. “Il logos –<br />

secondo Pietro Prini – è un ethos profondo” 51 . Affermare questo<br />

non significa che il conoscere si svuoti dei suoi aspetti intellettivi,<br />

ma si determina in esso – afferma Cozzoli – “una coincidenza<br />

dialettica di intelletto e di volontà, di verità e di libertà, di logos<br />

e di ethos” 52 . Riconoscere il suo carattere ontologico intensivo<br />

come essere-più è nello stesso tempo l’affermazione etica dell’essere<br />

più persona che coinvolge e dispone la sua libertà-volontà.<br />

Così la coscienza morale è simultanea alla coscienza ontologica<br />

53 . La coscienza morale di Marcel è fondata sulla morale<br />

della persona che tiene conto del cammino esistenziale dell’individuo,<br />

dell’apporto ontologicamente determinate della sua<br />

coscienza, della conoscenza come sensazione e partecipazione,<br />

incontro e comunione 54 .<br />

Per Marcel non esiste la libertà in quanto facoltà assoluta,<br />

demotivata oppure come la semplice capacità di scelta (Sartre).<br />

Neppure esiste la morale autonoma, distaccata dall’ontologia<br />

fondata solo sul razionalismo puro ed astratto (si pensi alla critica<br />

di Marcel dell’autonomia della morale kantiana 55 ). La vera<br />

libertà si erige a offerta assoluta a Dio-Essere-Amore. L’Essere-<br />

Amore fonda, suscita e indirizza eticamente la libertà dell’uomo,<br />

perché l’essere io si riconosce come essere-partecipante nell’Essere<br />

in quanto Fonte-Fine del suo essere verso-per-con. La co-<br />

50 Ibidem, 198-201, 268-270; P. RICOEUR e G. MARCEL, Per un’etica dell’alterità.<br />

Sei colloqui, op. cit., 127; HV, 30-33.<br />

51 P. PRINI, Gabriel Marcel e la metodologia dell’inverificabile, Studium,<br />

Roma 1968, 81.<br />

52 M. COZZOLI, L’uomo in cammino verso, op. cit., 270.<br />

53 Ibidem, 271.<br />

54 Ibidem, 272; J. P. BARGOT, Connaissance et Amour, op. cit., 213-229.<br />

55 GM, 101-107.


156 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

munione tra Dio-Tu e l’io pone la libertà autentica (“la verità della<br />

libertà”). Non esiste allora opposizione tra libertà e grazia perché<br />

l’io riconosce in Dio l’Autore e la Guida del suo essere, nonché<br />

il Fine-Bene-Valore supremo del suo essere-da-compiere nell’Amore<br />

56 . “Camminare nell’essere verso l’Essere è costituirsi e<br />

maturarsi come persona” 57 . Riconoscere il suo essere nell’Essere-Verità-Vita<br />

e camminare nell’essere verso l’Essere-Fine-Pienezza<br />

implica il suo agire verso l’Essere-Bene-Valore. La verità<br />

dell’essere (logos) nell’esperienza del co-essere si rivela nella verità<br />

come valore-bene che impegna l’uomo nel momento stesso<br />

in cui la riconosce (ethos). E viceversa, attraverso il suo impegno<br />

etico l’uomo riconosce il suo essere 58 . L’esigenza ontologica dell’essere-più<br />

è l’imperativo morale dell’essere come valore-bene<br />

da “realizzare”, cioè da vivere-compiere. In seguito non si può rivendicare<br />

l’autonomia dell’agire dall’essere. Il fondamento universale<br />

ontologico-morale dell’essere-uomo-valore-bene si fonda<br />

nel co-Essere, nel riconoscersi e nel conformarsi al Valore-Bene.<br />

La morale esistenziale e personale, orientata essenzialmente verso<br />

la Trascendenza, si realizza come compresenza di universalità<br />

(l’Essere-Bene-Valore) e incarnazione (l’io esistenzialmente situato-agente).<br />

Come io non creo l’Essere, ma solo lo riconosco,<br />

entro in partecipazione e da Lui mi lascio illuminare e guidare,<br />

lo stesso si passa con i valori: io non creo i valori, ma io mi apro<br />

ai valori, li incarno nella mia vita e mi lascio illuminare nel mio<br />

agire 59 . “Il valore è come l’orizzonte sul quale risalta il progetto,<br />

cioè l’azione. Possiamo anche affermare che esso è l’interpretazione<br />

schematica che la coscienza dà a se stessa dell’impresa,<br />

nella quale si impegna tuffandosi nell’azione” 60 . L’appello ontologico<br />

dell’essere-più è l’appello etico dei valori per intensificare<br />

56 ME, 254-266, 267-284, 285-297; EA, 329-331; cfr E. SOTTIAUX, Gabriel<br />

Marcel, op. cit., 83-133 (La communion au trascendant); R. DAVIGNON, Le mal<br />

chez Gabriel Marcel, op. cit., 81-91, 111-139.<br />

57 M. COZZOLI, L’uomo in cammino verso, op.cit., 269; HV, 30-33; GM, 40-<br />

49.<br />

58 M. COZZOLI, L’uomo in cammino verso, op. cit., 276.<br />

59 Ibidem, 277; J. P. BARGOT, Connaissance et Amour, op. cit., 207-211;<br />

HCH, 87, 128; UP, 40-41, 49; HV, 34-35.<br />

60 UP, 40-41.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 157<br />

il suo essere nel suo agire: essere-più significa essere-più-uomo<br />

in quanto persona. I valori sono dunque punti d’incontro del logos<br />

e dell’ethos. Tradurre l’essere nel termine persona fa emergere<br />

il suo significato etico come valore-bene. L’uomo deve custodire,<br />

promuovere, sviluppare e compiere il suo essere per essere<br />

più uomo. Inoltre, l’essere più uomo significa intraprendere il<br />

processo della personalizzazione: la realizzazione etica dell’uomo<br />

in quanto persona.<br />

“L’essere – afferma Marcel – non si può separare da una certa<br />

pienezza di verità” 61 . “Pienezza”, in quanto portata ontologica,<br />

non è interpretata da Marcel in senso quantitativo come totalità,<br />

ma come quid non rappresentabile, non proiettabile in<br />

una raffigurazione. L’esigenza o meglio il bisogno di pienezza<br />

dell’uomo fa parte dell’esperienza del suo essere come esserepiù,<br />

essere in cammino ed essere-da-compiere. L’essere uomo significa<br />

appunto essere “pastore dell’essere”. Questa molto significativa<br />

definizione dell’uomo di M. Heidegger è stata ripresa e<br />

sviluppata da Marcel in L’uomo problematico 62 . “Affermare che<br />

l’uomo è il pastore dell’essere significa attribuirgli una responsabilità<br />

ontologica. La qual cosa non avrebbe senso, a dire il vero,<br />

se l’essere fosse concepito come dotato di una esistenza in sé,<br />

alla maniera della natura, quale almeno siamo abituati a concepirla.<br />

D’altronde – sempre perché la formula abbia senso – non<br />

si tratterebbe di ridurre l’essere alla modalità del soggetto pensante,<br />

conformemente a certo idealismo” 63 . Il concetto antropologico-ontologico<br />

dell’uomo di Marcel mette in luce il carattere<br />

crescente e relazionale della persona. Il suo profondo carattere<br />

ontologico in quanto intensificazione dell’essere, articolato con<br />

la sua libertà, è nello stesso tempo affermazione etica che coinvolge<br />

e dispone la sua volontà. L’identità uomo-pastore non può<br />

essere veramente compresa in senso funzionale (essere-custodire)<br />

se non come atto d’amore 64 . L’amore suppone sempre la libertà<br />

umana e l’apertura verso un altro diverso da sé come l’altro<br />

essere-io-uomo e soprattutto verso Uno più grande di lui:<br />

61 ME, 234.<br />

62 UP, 41-62.<br />

63 UP, 41-42.<br />

64 UP, 44.


158 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

l’Essere-Tu. Il compimento dell’essere uomo nell’amore è “un<br />

modo di partecipare a” e si svolge nell’ambito dell’attività creatrice<br />

dell’essere verso, dell’essere per e dell’essere con. L’essere verso-per-con<br />

si attua in rapporto con l’Altro, che risolve in dualità<br />

l’unità d’esperienza a livello della “coscienza esclamativa di esistere”:<br />

sensazione, corpo, esistenza (la riflessione primaria). La<br />

riflessione secondaria nella forma del riconoscimento e della<br />

partecipazione ontologica, invece, riconquista questa unità tra<br />

l’Io e il Tu e si trasfigura in una comunione esistenziale: noi due<br />

viviamo nella comunicazione delle proprie esperienze di significati<br />

e valori personali. L’incontro dell’Io con il Tu e il riconoscimento<br />

del Tu fonda l’intersoggettività dal quale spunta la partecipazione<br />

ontologica dell’uno nell’altro: Noi 65 .<br />

Il fondamento dell’etica di G. Marcel è dunque l’incontro esistenziale<br />

dell’Io con il Tu, che si attua nella comunione reciproca<br />

mediante il dialogo e l’amore tra l’Io e il Tu per creare la nuova<br />

realtà: Noi. Il dialogo e l’amore non sono correlati, ma ambedue<br />

tracciano la dimensione etica dell’intersoggettività: l’incontro<br />

dialogico con l’amore o l’amore reciproco ove l’incontro e il<br />

dialogo non sono essenziali 66 . L’incontro l’io-Tu come partecipazione<br />

dell’essere nell’Essere fa riconoscere l’Essere-Amore. L’Amore<br />

è il Valore nel quale tutti i valori si riconoscono e a cui tutti<br />

si riconducono 67 . I valori sono sempre i punti dell’incontro del<br />

logos (Essere) e dell’ethos (Amore). In essi l’Essere, per cui tutti<br />

gli esseri umani sono, si rivela a loro come Amore: l’Essere è<br />

Amore. Ed esseri umani in quanto persone, invece, scoprono<br />

l’imperativo etico e il senso morale del loro essere attraverso il<br />

riconoscersi e vivere per l’Amore, e nell’Amore 68 . “Vivere nell’Amore”<br />

non solo suppone ed attesta una libertà della persona, ma<br />

anche impegna ed indirizza la persona-libertà a prendere la responsabilità<br />

dell’attestazione di sé come persona in una comunità<br />

di persone. Solo l’amore mi permette di conoscere piena-<br />

65 ME, 78-101, 102-120; GM, 61-64, 95-100; J. P. BAGOT, Connaissance et<br />

Amour, op. cit., 215; D. COMPOSTA, Intersoggettività e morale, op. cit., 76-78.<br />

66 Ibidem, 78-83.<br />

67 HCH, 140-141; M. COZZOLI, L’uomo in cammino verso, op. cit., 181,<br />

278.<br />

68 Ibidem, 278.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 159<br />

mente me stesso e l’altro in quanto Tu. La logica della libertà si<br />

traduce infatti nella profonda esigenza morale – come istanza<br />

primaria dell’esistenzialità – della promozione e dello sviluppo,<br />

della partecipazione e della comunione. Le capacità di partecipazione<br />

e di comunione danno alle persone la misura della maturazione<br />

nell’essere, della realizzazione e della pienezza della<br />

vita umana. L’incontro interpersonale in Marcel è impensabile e<br />

irrealizzabile al di fuori dell’impegno etico dell’amore-carità<br />

mentre l’amore-carità non è un valore se non è l’indicativo-imperativo<br />

dell’intersoggettività 69 . L’amore-carità non solo rende<br />

possibile e intensifica la comunione delle persone, ma come appello<br />

alla libertà della persona a disporsi eticamente rende possibile<br />

e intensifica la persona stessa in quanto essere verso-percon.<br />

L’esigenza ontologica dell’intersoggettività per essere l’iouomo-persona<br />

è dunque l’imperativo etico dell’amore-caritàagapé:<br />

io sono perché io amo, io sono perché noi siamo, io sono<br />

l’amore che mi fa essere 70 . Dall’imperativo etico dell’amore per essere-uomo-persona<br />

nasce la fedeltà all’essere-amore come responsabilità<br />

morale. Questa fedeltà all’essere-amore e responsabilità<br />

dell’essere-amore è il criterio normativo dell’agire morale<br />

e della coscienza morale. Siccome l’essere-amore è co-Essere<br />

nell’Amore allora il criterio normativo universale, assoluto e unificante<br />

dell’agire morale umano è l’Essere-Amore che costituisce<br />

ontologicamente l’essere-uomo-persona e lo dinamizza eticamente.<br />

L’etica dell’incontro è l’etica dell’amore-carità-agàpe 71 .<br />

Concludendo possiamo dire che l’uomo come pastore dell’essere<br />

(aspetto ontologico) diventa “buon pastore” quando<br />

ama, unisce e fa comunione (aspetto etico). La verità dell’essere<br />

come esigenza ontologica e la verità dell’amore in quanto imperativo<br />

etico si incontrano nell’interiorità di ogni coscienza morale<br />

e fanno appello alla libertà che implica e rivela per se stessa<br />

un profondo senso morale: fedeltà alla verità dell’essere e responsabilità<br />

della verità dell’amore per essere-uomo-persona. Allora,<br />

ogni atto di libertà – che è insieme un riconoscimento e una<br />

scelta: accogliere l’essere (verità, bene, amore) e rifiutare il non-<br />

69 Ibidem, 281.<br />

70 Ibidem, 175-198, 281, 186.<br />

71 Ibidem, 280-296.


160 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

essere (menzogna, male, egoismo) – orienta tutta la vita umana<br />

personale: l’opzione fondamentale verso la verità dell’essereamore<br />

in quanto co-Essere nell’Amore-Verità-Bene. Di conseguenza,<br />

ogni atto della libertà umana ha, allo stesso tempo, valore<br />

ontologico ed etico, cioè conferma, crea e realizza l’uomo in<br />

quanto persona. In questo contesto, l’uomo come pastore dell’essere<br />

e “buon pastore” che ama l’essere, diventa pastore-creatore<br />

dell’essere. L’ambito della creazione graduale e intensificante<br />

dell’essere è sempre la vita morale: optare per l’Essere-<br />

Amore ed operare nell’amore-carità-agàpe-philìa 72 . La realizzazione<br />

personale passa attraverso gli atti della libertà: ragionevoli<br />

(riconoscimento dell’io sono e dell’io sono più) e responsabili<br />

(scelta di ciò che decido di essere) per crearsi come persona. Logos<br />

come conoscenza-intensificazione-partecipazione ontologica<br />

ed ethos in quanto realizzazione ontologico-etica nell’amore<br />

si incontrano nell’unico atto creatore. La libertà creatrice è condizione<br />

fondamentale di ogni responsabilità nell’ordine morale<br />

dell’unificazione di sé ed al tempo stesso il limite morale della<br />

creazione integrale di sé e non della degradazione-destruzione<br />

di sé come persona. La condizione fondamentale ed allo stesso<br />

tempo il limite morale della libertà creatrice personale si verifica<br />

sempre su un duplice livello: la verità dell’essere-amore in<br />

quanto co-Essere nell’Amore e la libertà dell’altro come Tu-Noi.<br />

3. Implicazioni ontologiche, antropologiche ed etiche<br />

nel campo della bioetica<br />

Le due dimensioni dell’essere uomo-persona nel pensiero filosofico-antropologico<br />

di G. Marcel – enucleate nei punti precedenti:<br />

quella ontologica e quella etica – serviranno adesso per intraprendere<br />

un tentativo di ampliare con implicazioni ermeneutiche<br />

la riflessione bioetica contemporanea. L’etimologia stessa<br />

del termine bio-etica conferma del resto le tendenze bilaterali del<br />

nostro obiettivo: una <strong>propos</strong>ta-dimensione ontologico-antropo-<br />

72 ME, 209.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 161<br />

logica per bios inteso come vita umana e una <strong>propos</strong>ta-dimensione<br />

ontologico-antropologico-etica per ethos.<br />

Che spazio potrebbe acquisire – possiamo dire – G. Marcel<br />

in merito al bios umano nella riflessione bioetica contemporanea?<br />

Prima di tutto, contro ogni forma di idealismo, di soggettivismo<br />

e di dualismo nella visione antropologica dell’uomo, Marcel<br />

propone l’approccio personalistico-esistenziale a connotazione<br />

ontologico-etico ed etico-relazionale come il terreno più adatto<br />

per verificare le capacità interpretative e argomentative di<br />

fronte alla gestione dei nuovi problemi biomedici. Per rispondere<br />

a questi problemi è necessario fornire innanzitutto una chiara<br />

definizione dei punti di riferimento: l’essere uomo in quanto<br />

persona, il corpo umano, la vita umana. Nell’affermare l’essere<br />

uomo in quanto persona, il personalismo marceliano, sulla base<br />

della concezione dinamica dell’ontologia, si pone apertamente<br />

contro l’ontologia per sé, astratta ed universalistica come espressione<br />

di un’antropologia statica ed, allo stesso tempo, contro<br />

un’antropologia senza ontologia. Simili antropologie sono personalmente<br />

anonime, esistenzialmente disincarnate ed eticamente<br />

infeconde 73 . Il riconoscimento fenomenologico dell’essere<br />

uomo come “essere in cammino” conduce Marcel ad un’ontologia<br />

più esistenziale, cioè più attenta alla vita umana concreta come<br />

cammino da percorrere, processo di crescita e come intensificazione<br />

progressiva nell’essere in sé, che si snoda nella maturazione<br />

personale dell’essere per sé della persona. L’essere personale,<br />

preso nella sua inscindibile unità come l’essere incarnatoincorporato<br />

e nella sua dinamica continuità ontologico-transcendente<br />

dell’essere-più e l’essere-da-compiere in quanto co-Essere<br />

fonda, precede e supera l’essere cosciente. Sostenendo la<br />

precedenza dell’io esisto-sono dinanzi all’io penso, da parte di<br />

Marcel, significa ritrovare – utilizzando il linguaggio di P. Ricoeur<br />

– “l’ego dell’ego cogito” 74 , fondamento dei fondamenti,<br />

principio dei principi e norma delle norme. Tanto più che i rappresentanti<br />

dell’utilitarismo, “vitalismo” oppure “funzionali-<br />

73 M. COZZOLI, L’uomo in cammino verso, op.cit., 268-269.<br />

74 P. RICOEUR, Demitizzare l’accusa, in: P. RICOEUR, Il conflitto delle interpretazioni,<br />

Jaca Book, Milano 1977, 349-366.


162 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

smo”, considerando l’essere cosciente come unico criterio dell’essere<br />

uomo-persona, aprono ed entrano nella discussione meta-bioetica<br />

odierna sulla strada della “diluizione” – di cui parla<br />

Filippo Boscia 75 – per stabilire confini variabili ed artificiali tra<br />

vita umana e non-umana, individuo biologico e individuo in senso<br />

personale (ad esempio Engelhardt), la vita degna di vivere o<br />

quella da sopprimere (la cosiddetta “qualità della vita”) per suggerire<br />

l’idea di una “ontologia intermedia” da cercare attraverso<br />

l’abbandono della polarità cose-persone. Di conseguenza la persona<br />

in questa visione è ridotta al temporale soggetto parlante,<br />

oppure ad un soggetto che diventa oggetto da manipolare, ed<br />

inoltre la coscienza morale personale si riduce alla conoscenza e<br />

dunque alla scienza, l’atto umano all’applicazione implicita della<br />

norma positiva stabilita da parte della società o dei tecnocrati<br />

e la libertà alla ragione “pratica”, tecnicamente orientata. In<br />

Marcel, invece, l’io esistente-incarnato – in quanto unica unità<br />

personale – non è riducibile ai meccanismi dell’oggettività scientifico-tecnica,<br />

perché egli ha il suo cammino ontologico verso la<br />

Pienezza del suo essere nell’Essere-Fine e la vita umana storica<br />

da compiere come persona. La dimensione del superamento è<br />

collegata al recupero del mondo della vita umana personale,<br />

soggiacente e antecedente l’attività scientifica e la prassi tecnica.<br />

Da questa esigenza ontologica, in quanto recupero del “fondamento”,<br />

secondo la filosofia esistenziale dell’essere, smarrito nel<br />

mondo dell’oggettualità e della funzionalità, dove la persona è<br />

destinata a cadere nell’area della manipolazione, della frammentazione<br />

e della riduzione, nasce l’imperativo etico d’essere e<br />

di diventare persona. L’io esistente in quanto persona non soltanto<br />

indica l’abisso ontologico tra persone e cose, ma anche tra<br />

il mondo umano e non-umano (biologico, animale). L’io sono<br />

persona vuol dire io sono unico e farmi conoscere in quanto l’io<br />

unico o riconoscere dagli altri, anche in quanto persone uniche.<br />

L’io unico rivela dunque la verità del suo essere e l’autenticità<br />

del vivere il suo essere come unica possibilità della unicità del<br />

75 F. BOSCIA, Sul piano delle biotecnologie, in: M. COZZOLI (a cura di), La<br />

soggettività tra individualismo e personalismo, Edizioni VIVERE IN, Roma<br />

1996, 101-119.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 163<br />

proprio essere in quanto persona. La persona come unica possibilità<br />

del suo essere uomo e del vivere come uomo, in forza dell’atto<br />

dell’essere o meglio del co-Essere, possiede una dignità intrinseca<br />

invariabile, teleologicamente fondata, orientata e quindi<br />

non da stabilire al di fuori ad essa. L’invariabilità della dignità<br />

intrinseca dell’essere riguarda il tutto essere uomo dall’inizio alla<br />

fine del suo cammino ontologico-personale.<br />

Dalla dimensione ontologica della dignità della persona in<br />

quanto realtà inseparabile dall’essere uomo nasce la dimensione<br />

etica: la persona come norma normativa per sé e per gli altri. La<br />

persona in quanto norma normativa a se stessa è l’imperativo<br />

etico d’essere e diventare persona. L’intensificazione ontologica<br />

nell’essere – come abbiamo visto in Marcel – passa attraverso<br />

l’atto della conoscenza-libertà: accedere all’essere (io sono) e<br />

camminare nell’essere (io sono ciò che desidero essere) per costituirsi<br />

come persona (processo di personalizzazione). La conoscenza<br />

di se stesso dell’essere in cammino (essere-da-compiere,<br />

essere-storia, essere-nel-mondo) e dell’essere incarnato (io sono<br />

corporeo) diventa conoscenza-coscienza concreata, eticamente<br />

orientata e impegnata. Da questa constatazione risulta che la coscienza<br />

morale personale focalizza la concentrazione dell’io verso<br />

il proprio essere e la sua espansione nel mondo. La coscienza<br />

e l’agire morali sono la creazione-realizzazione in atto della persona<br />

e nello stesso tempo l’affermazione-effusione del suo essere-persona.<br />

La persona come norma normativa ad altri è anche<br />

l’imperativo etico che esige di rispettare la dignità della persona<br />

in quanto persona, cioè gli altri (si pensi in questo conteso ai<br />

medici, ai biologici o agli scienziati) debbono garantire, promuovere<br />

e custodire il processo di sviluppo dell’essere-uomopersona.<br />

Questo processo non può passare che attraverso il suo<br />

corpo umano-personale e nella sua storia umana e personale come<br />

unica possibilità d’essere-diventare persona e d’essere al<br />

mondo. Allora, la riflessione meta-bioetica deve non soltanto riconoscere<br />

questo principio dei principi per essere fedele alla verità<br />

dell’essere e alla verità cognitivo-ermenutica (logos), ma soprattutto<br />

deve cominciare la sua riflessione da questo principio<br />

per difendere la persona dalle minacce da parte della prassi biomedicale<br />

e il mondo dalla minaccia di una globale e totale catastrofe<br />

ecologica (ethos). La bioetica come scienza non può dunque<br />

rappresentare una minaccia costante all’uomo e al suo am-


164 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

bito naturale, ma al contrario deve proteggere l’integrità e l’autonomia<br />

dell’uomo in quanto persona collaborando strettamente<br />

con l’antropologia e l’etica. La persona deve essere l’inizio, il<br />

centro, la direzione e il fine della riflessione e della prassi della<br />

bioetica e non sempre l’oggetto da indagare per essere poi l’oggetto<br />

da stabilire, da manipolare. Tanto più che la dimensione<br />

umana è prioritaria e soggiacente, la bioetica in quanto scienza<br />

non può maturare in conflitto con l’antropologia e l’etica, né respingerne<br />

il ruolo di guida, pur nel rispetto di ambiti e di logiche<br />

diversi. La bioetica in quanto scienza non può maturare perché:<br />

in primo luogo, non vuole dentro di sé ricostruire o recuperare<br />

il soggetto-persona dal suo “oggetto-persona” e neanche si<br />

rende conto che lo stesso soggetto-persona che fa teoria-prassi<br />

biomedica, fra poco tempo, può diventare anche “oggetto” della<br />

sua teoria-prassi, ma al contrario tende ad una totale oggettivabilità<br />

delle realtà umane-personali, in seconda istanza, vuole invece<br />

sostituire l’antropologia e l’etica per stabilire criteri dell’uomo-persona<br />

e norme morali al di là di esse e per questo uscire illegittimamente<br />

dal suo campo metodologicamente organizzato<br />

ed epistemologicamente determinato. Tale conflittualità minaccia<br />

la perdita del suo rigore e della sua praticabilità in quanto<br />

scienza.<br />

Inoltre, la verità e fedeltà all’essere, in modo particolare all’essere-uomo-persona,<br />

significa prendere la responsabilità morale<br />

individuale e collettiva di ogni forma di bios. Creare un nuovo<br />

ethos in quanto lo scopo principale della riflessione bioetica<br />

contemporanea si traduce dunque in un duplice impegno, in<br />

realtà dialettico e complementare: in primo luogo, la formazione<br />

della coscienza e dell’agire morale individuale pro life, poi,<br />

svegliare, attivare e formare la “coscienza morale collettiva” nella<br />

forma della cultura etica, della cultura della vita e della responsabilità<br />

sociale e politica di ogni forma di vita (l’etica dell’ecologia),<br />

e di vita umana personale in particolare, da parte degli<br />

organismi nazionali ed internazionali 76 .<br />

76 Donum vitae, nn. 1-2; Parte III Morale e legge civile; Evangelium vitae,<br />

nn. 78-101; Veritatis splendor, nn. 64, 97-99; G. PIANA, Persona e società: per<br />

una rifondazione etica della politica, in: AA. VV., Persona e personalismo, Fondazione<br />

LANZA, Padova 1992, 187-203; L. SANTORI, La persona nella storia


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 165<br />

Forse più pertinente può apparire il richiamo al principio<br />

dell’amore per l’attivazione e l’intensificazione di un’autentica dinamica<br />

di unità e di universalità degli uomini in relazione persona-persona<br />

e persona-comunità delle persone come <strong>propos</strong>tadimensione<br />

ontologico-antropologico-etica per ethos in quanto<br />

l’etica dell’incontro nell’amore di G. Marcel. Il pensatore francese,<br />

abbandonando il principio della ratio come affermazione di<br />

uno stile di “introversione egocentrica” (tutto e tutti per il soggetto<br />

oppure secondo soggetto) e fornitore fondamentale della<br />

morale autonoma (creazione arbitraria dell’etica da parte del<br />

soggetto), propone al contrario il principio dell’amore-caritàagàpe<br />

che muove il soggetto – che in Marcel è sempre l’essere-uomo-persona<br />

– verso il soggetto e l’oggetto. La ratio obbliga a dividere<br />

e a distinguere tra soggetto pensante-riconoscente e soggetto-oggetto<br />

da riconoscere, l’amore, invece, conduce all’unione<br />

interpersonale fino alla contemplazione-participazione-comunione,<br />

cioè all’uscire da sé come l’essere-verso-per-con e al ricevere-accogliere<br />

l’altro-essere-verso-per-con in sé. L’uscire da sé e<br />

l’accogliere in sé, come la fecondità ontologica dell’essere nell’amore,<br />

crea l’essere-uomo-persona in quanto persona ed al tempo<br />

stesso crea la comunità delle persone, “la città degli uomini”<br />

(“mondo delle persone”, personne des personnes di E. Mounier)<br />

e anche la comunione con il mondo non-umano (“la casa dell’essere”<br />

direbbe Heidegger). L’ontologia etica esistenziale di<br />

Marcel non soltanto si svolge nell’etica ontologica, ma anche<br />

traccia le dimensioni etiche dell’antropologia: la partecipazione<br />

intensiva dell’uomo al suo essere è la creazione-realizzazione etica<br />

della persona. Questa realizzazione passa attraverso l’incontro-dialogo-comunione-amore<br />

con gli altri e con il mondo, perché<br />

la conoscenza filosofica è sempre in Marcel la conoscenzacoscienza<br />

personale, eticamente orientata e impegnata. Riconoscere<br />

il suo carattere ontologico intensivo come essere-più, che<br />

è nello stesso tempo l’affermazione etica dell’essere più uomopersona,<br />

significa riconoscere anche il suo carattere trascenden-<br />

della teologia, ivi, 173-183; J. Bouëssée, A. Marcel (a cura di), Gabriel Marcel<br />

et les injustices de ce temps. La responsabilité du philosophe, Cahier 4, Présence<br />

de Gabriel Marcel, Paris 1983, 9-137.


166 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

tale in quanto co-Essere nell’Amore. Approfondendo quest’ottica<br />

possiamo constatare che logos ed ethos fanno riconoscere bios<br />

come dono reciproco, co-essenziale, co-esistente e mai come cosa<br />

da possedere. Allora bios è: il valore fondamentale, l’ambito<br />

esistenziale e la condizione sine qua non d’essere e diventare<br />

persona; l’affermazione dell’unità di tutti gli esseri umani e dell’universalità<br />

dei diritti e della dignità della persona umana in<br />

ogni forma e tappa del suo sviluppo e della sua maturazione, di<br />

cui nessuno può privarla. “L’atto con cui io sopprimo la vita, per<br />

quanto motivato, implica la pretesa sacrilega di interrompere un<br />

ciclo o addirittura la volontà di porre ad esso un termine assoluto.<br />

Uccidere significa prima di tutto sopprimere, considerare<br />

suscettibile di distruzione ciò che forse è indistruttibile: è un atto<br />

oggettivamente sacrilego e sostanzialmente assurdo. In questo<br />

senso è facile accorgersi di quanto la speranza s’innesti nella<br />

vita, considerata non tanto nelle sue manifestazioni, quanto<br />

nella sua essenziale perennità” 77 . Infine, bios, riconosciuto e<br />

contemplato da logos, partecipato e confermato da ethos, fa riconoscere<br />

l’Essere-Dio-Creatore in quanto Principio-Fine della<br />

creazione. Il riconoscere tutte queste dimensioni trascendentali<br />

dell’essere-uomo-persona, nell’esperienza esistenziale di bios-logos-ethos,<br />

cioè nella unicità dinamica del proprio essere-più, in<br />

relazione creaturale con Dio e co-esistenziale verso Dio, interpersonale<br />

con gli altri e solidale con il mondo, garantisce la dignità<br />

della persona nel senso pieno.<br />

Conclusioni<br />

Chi sono io? Che senso ha la mia vita? Queste domande, in<br />

quanto questioni iniziali dell’indagine filosofica di Gabriel Marcel<br />

che sono state poste a se stesso ed all’uomo d’oggi, sono sempre<br />

gli stessi interrogativi concernenti le sue origini, la sua natura<br />

e il suo destino che l’uomo si è posto da molti secoli, fin dall’antichità<br />

greca 78 . Il suo problema esistenziale, che l’uomo pone<br />

77 ME, 328.<br />

78 UP, 9.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 167<br />

da sempre a se stesso ed ad altri, implicato costantemente nella<br />

situazione storica concreta e complessa, non si può risolvere rispondendo:<br />

“Tu sei un animale ragionevole” oppure “Tu sei rationalis<br />

naturae individua substantia”. Senza dubbio questo problema<br />

instaura una relazione tra l’uomo-in-situazione e l’uomo<br />

concreto che vorrebbe avere una risposta ad hoc per comprendere<br />

se stesso hic et nunc e dare un senso alla sua esistenza vissuta<br />

in prima persona. Dopo la sua analisi ontologico-antropologica<br />

ed ontologico-etica, Marcel – “un uomo autentico, un vero<br />

cristiano, un testimone della verità” 79 e filosofo della speranza<br />

80 – può rispondere a quest’uomo: “Tu sei l’unico nel mondo<br />

perché tu sei voluto-creato da Dio e tu hai la vita unica da percorrere<br />

e da compiere come persona, e, di più, tu non morrai<br />

quando tu ami qualcuno”. Ma il pensatore francese non si ferma<br />

nella sua indagine filosofica soltanto a questo livello individuale-esistenziale<br />

dell’uomo-quesito a se stesso, perché vorrebbe<br />

smascherare le radici di questo problema, formulando la sua<br />

questione così: “a quali condizioni l’uomo, nella sua pienezza, è<br />

diventato un quesito per l’uomo?” 81 In altre parole, Marcel vorrebbe<br />

approfondire il problema dell’alienazione dell’uomo contemporaneo,<br />

che sembra essere diventato sempre più estraneo a<br />

se stesso, fino a mettere in dubbio la sua esistenza e la sua essenza:<br />

“l’uomo della baracca”, l’uomo senza faccia e “l’immagine<br />

deformata e quasi irriconoscibile riflessa dallo specchio interiore”<br />

come la rende manifesta l’arte contemporanea 82 . Parlando<br />

d’alienazione dell’uomo, ci troviamo – secondo Marcel – di fronte<br />

alle “modalità esistenziali operanti al di qua della soglia della<br />

79 B. HÄRING, CSsR, Prefazione, in: M. Cozzoli, L’uomo in cammino verso,<br />

op. cit., 9.<br />

80 G. MARCEL, Structure de l’Espérance, Dieu vivant, 1951/19, 73-80; Dialogo<br />

sulla speranza (a cura di Enrico Piscione), Edizioni Logos, Roma 1984;<br />

ME, 314-329; M. BECQUÉ, CSsR, J. PRIEUR, R. TROISFONTAINES, SJ, (avec la collaboration<br />

de: Jean Guitton, L. Becqué, CSsR), Gabriel Marcel (1889-1973).<br />

Philosophe de l’Espérance, Editions Jules Hovine, Marquain (Belgique) 1990;<br />

S. PLOURDE, Gabriel Marcel. Philosophe et témoin de l’Espérance, op. cit., 129-<br />

226.<br />

81 UP, 9.<br />

82 UP, 10-11.


168 EDMUND KOWALSKI C.SS.R.<br />

coscienza quotidiana”: lo stato o la società, il nazionalismo nelle<br />

sue forme estreme del razzismo e del nazismo che fanno sparire<br />

l’uomo-persona nella massa della super-nazione, della classe<br />

inferiore oppure della collettività anonima; il capitalismo con<br />

il suo liberalismo industriale e il comunismo come sistema totalitario<br />

che lo riducono a robot, a numero e a strumento delle sue<br />

ideologie applicate. Paradossalmente, in fondo a queste modalità<br />

esistenziali che provocano e conducono il processo della riduzione-deformazione<br />

dell’uomo in quanto persona sta l’ansioso<br />

interrogativo di origine metafisica: ”l’uomo pare aver perduto<br />

ogni riferimento al divino: egli non si pone più davanti a un<br />

Dio del quale sarebbe creatura e immagine. La morte di Dio, nel<br />

preciso significato che Nietzsche ha dato a queste parole, non<br />

sarebbe all’origine del fatto che l’uomo è diventato per se stesso<br />

un quesito senza risposta?” 83 Ma, e questo sarebbe il secondo paradosso,<br />

Dio è stato ucciso dagli uomini – come del resto afferma<br />

Nietzsche stesso in Così parlò Zarathustra e in La gaia scienza<br />

– per il fatto di distaccare radicalmente l’uomo dall’atto del<br />

creare e riducendolo all’atto del produrre 84 . Per non cadere nello<br />

stesso errore dell’ardua ed acuta questione: uomo o Dio, dal<br />

quale il pensiero filosofico ha tentato per secoli di liberarsi, Marcel<br />

propone “la particolare modalità di relazione che mi unisce<br />

a Dio al quale mi riferisco in quanto uomo” 85 , l’incontro tra la libertà<br />

e la grazia, tra la conoscenza filosofica e la coscienza etica<br />

per possedere “il segreto di ciò che io sono e di ciò che sono atto<br />

a diventare” 86 . Di conseguenza, né il superuomo del passato<br />

né la società-scienza-tecnica d’oggi che si è sostituita all’io onnipotente<br />

ed onnipresente possono dar morte a Dio e poi all’uomo<br />

in quanto persona perché, dal momento in cui decidono di porre<br />

se stesso come assoluto, non possono che distruggersi, e, la<br />

“potenza” della verità e della libertà del suo co-Essere nell’Amore,<br />

confermata ed attualizzata nella coscienza morale personale<br />

non è nelle mani del potere di nessuno. L’uomo, in quanto pastore-creatore<br />

dell’essere e come “testimone di una realtà tra-<br />

83 UP, 22.<br />

84 UP, 54; cfr anche 22-32.<br />

85 UP, 50.<br />

86 UP, 61.


L’UOMO PASTORE DELL’ESSERE 169<br />

scendente”, nella comunione-agàpe con gli altri e con il mondo<br />

prolunga l’atto della creazione e della redenzione. “Ma ciò che<br />

dobbiamo ricordare – afferma Marcel in L’inquietudine nel mondo<br />

d’oggi – in nome di una più alta esigenza, è che qualsiasi progresso<br />

tecnico non può bastare a se stesso: esso degenera in un<br />

gioco ridicolo se si sgancia dalla proclamazione del regno della<br />

carità, garante – in condizioni del resto imperfettamente rappresentabili<br />

– dell’unità di tutti in tutti e della quale il concetto<br />

di ‘corpo mistico’, proprio della teologia cristiana, ci dà l’unica<br />

nozione suscettibile di colmarci, direi perfino di dissetarci” 87 . La<br />

vera risposta all’uomo che è problema a se stesso non sarebbe<br />

infatti la ratio-techné, ma innanzitutto la carità-agàpe vissuta nel<br />

quotidiano dalla persona che rivela: il senso del suo essere-piùuomo<br />

come essere-amore-persona, il senso della sua vita come<br />

dono da ricevere e da donare, ed, attraverso se stessa, la presenza<br />

di Dio nel mondo come l’Essere-Creatore-Amore. “C’è un atteggiamento<br />

singolare e proprio di Dio – afferma Ignazio Sanna<br />

in Dalla parte dell’uomo: la Chiesa e i valori umani – nei confronti<br />

dell’uomo: quello di perdonare, cioè di donarsi-per, di darsi, concedersi.<br />

E c’è un atteggiamento singolare e proprio dell’uomo<br />

nei confronti di Dio: quello di credere, cioè cor-dare, dare il cuore,<br />

donare qualcosa di se stessi, donare il proprio intimo, nella<br />

lode, nel ringraziamento, nell’accoglienza. L’uomo è un dono<br />

per essenza, e si realizza donandosi” 88 .<br />

—————<br />

EDMUND KOWALSKI CSSR<br />

The author is an invited professor at the Alphonsian Academy.<br />

El autor es profesor invitado en la Academia Alfonsiana.<br />

—————<br />

87 UP, 156-157.<br />

88 I. SANNA, Dalla parte dell’uomo: la Chiesa e i valori umani, Edizioni<br />

Paoline, Milano 1992, 271.


StMor 40 (2002) 171-204<br />

TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM:<br />

A METHODOLOGICAL COMPARISON<br />

ON THE USE OF TRADITION AS A SOURCE<br />

OF MORAL KNOWLEDGE<br />

Catholic ethical method continues to be a central topic of<br />

debate in fundamental moral theology in the post-Veritatis splendor<br />

era. This article is the third in a series of three articles comparing<br />

the two predominant ethical methods in Catholic moral<br />

theology: Revisionism and the Basic Goods Theory (BGT). 1<br />

Here, I will focus on tradition as a source of moral knowledge.<br />

There are two relevant senses in which tradition is used in this<br />

paper. Tradition with a capitol “T” depicts the infrastructure and<br />

process or system for handing over lived faith and tradition with<br />

a small “t” is the content of that lived faith that is handed over. 2<br />

1 See my “The Basic Goods Theory and Revisionism: A Methodological<br />

Comparison on the Use of Reason and Experience as Sources of Moral<br />

Knowledge,” Heythrop Journal 42 (2001) 423-50; and “The Basic Goods Theory<br />

and Revisionism: A Methodological Comparison on the Use of Scripture<br />

as a Source of Moral Knowledge,” Louvain Studies 26 (2001) 117-46.<br />

2 See P.C. RODGER and L. VISCHER, eds., The Fourth World Conference on<br />

Faith and Order: Montreal, 1963, Faith and Order Papers, No. 42 (London:<br />

SCM, 1964) nn. 38-63, 50-57 (cited in CHARLES E. CURRAN, The Catholic Moral<br />

Tradition Today: A Synthesis [Washington, DC: Georgtown University Press,<br />

1999] 59), 66-106. It should be noted that the distinction made in this document<br />

differs fundamentally from that posited within Catholic theological<br />

discourse. In that discourse, Tradition refers not simply to the process and<br />

structure but also to the content, whereas traditions refer to particular determinations<br />

of the tradition, which may be permanent in certain contexts,<br />

but are not necessarily enduringly normative. (See YVES CONGAR, Tradition<br />

and Traditions, MICHAEL NASEBY and THOMAS RAINBOROUGH [trans.] [New York:<br />

The Macmillan Company, 1967]). Even within this discourse, however, there<br />

is fluidity in interpreting these two terms. For instance, while the INTERNA-<br />

TIONAL THEOLOGICAL COMMISSION published a document entitled “The Interpretation<br />

of Dogmas,” and uses the terms Tradition and tradition throughout


172 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

A fundamental difference between revisionism and the BGT is<br />

on the role, function, and authority of Tradition and tradition in<br />

either ethical theory. For Tradition, the question of authority<br />

within the Church and the ecclesiologies that the view of authority<br />

reflects is central. For tradition, “the hermeneutic problem<br />

is to discern the difference between continuing a content<br />

that expresses divine revelation and a teaching that merely reflects<br />

the sociological and cultural circumstances of a particular<br />

time and place.” 3 Since the impact of Tradition and tradition on<br />

moral theology are extensive and warrant far greater treatment<br />

than I can do them justice in this paper, I must narrow my investigation<br />

of them as methodological sources to three central<br />

issues. First, I will investigate the nature of the relationship between<br />

theologians and the magisterium; second, the criteria for<br />

determining whether or not moral teachings belonging to the<br />

“secondary object of infallibility” have been taught infallibly;<br />

and third, intrinsically linked to this second issue, is which, if<br />

any, norms belong to the “secondary object of infallibility.” The<br />

first issue pertains to Tradition whereas the latter two issues pertain<br />

to tradition. The differences in ecclesiological models between<br />

the BGT and revisionism are key for understanding and<br />

responding to these issues. Consequently, before addressing<br />

them I will explore the ecclesiologies of both theories.<br />

Ecclesiology and Tradition<br />

The late RICHARD MCCORMICK, S.J., frequently pointed out<br />

that one’s understanding of the teaching authority on morality<br />

within the church is intimately linked with one’s ecclesiology, or<br />

understanding of the church. 4 The BGT recognizes the funda-<br />

the text, it provides no explanation of the terms (see “De interpretatione dogmatum,”<br />

Gregorianum 72 [1991] 5-37).<br />

3 CURRAN, The Catholic Moral Tradition Today, 53.<br />

4 See, for example, The Critical Calling: Reflections on Moral Dilemmas<br />

Since Vatican II (Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 1989) 19-<br />

21, 34-45, 54-55, 163-69; and, “Some Early Reactions to Veritatis Splendor,”<br />

in CURRAN and MCCORMICK, eds., Readings in Moral Theology No. 10: John<br />

Paul II and Moral Theology (New York: Paulist Press, 1998) 5-34, at 28-30.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 173<br />

mental importance of this relationship as well. 5 Ecclesiology is<br />

central to how one comprehends Tradition and the role and<br />

function of the magisterium in relation to the theologian and the<br />

faithful.<br />

Since Vatican II, theologians have generally adhered to two<br />

fundamentally different ecclesiological models. The model that<br />

originated in the Middle Ages and predominated up until Vatican<br />

II is the hierarchical model. According to this ecclesiological<br />

model, knowledge flows downward from the magisterium to<br />

theologians to the faithful. The role and function of theologians<br />

in this model is to explain and clarify to the faithful what the<br />

magisterium has taught authoritatively, but not to question or<br />

challenge those teachings. 6 While the sensus fidelium and their<br />

experiences are a source for informing the magisterium in its<br />

formulation of moral teachings, it is the magisterium’s responsibility<br />

to determine how that experience is to be interpreted and<br />

incorporated into its teaching. In cases where there is a disparity<br />

between human experience and magisterial teaching (e.g., artificial<br />

birth control), the magisterium holds the trump card. According<br />

to this model, then, the magisterium is the final authority<br />

for interpreting, formulating, and dispensing moral teachings.<br />

Theologians help to explain and disseminate those teachings<br />

to the faithful. They should not question or challenge authoritative,<br />

non-infallible teachings where the magisterium has<br />

deliberately stated an opinion about a controverted matter, even<br />

if their scholarship challenges it, but should defend and explain<br />

such teachings. If we think of this ecclesiological model as a<br />

pyramid, the magisterium is at the pinnacle of the pyramid and<br />

is the hermeneutical key for all other sources of moral knowledge.<br />

With Vatican II came a profound transition in ecclesiology<br />

and, by implication, moral epistemology. The <strong>propos</strong>ed concentric<br />

model is referred to as the people of God or communio<br />

(communion) model. 7 Within this model, knowledge is dis-<br />

5<br />

GRISEZ, Christian Moral Principles 831.<br />

6 This model is clearly reflected in PIUS XII’s Humani Generis (see, for<br />

example, DENZINGER, 2313-14).<br />

7<br />

MCCORMICK, Critical Calling 40. For a helpful study on communio as an<br />

ecclesiological model, see JEAN-MARIE ROGER TILLARD, O.P., Church of Church-


174 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

cerned through the people of God in its entirety – the magisterium,<br />

theologians, and the faithful alike. There is a “trialogue,” if<br />

you will, among the three groups guided by the Holy Spirit with<br />

Scripture and human experience at the very center of this conversation.<br />

It is this ongoing conversation that moves the pilgrim<br />

Church through history towards a fuller recognition, knowledge,<br />

understanding, and appreciation of God’s self-communication<br />

to humanity. While the magisterium still maintains authority in<br />

this model, and there is a presumption of truth regarding its<br />

teaching, this authority is qualified by its role as learner-teacher.<br />

The faithful and theologians facilitate, contribute to, and sometimes<br />

may even challenge noninfallible magisterial teachings in<br />

this learning-teaching process.<br />

The BGT espouses a hierarchical ecclesiology. GRISEZ and<br />

SHAW note, “God prescribes that there be a visible human community<br />

which is ‘the Church’ and that it be organized hierarchically<br />

rather than democratically or in some other way.” 8 Within<br />

such a model, hierarchical authority, and obedience and conformity<br />

to that authority, are key. While the BGT recognizes the importance<br />

of the contributions of both theologians and the faithful<br />

in this model, how does it explain their respective roles in relation<br />

to the magisterium? It is the task of theologians to aid the<br />

magisterium by eliciting “the testimony of witnesses of faith on<br />

matters about which the magisterium must judge” and to <strong>propos</strong>e<br />

“the material or conceptual content for possible judgments<br />

by which the faith will be freshly articulated and developed, or<br />

challenges to it answered.” In addition, “the faithful at large can<br />

<strong>propos</strong>e material from their experience.” 9 What happens if the<br />

experiences of the faithful conflict with the authoritative judgments<br />

of the magisterium? “A sound method in moral theology<br />

will not allow the moral experiences and judgments of some of<br />

es: The Ecclesiology of Communion, R.C. DE PEAUX (trans.) (Collegeville, MN:<br />

The Liturgical Press, 1992).<br />

8 GRISEZ and SHAW, Fulfillment in Christ: A Summary of Christian Moral<br />

Principles (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 1991) 130.<br />

9 GRISEZ, “How to Deal with Theological Dissent,” in CURRAN and MC-<br />

CORMICK, eds., Readings in Moral Theology No. 6: Dissent in the Church (New<br />

York: Paulist Press, 1988) 442-72, at 460-61.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 175<br />

the contemporary faithful to override the constant and very firm<br />

moral teaching of the Church.” 10 In this case, it is the role of the<br />

theologian to consult moral principles and the fundamental<br />

truths of faith “to find resources for explaining modern experience<br />

and criticizing dissenting opinions.” 11 What if theologians<br />

find grounds for legitimate dissent from noninfallible magisterial<br />

teachings based on the experiences of the faithful and/or their<br />

own research and scholarship? While rational argumentation<br />

can sometimes be convincing, it is susceptible to distorting the<br />

truth, according to the BGT. “No moral theory can settle any issue<br />

with complete certainty by experience and purely rational<br />

analysis.” 12 The only possibility for legitimate dissent from noninfallible<br />

moral norms is if a stronger authority is drawn from<br />

faith itself. Since it is the ultimate authority of the magisterium<br />

to interpret articles of faith, the hierarchical epistemological circle<br />

is complete. That is, the magisterium issues teachings on<br />

faith and morals, and theologians defend those teachings. If theologians<br />

are to have a legitimate basis to question noninfallible<br />

teachings, they must invoke a higher source drawn from faith itself<br />

“such as Scripture, a defined doctrine, or a teaching <strong>propos</strong>ed<br />

infallibly by the ordinary magisterium.” 13 The magisterium<br />

is responsible for interpreting and defining sources of faith.<br />

Given the constraints for legitimate dissent from noninfallible<br />

magisterial teaching, such dissent is very limited in this ecclesiological<br />

model.<br />

Contrarily, revisionism espouses a people of God or communion<br />

ecclesiological model. This model is based on Trinitarian<br />

theology in that, just as the Trinity is a relational entity, no<br />

10<br />

GRISEZ, Christian Moral Principles 10. We must note that the phrase<br />

“constant and very firm” implies infallible statements. If a moral teaching<br />

is infallibly taught, it is understood that neither theologians nor the experiences<br />

of the faithful could challenge such a teaching. A moral teaching’s<br />

infallibility, however, is precisely what is being debated between the two<br />

theories.<br />

11 Ibid. 10-11.<br />

12 Ibid. 853.<br />

13 Ibid. 854 (while this assertion is made in the context of the faithful’s<br />

response to noninfallible teachings, the point is reiterated in the context of<br />

Grisez’s discussion of radical theological dissent (871).


176 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

member superior to the other, so too, the three bodies which<br />

constitute the Church. 14 While this model does not deny the importance<br />

and authority of the magisterium as an authoritative<br />

witness to truth, it stands in relation to, not above, the other two<br />

bodies. The relationship between the magisterium, theologians<br />

and the people of God are communal and dialectical. It is communal<br />

in the sense that all the faithful share a common baptism<br />

that unites them in faith. On the basis of this faith, the faithful<br />

“cannot err in matters of belief.” 15 Given this communal unity,<br />

however, there remain different gifts and roles in discovering,<br />

articulating, and defining “matters of belief.” For the faithful, experience<br />

in their faith journey as this is lived out and manifested<br />

in community is key to determining what constitutes matters<br />

of belief. For moral theologians, it is reflection on that experience<br />

as well as upon revelation and reason that help to formulate<br />

and articulate matters of belief in a comprehensive ethical<br />

system. For the magisterium, it is discernment that both listens<br />

to the experiences of the faithful and is in thoughtful, honest,<br />

and respectful dialogue with theologians in the process of formulating<br />

matters of belief and to teach authoritatively. In all of<br />

these processes, the Holy Spirit is present to guide the entire<br />

church. Whenever there is a disagreement over noninfallible<br />

magisterial teachings, whether it be the faithful in relation to the<br />

magisterium, theologians in relation to the magisterium, or the<br />

magisterium in relation to the faithful and theologians, such disagreements<br />

must be thoroughly investigated to discern their<br />

source, their validity, and if and how it challenges those teachings.<br />

Mere disagreement does not constitute an argument<br />

against noninfallible teachings. What it does warrant is a serious<br />

investigation that can seek to clarify, correct, or in extreme cases<br />

change those teachings on the basis of responsible dialogue.<br />

The only teachings that are beyond correction and change are<br />

infallible teachings.<br />

Both of these ecclesiological models are evident in the early<br />

14 See RICHARD R. GAILLARDETZ, Teaching with Authority: A Theology of the<br />

Magisterium of the Church (Collegeville, MN: Liturgical Press, 1997) 241-52.<br />

15 Lumen Gentium par. 12.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 177<br />

history of the Church and can be defended through recourse to<br />

the documents of Vatican II. Historically, FRANCIS SULLIVAN notes<br />

that whereas the roots of the infallibility of ecumenical councils<br />

and pope date back to the ninth and thirteenth centuries respectively,<br />

“the conviction that the consensus of the universal<br />

church in its faith is an infallible norm of truth goes back to the<br />

second century, with Irenaeus, and is a consistent element of<br />

Christian belief.” 16 GRISEZ challenges this revisionist perspective<br />

on history and authority within the Church. Instead, he defends<br />

the kind of teaching authority the hierarchy claims for itself in<br />

Lumen Gentium 25 and Dei Verbum 10 as stemming back to Jesus’<br />

authorizing the apostles to teach with authority. He writes,<br />

“the fact that supreme teaching authority, however exercised and<br />

articulated, is vested in the pope and bishops as successors of the<br />

apostles goes back to the origin of the Church herself.” 17 Furthermore,<br />

support for both models can be deduced from Vatican<br />

II’s documents, especially Lumen Gentium, depending on one’s<br />

interpretive lens. In fact, there is a dialectic between the ecclesiological<br />

model one espouses, the documents of Vatican II, and<br />

the hermeneutical lens one develops in order to interpret those<br />

documents. Revisionism interprets those documents as expressing<br />

ecclesiological innovations that departed significantly from<br />

the ecclesiology developed in the Middle Ages, and that continued<br />

up until Vatican II. AVERY DULLES refers to this perspective as<br />

a “hermeneutics of discontinuity.” 18 The BGT would opt for a<br />

hermeneutics of continuity whereby Vatican II merely reaffirmed<br />

the traditional hierarchical ecclesiology. 19<br />

16<br />

SULLIVAN, Creative Fidelity 97; and, Magisterium: Teaching Authority in<br />

the Catholic Church (New York: Paulist Press, 1983) 84-99.<br />

17<br />

GRISEZ, Christian Moral Principles 882-83 (emphasis added).<br />

18<br />

AVERY DULLES, S.J., “A Half Century of Ecclesiology,” TS 50 (1989) 419-<br />

42, at 430-31.<br />

19<br />

GRISEZ critiques DULLES’revisionist ecclesiology (Christian Moral Principles<br />

894-97). In so doing, he posits that this ecclesiology is untenable because<br />

it posits a view of revelation and faith that are inconsistent with<br />

Church teaching (481-85). His critique, however, is both an oversimplification<br />

of DULLES’ position and utilizes the very tools of a hierarchical ecclesiology<br />

that are being debated.


178 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

As I understand the debate over the hierarchy and its teaching<br />

authority, the important question is not if the bishops and<br />

pope have this teaching authority, but how the teaching authority<br />

is to be exercised. That is the very point of debate on the historical<br />

investigation of ecclesiological models. Whereas the BGT<br />

has a very limited role for the faithful and theologians in their<br />

hierarchical model, revisionism’s people of God model allows<br />

for much greater input from both groups in developing, formulating,<br />

and reformulating noninfallible teachings. This model is<br />

particularly relevant for the contemporary Church, given that<br />

many of the faithful are educated and have a very active ministry<br />

within Church institutions (e.g., universities and parishes). Furthermore,<br />

with the radical decline of vocations to the priesthood<br />

and religious life in the contemporary church, the Church herself<br />

is moving more towards a “Church of the Laity” whereby the<br />

laity have a much greater role to play in every aspect of Church<br />

life. For revisionism, the re-positioning of authority based on a<br />

revised, yet traditional, ecclesiology reflects not only a Trinitarian<br />

theology and the documents of Vatican II but also Catholic<br />

social teaching and the principle of subsidiarity or participation<br />

that applies to social and ecclesial structures. 20 The implications<br />

of these sources for the authority of the magisterium and its relationship<br />

to theologians and the faithful supports a communion<br />

ecclesiological model which is more reflective of the “signs of<br />

the times” than is the antiquated exclusively hierarchical model.<br />

In light of these two different ecclesiological models, we can<br />

now address three central issues concerning the teaching authority<br />

of the magisterium on morality and its role and function within<br />

ethical theory that divide the BGT and revisionism. The first issue<br />

is the proper relationship between theologians and the magisterium<br />

when the magisterium exercises its teaching function.<br />

20 PIUS XI, Quadragesimo anno par. 79. See JOSEPH A. KOMONCHAK, “Subsidiarity<br />

in the Church: The State of the Question,” The Jurist 48 (1988) 298-<br />

349; and JOHN R. QUINN, “The Exercise of the Primacy and the Costly Call to<br />

Unity,” in PHYLLIS ZAGANO and TERRENCE W. TILLEY, eds., The Exercise of the<br />

Primacy: Continuing the Dialogue (New York: Crossroad Publishing Co.,<br />

1998) 1-28, at 21-24.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 179<br />

Relationship between Theologians and the Magisterium<br />

The BGT and the Juridical Model<br />

At the heart of the current “crisis of faith in the Church” 21 according<br />

to GRISEZ, is the “cancer” of dissenting theologians. 22<br />

This state of affairs is due, in large part, to an improper relationship<br />

between the magisterium (pope and bishops) and theologians<br />

in the magisterial process. To heal this cancer, GRISEZ<br />

<strong>propos</strong>es a juridical or high court model for this relationship<br />

that follows from a hierarchical ecclesiological model. 23 There<br />

are three features to this “high court” model. “The pope and other<br />

bishops should first listen together to theological debate, then<br />

dismiss the theologians and engage in their own reflection.” 24 In<br />

this way, the role and function of theologians in relation to the<br />

magisterium becomes clear. Just as the arguments of the advocates<br />

representing each side of a case settle nothing, so too, this<br />

model “would make clear to everyone the quite limited and relative<br />

value of all theological arguments.” 25 The act of evaluating<br />

and judging those arguments is reserved for the magisterium ‘in<br />

chambers.’ Second, “theologians and others invited to make<br />

their appropriate contributions to the theological debate should<br />

be instructed clearly regarding what is expected of them.” 26 In<br />

the case of disputed theological viewpoints, “both sides should<br />

be given equal and adequate opportunities to present their cases.”<br />

27 Finally, “to assure collegial solidarity in magisterial judgments,<br />

those which concern disputed questions ordinarily<br />

should be made in a collegial manner as the outcome of such a<br />

process.” 28<br />

21 GRISEZ, “How to Deal with Theological Dissent” 443.<br />

22 Ibid. 456.<br />

23 Ibid. 465.<br />

24 Ibid.<br />

25 Ibid.<br />

26 Ibid.<br />

27 Ibid.<br />

28 Ibid.


180 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

GRISEZ’S “high court” analogy does not end with the magisterial<br />

process of judgment but reflects what may be considered<br />

a punitive component for dissenting theologians as well. GRISEZ<br />

belittles the 1985 assembly of the SYNOD OF BISHOPS’ call for “reciprocal<br />

dialogue between the bishops and theologians…for the<br />

building up of the faith and its deeper comprehension” 29 given<br />

the current state of “radical dissent” within the Catholic Church.<br />

Instead, he <strong>propos</strong>es the remedies of the first assembly of the<br />

SYNOD in 1967. “Those who are rash or imprudent should be<br />

warned in all charity; those who are pertinacious should be removed<br />

from office.” 30<br />

This juridical model is based on certain premises. First, the<br />

magisterium “should respect” the scholarly authority of theologians.<br />

31 Second, rational arguments do not carry doctrinal<br />

weight. 32 Third, the special sacramental power of popes and bishops,<br />

through grace, gives them supernatural access to truth. 33<br />

Fourth, while recognizing that the magisterium can err in authoritative,<br />

noninfallible teachings, these teachings ought to be<br />

followed because “even when it is not clear that the bishop’s or<br />

pope’s teaching is <strong>propos</strong>ed infallibly, one has a good reason for<br />

assuming that his teaching pertains to divine revelation.” 34<br />

Fifth, the juridical model is based on a hierarchical ecclesiology<br />

represented, for example, in Humani Generis and Lumen<br />

Gentium 25. There is a curious tension here between the BGT reliance<br />

upon Humani Generis to defend the proper relationship<br />

between the magisterium and theologians and GRISEZ’S critique<br />

of this relationship prior to Vatican II. As he notes, “before Vatican<br />

II, too much conformity was demanded of Catholic theologians.<br />

Their work was so closely integrated with the magisteri-<br />

29<br />

SYNOD OF BISHOPS, “A Message to the People of God,” Origins 15/27 (December<br />

19, 1985) 441-50, at 447-48. Cited in GRISEZ, “How to Deal with Theological<br />

Dissent” 443.<br />

30 Cited in ibid. 444. See also, JOHN KIPPLEY, Fellowship of Catholic Scholars<br />

Newsletter 8 (September 1985) 9 (cited in MCCORMICK, Critical Calling 25).<br />

31<br />

GRISEZ, “How to Deal with Theological Dissent” 460.<br />

32<br />

GRISEZ, Christian Moral Principles 853, 856.<br />

33 Ibid. chapt. 35.<br />

34 Ibid. 852 (emphasis omitted).


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 181<br />

um’s work that there was virtually no room for them to <strong>propos</strong>e<br />

views which the magisterium could not at once accept and approve.”<br />

35 Revisionism would certainly agree with this statement.<br />

Furthermore, revisionism would posit the statements of Humani<br />

Generis used by GRISEZ to defend his juridical model as both a reflection<br />

and confirmation of this unhealthy relationship.<br />

Finally, material for debate in this model presumes issues<br />

open to discussion. The reliance upon, and authority granted to,<br />

PIUS XII’s Humani Generis substantially limits this material. PIUS<br />

XII declares, “but if the Supreme Pontiffs in their acts, after due<br />

consideration, express an opinion on a hitherto controversial<br />

matter, it is clear to all that this matter, according to the mind<br />

and will of the same Pontiffs, cannot any longer be considered a<br />

question of free discussion among the theologians.” 36 This statement<br />

applies to noninfallible pronouncements and is sometimes<br />

expressed in the Latin aphorism, Roma locuta, causa finita. As<br />

we shall see below, this last premise is intimately linked to the<br />

debate over what belongs to the secondary object of infallibility.<br />

Revisionism and the Dialogical Model<br />

Revisionism qualifies or rejects these premises, rejecting also<br />

the BGT’s high court or juridical model. Instead, revisionism<br />

posits a dialogical model for the relationship between theologians<br />

and the magisterium. Revisionism’s response to the BGT’s<br />

premises focuses first on the term “respect.” “Respect” should entail<br />

not only allowing theologians to present their arguments, but<br />

also the magisterium’s seriously and accurately considering the<br />

content and meaning of those arguments without an inherent<br />

bias in favor of those theologians who merely support a traditional,<br />

non-infallible, position. As it stands, and as Veritatis Splendor’s<br />

misrepresentation of proportionalism made evident, 37 there<br />

35<br />

GRISEZ, “How to Deal with Theological Dissent” 456-57.<br />

36<br />

DENZINGER, 2313.<br />

37 See, for example, JOSEPH SELLING and JAN JANS (eds.), The Splendour of<br />

Accuracy: An Examination of the Assertions made by Veritatis Splendor<br />

(Kampen, Netherlands: Kok Pharos Publishing House, 1994); and a number<br />

of articles written by revisionist moral theologians in The Tablet 247 (1993)<br />

published shortly after the encyclical.


182 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

is a magisterial presupposition against revisionism that makes<br />

such respect and unbiased appraisal of arguments problematic<br />

in the current situation. Second, given that rational arguments<br />

are not a sufficient criterion for determining and formulating authoritative,<br />

noninfallible teaching, they are certainly a necessary<br />

criterion. When there are sound reasons and arguments for challenging<br />

what may, by definition, be an erroneous teaching, those<br />

arguments should be given due consideration. How those arguments<br />

relate to, and utilize, other sources of moral knowledge<br />

must be analyzed and discussed in their entirety.<br />

Third, given the accessibility to the truths of natural law<br />

through right reason, revisionism would qualify the BGT’s epistemological<br />

claim concerning the relationship between knowledge<br />

and grace. Certainly God’s grace, as promised to the<br />

Church and in a special way to the magisterium, facilitates the<br />

process in the discernment of truth, but it does not dispense the<br />

Church from the very human tasks of gathering information and<br />

evaluating that information. 38 It is in this process that the development<br />

of moral doctrine takes place as history has shown. 39<br />

Fourth, revisionism would accuse the BGT of advocating a<br />

certain “creeping infallibility,” to use the words of CHARLES CUR-<br />

RAN, 40 regarding the faithful’s response to noninfallible but authoritative<br />

judgments. In the view of some revisionists, GRISEZ<br />

calls for greater respect and authority to be given to such judgments<br />

than is warranted by their status. GRISEZ writes, “when a<br />

faithful Catholic’s best judgment is formed, as it should be, by<br />

the Church’s noninfallible teaching, the Catholic might possibly<br />

be following a false norm. Yet God has provided no better norm<br />

for his or her current belief and practice.” 41 To give such judgments<br />

this authority in cases where there are strong contrary arguments<br />

is to both deny the role and function of the primacy of<br />

38 See MCCORMICK, Notes on Moral Theology: 1965 through 1980 (Washington,<br />

DC: University Press of America, 1981) 262-66.<br />

39 See JOHN T. NOONAN, “Development in Moral Doctrine,” TS 54 (1993)<br />

662-77.<br />

40<br />

CURRAN, Catholic Moral Tradition Today 226.<br />

41<br />

GRISEZ, Christian Moral Principles 884.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 183<br />

conscience 42 and to ignore history. First, Christian tradition has<br />

consistently defended the authority of conscience in moral matters.<br />

AQUINAS writes regarding the application of knowledge to<br />

action, “conscience is said to bind by force of the divine precept.”<br />

43 That is, as long as one acts according to one’s well<br />

formed and informed conscience, even in the case of invincible<br />

ignorance and an erroneous judgment of conscience, that conscience<br />

maintains its dignity. 44 While it certainly is the case that<br />

one who informs one’s conscience according to the noninfallible<br />

authoritative teachings of the magisterium is not morally culpable<br />

if this teaching is erroneous, it does not follow that, given serious<br />

reasons that conflict with the claims of those teachings,<br />

one who acts against them is morally culpable. Revisionists argue<br />

that while there is always a strong presumption of truth in<br />

favor of magisterial teaching, if there are serious reasons for<br />

questioning that teaching, one can indeed knowingly and willingly<br />

act against such a teaching on the authority of conscience.<br />

One only need look at the history of the Church to see that, especially<br />

in questions of morals, the magisterium has erred on<br />

noninfallible judgments, even grievously. 45 POPE JOHN PAUL II’s recent<br />

acknowledgement of the sins of the sons of the Church<br />

would seen to attest to this fact. 46 If individual Christians err, including<br />

those acting in a magisterial capacity, it is proof not of<br />

the limits of the Holy Spirit but of the limits of human beings to<br />

respond faithfully to the Spirit. All human beings, including<br />

members of the magisterium, are subject to sin and its impact<br />

on the discernment of truth. And while the Church as a whole<br />

42 Code of Canon Law c. 752 and the commentary 548.<br />

43<br />

AQUINAS, De Veritate, q. 17, a. 3. See JOHN MAHONEY, The Making of<br />

Moral Theology: A Study of the Roman Catholic Tradition (Oxford: Clarendon<br />

Press, 1987) 192.<br />

44<br />

POPE JOHN PAUL II, Veritatis Splendor par. 62; and The Universal Catechism<br />

of the Catholic Church (Rome: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1994) par.<br />

1793.<br />

45<br />

NOONAN, “Development in Moral Doctrine”.<br />

46<br />

JOHN PAUL II, “Jubilee Characteristic: The Purification of Memory,”<br />

Origins 29/40 (March 23, 2000) 648-50. See also, INTERNATIONAL THEOLOGICAL<br />

COMMISSION, “Memory and Reconciliation: The Church and Faults of the<br />

Past,” Origins 29/39 (March 16, 2000) 626-44.


184 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

cannot err in matters of belief, 47 discerning the implications of<br />

that belief for moral teaching is an ongoing process. The Church<br />

has erred in moral matters in the past. However, the Church as<br />

a pilgrim Church in the process of becoming provides hope that<br />

error will not persist in the long term.<br />

Fifth, revisionism would contrast the ecclesiology developed<br />

by the BGT and their reliance upon Humani Generis and Lumen<br />

Gentium 25, with that developed elsewhere in Lumen Gentium<br />

and other Vatican II documents. For example, Gaudium et Spes<br />

reflects a communion ecclesiology:<br />

With the help of the Holy Spirit, it is the task of the entire People<br />

of God, especially pastors and theologians, to hear, distinguish,<br />

and interpret the many voices of our age, and to judge them in the<br />

light of the divine Word. In this way, revealed truth can always be<br />

more deeply penetrated, better understood, and set forth to greater<br />

advantage. 48<br />

One might ask how such ecclesiological models at variance<br />

with one another could evolve from the same Council? Not only<br />

does the hermeneutical lens determine one’s interpretation of these<br />

documents, but also, as MCCORMICK notes, “it is a known and acknowledged<br />

fact that the documents of Vatican II contain perspectives<br />

and statements that are ill at ease with each other.” 49 In revisionism’s<br />

ecclesiology, legitimate and respectful dissent is a part of<br />

the dialogical model between theologians and the magisterium. It<br />

is not a cancer to be eliminated but a service to the Church in her<br />

ongoing journey to discern how we respond to complex moral<br />

questions through an ongoing reflection on Revelation.<br />

Finally, while the BGT would strictly limit those issues that<br />

are open to discussion between theologians and the magisterium,<br />

revisionism would maintain that all noninfallible magisterial<br />

pronouncements are open to scholarly investigation.<br />

The revisionist dialogical model is based on the two components<br />

of dialogue itself, listening and speaking. For theologians,<br />

47 Lumen Gentium par. 12.<br />

48 Gaudium et Spes par. 44.<br />

49 MCCORMICK, Critical Calling 103.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 185<br />

the listening pole entails several dimensions. First, as Catholic<br />

theologians, they must listen to the magisterium and its authoritative<br />

teaching as the Holy Spirit guides it. This is so because<br />

the magisterium is not just another source or authority for theologians.<br />

It is a religious authority. As such, it is to be trusted because<br />

Christ has promised that he will not abandon his Church<br />

to error. 50 Those who are in positions of authority within the<br />

Church have been promised the guidance of the Holy Spirit, and<br />

this fundamental truth does not allow the theologian to view the<br />

authority of the magisterium as an equal, much less a competing<br />

authority, among others. Second, theologians must listen to<br />

the Holy Spirit guiding them in their own spiritual journey. This<br />

journey includes all dimensions of their lives, including scholarship.<br />

There is a scholarly pneumatology within the theological<br />

discipline. (Indeed, I would see the call to be a theologian as a<br />

vocation, just as the call to be a priest, married, or celibate is a<br />

vocation. One is not limited to a single vocation in life.) Third,<br />

theologians must listen to their own scholarship and research,<br />

including all the sources of moral knowledge, and must try to<br />

discern the truth in community in light of that scholarship. In<br />

light of these three components, theologians must speak. Dissent<br />

is not the purpose of the listening process, but can certainly<br />

be a component of this process when there are serious reasons<br />

for questioning noninfallible magisterial teachings. Revisionist<br />

theologians, in fact, dissent on a very narrow range of ethical issues.<br />

Their dissent, however, has attracted a disproportionate<br />

amount of attention. In other words, the issues on which there<br />

is dissent are rather miniscule in comparison to the agreement<br />

between theologians and the magisterium. For its part, the magisterium,<br />

both bishops and pope, must engage in much of the<br />

same processes of listening, as do theologians. Granted that the<br />

magisterium is promised the guidance of the Holy Spirit, as are<br />

the faithful as a whole, the Holy Spirit can only do so much. The<br />

work of the Holy Spirit produces its effects through finite and<br />

50 See JOSEPH KOMONCHAK, “Authority and Magisterium,” in WILLIAM W.<br />

MAY, ed., Vatican Authority and American Catholic Dissent: The Curran Case<br />

and its Consequences (New York: Crossroad, 1987) 103-14, at 110-11.


186 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

sinful human beings, who, as history has shown, can fail to cooperate.<br />

Because of human finitude and sin, this cooperation is<br />

not always present, either for theologians or the magisterium.<br />

Given the profound role of the magisterium to teach authoritatively<br />

within the Church, it has a greater burden, and thus a<br />

greater responsibility, in learning and searching out truth in light<br />

of “the signs of the times.” Part of this learning and searching entails<br />

not only the magisterium’s own listening in the form of discernment,<br />

research, scholarship, and prayer, but also dialoging<br />

with theologians in order to aid the magisterium in this process.<br />

Thus, while maintaining a central position in the learning-teaching<br />

process, the magisterium cannot dispense with the process.<br />

“Universal Consensus,” Theologians and the Magisterium<br />

The different ecclesiological models and models of the relationship<br />

between the magisterium and theologians lead to two<br />

fundamentally different hermeneutics of Church documents on<br />

the criteria for determining whether or not a pronouncement of<br />

the ordinary universal magisterium is infallible, the second issue<br />

to be addressed between the BGT and revisionism. Similar to<br />

the investigation of Scripture and its methodological function in<br />

ethical theory, 51 the selection of Church documents, and their interpretation<br />

and application, both shape and reflect one’s theory<br />

as well. While a detailed investigation of these texts would take<br />

us beyond the scope of this work, I will focus on a paragraph<br />

from Lumen Gentium used by both the BGT and revisionism.<br />

Based on different interpretations of this text each theory derives<br />

very different conclusions on its implications for tradition<br />

as a source of moral knowledge.<br />

Lumen Gentium 25 states the following with regard to the<br />

51 WILLIAM C. SPOHN, What Are They Saying about Scripture and Ethics?<br />

(New York: Paulist Press, 1995 rev. ed.) 13-20; and “Morality on the Way to<br />

Discipleship: The Use of Scripture in Veritatis Splendor,” in MICHAEL E. ALL-<br />

SOPP and JOHN J. O’KEEFE, eds., Veritatis Splendor: American Responses<br />

(Kansas City, MO: Sheed & Ward, 1995) 83-105, at 87-89.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 187<br />

infallibility of the ordinary universal magisterium:<br />

Although the individual bishops do not enjoy the prerogative<br />

of infallibility, they can nevertheless proclaim Christ’s doctrine infallibly.<br />

This is so, even when they are dispersed around the world,<br />

provided that while maintaining the bond of unity among themselves<br />

and with Peter’s successor, and while teaching authentically<br />

on a matter of faith or morals, they concur in a single viewpoint as<br />

the one which must be held conclusively. 52<br />

GERMAIN GRISEZ and FRANCIS A. SULLIVAN have extensively debated<br />

the numerous conditions laid out for declaring a teaching<br />

of the ordinary universal magisterium infallible, especially with<br />

regard to the magisterium’s teaching on artificial birth control. 53<br />

A particularly contentious point of debate between these two<br />

scholars on this paragraph from Lumen Gentium concerns the<br />

criteria for determining whether or not a judgment has been<br />

<strong>propos</strong>ed conclusively or definitively and is thus infallible. One<br />

way of determining whether or not this is the case is explained<br />

in the 1983 Code of Canon Law, namely, that such a teaching has<br />

been infallibly defined must be “clearly established.” There must<br />

be “universal consensus” on this teaching. 54 What are the episte-<br />

52 Lumen Gentium par. 25.<br />

53 The following literature traces the genesis and development of this debate.<br />

It begins with a paper published by GRISEZ and JOHN C. FORD, S.J., on<br />

the infallibility of the Church’s teaching on artificial birth control: “Contraception<br />

and the Infallibility of the Ordinary Magisterium,” TS 39 (1978) 258-<br />

312, and continues with the following works: FRANCIS A. SULLIVAN, Magisterium;<br />

GRISEZ, “Infallibility and Specific Moral Norms: A Review Discussion,”<br />

Thomist 49 (1985) 248-87; SULLIVAN, “The ‘Secondary Object’ of Infallibility,”<br />

TS 54 (1993) 536-50; GRISEZ, “Quaestio Disputata: The Ordinary Magisterium’s<br />

Infallibility: A Reply to Some New Arguments,” TS 55 (1994) 720-32,<br />

737-38; SULLIVAN, “Reply to Germain Grisez,” TS 55 (1994) 732-37; and SUL-<br />

LIVAN, Creative Fidelity 105-06.<br />

54 Both GRISEZ and SULLIVAN recognize that canon 749.3 applies to “defined<br />

doctrines.” However, based on theological reasons, Sullivan would expand<br />

the requirement of “clearly established” to doctrines “infallibly taught<br />

by the ordinary universal magisterium” (“‘Secondary Object’” 549; and<br />

GRISEZ, “The Ordinary Magisterium’s Infallibility” 730-31).


188 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

mological criteria for determining such a consensus? Whose<br />

“universal consensus” is required? Is it a universal consensus of<br />

bishops, theologians, the faithful, or solely a “firm and consistent”<br />

teaching of the papacy? How important is theological consensus<br />

in determining whether or not an infallible statement has<br />

been issued by the ordinary universal magisterium? Given the<br />

importance of such a statement, it would seem that there would<br />

be no doubt, especially among theologians and bishops, regarding<br />

the status of such a teaching. In his final point in one of their<br />

exchanges, GRISEZ asserts,<br />

for theologians, lack of consensus for a position is no argument<br />

against it, and an alleged consensus for a position is a bad argument<br />

in its favor…. Methodologically…this at best provides an<br />

unreliable sign of where the truth might lie. And logically, it provides<br />

no justification for participating in the alleged consensus; invoked<br />

as a response to a reasoned theological argument, it is fallacious.<br />

55<br />

In his reply to GRISEZ on this particular exchange between<br />

the two, SULLIVAN deems it important enough to their overall dialogue<br />

to focus on “the significance of the fact that there is no<br />

evidence of a consensus among Catholic theologians” on the infallibility<br />

of the teaching by the ordinary universal magisterium<br />

prohibiting the use of artificial contraception. 56 Given this lack<br />

of consensus for the FORD-GRISEZ thesis on the infallible teaching<br />

on artificial birth control developed in an earlier article, 57 SULLI-<br />

VAN maintains that “it can hardly be ‘clearly established’ that the<br />

official doctrine on artificial contraception has been infallibly<br />

taught….” Consequently, “it does not qualify as irreformable<br />

teaching.” 58 The “consensus of Catholic theologians” is a basic<br />

consideration of SULLIVAN’S response to GRISEZ for determining<br />

55<br />

GRISEZ, “The Ordinary Magisterium’s Infallibility” 732.<br />

56<br />

SULLIVAN, “Reply to Germain Grisez” 732.<br />

57 “Contraception and the Infallibility of the Ordinary Magisterium”<br />

258-312.<br />

58<br />

SULLIVAN, “Reply to Germain Grisez” 733.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 189<br />

whether or not this (or one may presume any) doctrine has been<br />

infallibly taught by the ordinary universal magisterium. To support<br />

his argument, SULLIVAN cites PIUS IX’s letter Tuas Libenter<br />

and a more recent statement by the International Theological<br />

Commission, On the Interpretation of Dogma. 59 Whereas GRISEZ<br />

“belittles the importance of such a [theological] consensus,” 60<br />

according to SULLIVAN, both of these documents highlight its importance.<br />

With regard to the former document, SULLIVAN concludes:<br />

Given the connection that Pius IX saw between the fact that a<br />

doctrine was being taught by the ordinary universal magisterium,<br />

and the presence of a constant and universal consensus among<br />

Catholic theologians upholding that same doctrine, it follows that<br />

in the absence of such a consensus among Catholic theologians, it<br />

would be difficult to maintain that a doctrine had been taught by<br />

the ordinary universal magisterium as definitively to be held. But<br />

this is precisely what Grisez wishes to maintain. 61<br />

While GRISEZ acknowledges, “Sullivan has drawn from Tuas<br />

Libenter a theological argument for the importance of the consensus<br />

of Catholic theologians,” it is authentic, and not alleged<br />

consensus that fulfills its stipulations. 62 One might pose the following<br />

question to GRISEZ: what constitutes the difference between<br />

these two types of consensus? Why does the pre-1962 consensus<br />

of bishops and theologians that he and FORD cite in favor<br />

of the infallibility of the norm prohibiting the use of artificial<br />

birth control represent an authentic consensus, 63 and therefore<br />

a legitimate component to “help gauge the ‘weight of this uniform<br />

teaching,’” 64 whereas any subsequent lack of consensus<br />

59 See Origins 20/1 (17 May 1990) 7.<br />

60<br />

SULLIVAN, “Reply to Germain Grisez” 735.<br />

61 Ibid. 736-37.<br />

62<br />

GRISEZ, “The Ordinary Magisterium’s Infallibility” 738. See also, Living<br />

a Christian Life 263-64.<br />

63<br />

FORD and GRISEZ, “Contraception and the Infallibility of the Ordinary<br />

Magisterium” 278-80.<br />

64<br />

GRISEZ, “The Ordinary Magisterium’s Infallibility” 737.


190 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

among both bishops and theologians 65 that challenges their conclusions<br />

is not an authentic lack of consensus that should also<br />

help in analyzing its authority? GRISEZ maintains that, given the<br />

state of theology today where “some contemporary theologians<br />

deny infallibility altogether, and quite a few deny that it can extend<br />

to specific moral norms,” as well as the fact that “neither<br />

uninterrupted Christian tradition nor repeated and forceful papal<br />

reaffirmations of a traditional teaching impress those who<br />

deny it…the absence of theological consensus about the status<br />

of moral teachings no longer has the significance it would have<br />

had in 1863.” 66 In addition, radical dissenting theologians have<br />

influenced bishops as well, 67 thereby lessening even the bishops’<br />

credibility in contributing to “authentic consensus.” 68 GRISEZ attributes<br />

this state of the theological discipline, as well as what he<br />

regards a crisis in the Church, to a radical dissent that gained a<br />

foothold at Vatican II and has spread like a cancer within the<br />

Church. In order to correct these ills and establish “authentic<br />

consensus” among Catholic theologians, the BGT would establish<br />

a right relationship between the magisterium and theologians.<br />

This right relationship consists of the juridical model presented<br />

above.<br />

What are we to say concerning this exchange between<br />

GRISEZ and SULLIVAN on “universal consensus” between theologians<br />

(and bishops) as a consideration for determining whether<br />

or not a doctrine has been infallibly taught by the ordinary universal<br />

magisterium? First, GRISEZ’S statement that, methodologically,<br />

consensus or the lack thereof is an “unreliable sign of<br />

where the truth might lie” is true, but requires qualification.<br />

Lack of consensus is unreliable in that it may not indicate pre-<br />

65 GRISEZ explicitly admits this lack of consensus on the issue of artificial<br />

birth control: “For, in view of the silence up to now of virtually all the<br />

bishops on the teaching’s infallibility, as well as the absence of the consensus<br />

among theologians who have dealt with the issue, most of the faithful who<br />

lack theological training will be unable to see that this teaching has been<br />

<strong>propos</strong>ed infallibly” (ibid. 732).<br />

66 Ibid. 738.<br />

67 GRISEZ, “How to Deal with Theological Dissent” 454 and 464.<br />

68 GRISEZ, “The Ordinary Magisterium’s Infallibility” 732.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 191<br />

cisely where the truth might lie, but it can certainly indicate<br />

where the truth does not lie. Perhaps it is an indication that we<br />

need to search out truth elsewhere in light of the sources of<br />

moral knowledge in the historical, cultural context in which we<br />

live. Second, to my knowledge, and as SULLIVAN’S own response<br />

to GRISEZ makes clear, no one uses the argument of consensus,<br />

in se, “as a response to a reasoned theological argument.” That<br />

is, no theologian would, or has, responded to GRISEZ’S argument<br />

that, in spite of your reasoned argument for artificial birth control<br />

as an infallible norm, the lack of consensus of theologians<br />

on the status of this teaching invalidates your argument. The<br />

lack of consensus is not merely a numbers game; it is reflective<br />

of the strengths or weaknesses of the arguments <strong>propos</strong>ed behind<br />

consensus or lack thereof. Therefore, revisionism would<br />

agree with GRISEZ that consensus, in itself, proves nothing.<br />

Third, and more to the point, SULLIVAN’S and GRISEZ’S exchange<br />

on the role and function of theological consensus as a<br />

consideration for determining whether or not the ordinary universal<br />

magisterium has issued an infallible statement seems to<br />

be given too much importance in their exchanges. It seems that<br />

this would be a crucial consideration to the question of infallible<br />

pronouncements by the ordinary universal magisterium only<br />

if universal consensus were a necessary condition for an infallible<br />

teaching, or somehow constitutive of it. While such theological<br />

consensus is certainly not essential for this determination,<br />

however, the connection between a lack of theological consensus<br />

and a teaching can be enlightening on two accounts.<br />

First, the arguments <strong>propos</strong>ed by theologians that challenge a<br />

particular magisterial teaching may, through an ongoing dialogue<br />

between theologians and the magisterium, indicate that<br />

the teaching needs to be explored, refined, clarified, or in extreme<br />

cases, abandoned. Second, the role and function of theological<br />

consensus in one’s ethical method indicates how one perceives<br />

the relationship between theologians and the magisterium<br />

and indicates, more basically, the ecclesiology of a particular<br />

ethical method. As indicated above, the arguments and reflections<br />

<strong>propos</strong>ed by many revisionist theologians based on the<br />

four sources of moral knowledge, which is at the heart of the<br />

lack of theological consensus on the teaching on artificial birth<br />

control, have not been adequately responded to by the magis-


192 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

terium. Rather, the response has been an authoritative reaffirmation<br />

of a traditional teaching. It is clear that what is at the<br />

heart of the debate over theological consensus and infallible<br />

teachings by the ordinary universal magisterium is as much (if<br />

not more) about authority, its exercise, role, and function in the<br />

current magisterium, as about the theological arguments for or<br />

against a particular ethical issue.<br />

GRISEZ’S identification of the lack of consensus amongst<br />

bishops with the influence of radically dissenting theologians<br />

that rules out authentic consensus, and his interpretation that<br />

radical dissent reflects a cancer in the church, represents a serious<br />

statement on how the Holy Spirit works within the Church.<br />

One could reasonably assert that GRISEZ’S position on authentic<br />

and alleged consensus is intimately tied to a very narrow, papal<br />

ecclesiology. That is, it is not the college of bishops who are<br />

God’s voice on earth, but only those bishops who conform to papal<br />

statements unconditionally. Such an ecclesiology virtually<br />

rules out authentic pluralism within the Church. Not only do<br />

GRISEZ and SULLIVAN differ on the criteria for establishing “universal<br />

consensus,” but the BGT and revisionism also disagree<br />

fundamentally on the proper object of the ordinary universal<br />

magisterium’s infallible teachings.<br />

Tradition and Ethical Method: the secondary object of<br />

infallibility?<br />

Both the BGT and revisionism agree that if a natural law<br />

norm is also contained in divine revelation, then that norm falls<br />

under the auspices of the primary object of infallibility. They further<br />

agree that any infallible teaching of the magisterium belonging<br />

to the primary object of infallibility requires an assent of<br />

“divine and Catholic faith.” A point of contention concerns those<br />

norms that belong to the secondary object of infallibility, i.e.,<br />

truths not contained in divine revelation, but which are required<br />

for revelation’s explanation and defense. The BGT maintains<br />

that the ordinary magisterium has taught infallibly such specific<br />

natural law norms; revisionism denies this claim. In this section,<br />

I will present two fundamental differences between the theories<br />

that draw from tradition yet support contradictory posi-


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 193<br />

tions on this issue: First, the distinction between two types of<br />

moral truths; second, the distinction between the first principles<br />

of the natural law and the secondary precepts that are derived<br />

from them.<br />

A fundamental question that divides revisionism and the<br />

BGT is whether or not specific natural law norms have been, or<br />

even can be, taught infallibly by the ordinary universal magisterium.<br />

In other words, are such norms (e.g., forbidding contraception)<br />

necessary to safeguard and defend the deposit of faith<br />

or revelation? The question is about the appropriate object of<br />

such infallible teachings. According to the BGT, the teaching<br />

prohibiting artificial birth control, for example, “is at least connected<br />

with [revelation] as a truth required to guard the deposit<br />

as inviolable and to expound it with fidelity.” 69 In this sense, the<br />

norm forbidding artificial birth control and similar norms are<br />

“truths of salvation,” i.e., they are moral truths in which the<br />

charism of the magisterium, through the guidance of the Holy<br />

Spirit, is equipped to teach infallibly. JOSEF FUCHS, S.J., responds<br />

to moral theologians (among them could be included GRISEZ and<br />

FORD) who have attempted to argue that such norms are “truths<br />

of salvation;” in so doing, he distinguishes between two types of<br />

moral truths. 70 According to FUCHS, moral truths can be divided<br />

into those that relate to moral goodness and moral rightness;<br />

these two categories of moral truths distinguish the magisterium’s<br />

teaching charism and the nature of its competence. Moral<br />

goodness pertains to the person as such and his or her character,<br />

motive, disposition, etc. Fundamentally, it asks whether or<br />

not the person is open and committed to God’s self-giving love.<br />

It is the vertical dimension of the person that relates to the person’s<br />

salvation. Moral goodness, however, is always realized in<br />

the world of other persons. This is the horizontal dimension of<br />

the person and is designated by moral rightness. Moral rightness<br />

is concerned with the kind of activity that facilitates human<br />

well-being. Strictly speaking, the adjective “moral” pertains to<br />

69<br />

GRISEZ and FORD, “Contraception and the Infallibility of the Ordinary<br />

Magisterium” 287.<br />

70 “Moral Truths – Truths of Salvation?” in Christian Ethics in a Secular<br />

Arena (Washington, DC: Georgetown University Press, 1984) 48-67.


194 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

goodness alone. It is used with rightness only in an analogous<br />

sense. That is, “‘moral’ in its proper and formal sense refers only<br />

to persons and their free attitudes and decisions, but, because<br />

personal moral goodness contains concern for the well-being of<br />

the human world as its moral task, it urges ‘right’ activity within<br />

this world; and only because of this relationship between personal<br />

goodness and material rightness, this rightness is also<br />

called moral rightness.” 71 Truths of salvation pertain to moral<br />

goodness whereas material norms indicate right or wrong behavior.<br />

According to FUCHS and other revisionist theologians, 72<br />

only the former can be considered as the proper object of the<br />

secondary object of infallibility and are within the infallible<br />

competence of the magisterium to teach.<br />

To defend this assertion FUCHS has recourse to Scripture, tradition,<br />

and magisterial documents. The upshot of his argument<br />

is three-fold. First, these sources reveal that, whereas the magisterium<br />

can teach infallibly on questions of natural law that are<br />

revealed, it has not taught infallibly on non-revealed questions<br />

of natural law (e.g., contraception). Second, there is agreement<br />

among theologians that the competence of the magisterium to<br />

guide the Church community is promised by the Holy Spirit.<br />

There is disagreement, however, on the nature of this competence<br />

and how it applies to questions of right/wrongness and<br />

material norms. MCCORMICK, for example, notes “one can be<br />

competent without being infallibly competent.” In comparison<br />

to pre-Vatican II magisterial teachings, MCCORMICK demonstrates<br />

that the documents of Vatican II and many subsequent<br />

magisterial teachings have clearly limited the nature of the<br />

magisterium’s competence to judge in the area of<br />

rightness/wrongness. 73 Finally, FUCHS and other revisionists<br />

71 Ibid. 52. See also, JAMES F. KEENAN, S.J., who has written extensively<br />

on the goodness/rightness distinction in moral theology: Goodness and<br />

Rightness in Thomas Aquinas’s Summa Theologiae (Washington, D.C.:<br />

Georgetown University Press, 1992); “Distinguishing Charity as Goodness<br />

and Prudence as Rightness: A Key to Thomas’s Secunda Pars,” Thomist 56<br />

(1992) 389-411; and “What is Good and What is Right? A New Distinction<br />

in Moral Theology,” Church 5 (1989) 22-28.<br />

72 SULLIVAN, “Secondary Object”, n. 60; MCCORMICK, Critical Calling 98-99.<br />

73 See MCCORMICK, Critical Calling 96-100, 147-62.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 195<br />

would classify norms such as those prohibiting contraception,<br />

masturbation, reproductive technologies, etc., as moral truths<br />

that pertain to material norms of rightness and wrongness, not<br />

truths of salvation that pertain to moral goodness. As such, they<br />

cannot be considered as the proper object of infallible teaching.<br />

One of the texts that FUCHS and many other revisionists cite<br />

to justify their argument against the plausibility of teaching nonrevealed<br />

infallible natural law norms is Gaudium et Spes, paragraph<br />

33: “The Church guards the heritage of God’s Word and<br />

draws from it religious and moral principles, without always<br />

having at hand the solution to particular problems.” 74 Religious<br />

and moral principles relate to truths of salvation and moral<br />

goodness, whereas solutions to particular problems relate to<br />

material norms and rightness/wrongness. The BGT gives two responses<br />

to revisionism’s use of this and similar texts to argue its<br />

position. In his response to revisionists who make “some play”<br />

with this and similar texts to deny that absolute specific moral<br />

norms exist, JOHN FINNIS asserts that revisionists have committed<br />

a non sequitur by overlooking the distinction between “not<br />

every” and “not any.” In doing so, they move from “‘The church<br />

cannot give a specific answer to every moral question’ to ‘The<br />

church cannot teach with definitive authority any specific moral<br />

norm.’” 75 In his references, he cites SULLIVAN, FUCHS, and GERARD<br />

HUGHES, S.J., as theologians who have repeatedly committed this<br />

non sequitur. According to FINNIS, then, revisionists have taken<br />

great liberty in their hermeneutic of passages from Vatican II to<br />

deny that some specific moral norms have been taught infallibly<br />

by the magisterium.<br />

GRISEZ has another response to revisionism. In his response,<br />

he cites a passage from Gaudium et Spes that substantiates that<br />

there are some specific moral norms whose truth precludes substantial<br />

revision: “Contemplating this melancholy state of humanity,<br />

the Council wishes to recall first of all the permanent<br />

binding force of universal natural law and its all-embracing<br />

74 WALTER M. ABBOTT, S.J., Documents of Vatican II (New York: America<br />

Press, 1966) 232 (emphasis added), see also, n. 90.<br />

75 FINNIS, Moral Absolutes 92.


196 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

principles. Man’s conscience itself gives ever more emphatic<br />

voice to these principles.” 76<br />

In response to GRISEZ’S point, revisionism has recourse to<br />

AQUINAS’ Summa Theologiae. RICHARD MCCORMICK and JOHN MA-<br />

HONEY note that AQUINAS distinguishes between the first principles<br />

of natural law and secondary precepts or certain detailed<br />

proximate conclusions that flow from those principles. 77 Whereas<br />

the first principles of natural law cannot change and are,<br />

therefore, absolute, the characteristics of the secondary precepts<br />

or application of the first principles are, in the words of MC-<br />

CORMICK, “provisionality, flexibility and contingency.” 78 In contemporary<br />

theological terminology, we could say that these secondary<br />

precepts are material norms that relate to rightness and<br />

wrongness and are subject to change, clarification, and evolution<br />

in light of their ongoing dialogue with the signs of the times<br />

(e.g., history, culture, and tradition).<br />

The BGT recognizes AQUINAS’ distinction between principles<br />

and their application as well. It further recognizes that revisionism<br />

cites this article from AQUINAS “to support their view that one<br />

must decide in each case whether a received moral norm must<br />

be fulfilled or is overridden by other considerations.” 79 In response<br />

to revisionism’s use of AQUINAS, GRISEZ notes the following.<br />

First, while it may be the case that AQUINAS’ statement may<br />

be true “with respect to most specific norms,” he does teach,<br />

“that there are norms that do not admit of exception.” 80 Second,<br />

he posits that THOMAS’ assertion, drawn from ARISTOTLE’S physics<br />

distinguishing between what is universal and absolute versus<br />

what is contingent and changing, is fallacious. It is based on a<br />

misperception of the existential, moral domain and the natural<br />

world.<br />

76 Documents 292, par. 79. See GRISEZ, “Infallibility and Specific Moral<br />

Norms” 274.<br />

77<br />

AQUINAS, S.T., I-II, q. 94, aa. 4-5. MCCORMICK, Critical Calling 150-51;<br />

and JOHN MAHONEY, Making of Moral Theology 189-90.<br />

78<br />

MCCORMICK, Critical Calling 151.<br />

79<br />

GRISEZ, Christian Moral Principles 268.<br />

80 Ibid. 269.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 197<br />

The whole morally significant content of one’s action must be<br />

intelligible, since one is responsible only for what one understands.<br />

For this reason, <strong>propos</strong>als one adopts by choice never are morally<br />

particularized by unique, unrepeatable, material, contingent factors.<br />

The really unique aspects of one’s action make no difference<br />

whatsoever to the morality of what one does. 81<br />

FINNIS also acknowledges revisionism’s use of this passage<br />

from AQUINAS. He asserts that revisionism makes “much play”<br />

with this statement to show “that derived moral norms, since<br />

they involve contingent particulars, hold not universally but only<br />

generally (ut in pluribus), subject to exceptions (ut in paucioribus).”<br />

82 FINNIS points out, however, that while many positive<br />

norms admit of exceptions, there are negative absolute norms<br />

that apply “always and everywhere without exceptions.” 83<br />

What can be said of this seemingly interminable debate between<br />

revisionism and the BGT and their conflicting interpretation<br />

of tradition as to whether or not the ordinary magisterium<br />

has taught infallibly specific natural law norms that belong to<br />

the secondary object of infallibility? There are at least three<br />

methodological differences that shape each school’s hermeneutical<br />

lens for interpreting tradition. The first entails what each<br />

school considers to be the moral realm. In their responses to revisionists,<br />

neither GRISEZ nor FINNIS (who specifically cites FUCHS’<br />

article, which we discussed earlier) consider the distinction of<br />

moral truths, i.e., goodness and truths of salvation or rightness<br />

and the fulfillment of human well-being. The distinction between<br />

these terms and the norms that correspond to each reflect<br />

a more foundational view of the moral realm itself.<br />

Many revisionists evaluate the rightness or wrongness of an<br />

act in terms of the human person adequately considered and<br />

how the act impacts its dimensions, aside from the subjective<br />

motivation or moral goodness of the agent choosing the act. 84<br />

81 Ibid. (emphasis added).<br />

82<br />

FINNIS, Moral Absolutes 90.<br />

83 Ibid. 91. See also, GRISEZ, Christian Moral Principles 269.<br />

84 See LOUIS JANSSENS, “Artificial Insemination: Ethical Considerations,”<br />

Louvain Studies 8 (1980) 3-29.


198 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

The relationship between the act and its impact on those dimensions<br />

defines objective morality for revisionism. So, for example,<br />

whereas giving alms for the sake of vainglory is morally<br />

blameworthy (bad), what of the impact of that act on the poor?<br />

Revisionism would say that the act is right, but the motive and<br />

act defined in terms of the motive, is morally bad. The BGT,<br />

however, does not view the moral realm in these terms. For the<br />

BGT, “moral acts are objectively constituted by what people<br />

think they are doing. Subjective morality is in the possibility of a<br />

person’s confusion and/or error about the moral goodness or<br />

badness of his or her act, and in the possibility that a person’s<br />

freedom to choose is blocked or impeded.” 85 In the case of almsgiving,<br />

then, the BGT would say that the act is morally bad since<br />

the agent thinks that he is doing the act to gain praise rather<br />

than to relieve the suffering of the poor. The BGT does not have<br />

the ethical tools to evaluate the impact of the act, in se, on human<br />

well-being detached from the subjective goodness/badness<br />

of the moral agent. So, for example, regardless of whether or not<br />

a person actually performs an act, intention itself is morally decisive<br />

in the BGT’s understanding of objective morality. A person<br />

who thinks about murdering another person is a murderer, regardless<br />

of whether or not he commits the act of murder. 86 Objective<br />

morality, then, resides within the willing subject, regardless<br />

of the impact of carrying out one’s intentions in actions and<br />

their impact on human well-being. The BGT, however, is not entirely<br />

consistent in its claim. For instance, if a couple thinks that<br />

they are practicing responsible parenthood by using artificial<br />

birth control, why would this not determine the objective morality<br />

of their act? While the BGT posits a moral order where there<br />

is an intrinsic relationship between certain acts (e.g., artificial<br />

birth control) and the will choosing the act (a contraceptive<br />

85<br />

GRISEZ and BOYLE, “Response to Our Critics and Our Collaborators”<br />

231.<br />

86 See for example, GRISEZ and JOSEPH BOYLE JR., Life and Death With Liberty<br />

and Justice (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press) 393. See<br />

EDWARD VACEK’S response to this assertion (“Contraception Again – A Conclusion<br />

in Search of Convincing Arguments: One Proportionalist’s [Mis?]Understanding<br />

of a Text,” in Natural Law and Moral Inquiry 50-81, at 52-53.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 199<br />

will), revisionism would deny this moral order and, consequently,<br />

this intrinsic relationship. It is on the basis of this moral order<br />

that the BGT posits specific natural law norms that belong<br />

to the secondary object of infallibility that have been taught by<br />

the ordinary universal magisterium. Though GRISEZ and BOYLE<br />

claim that they are confident that their position on the objective/subjective<br />

distinction, as well as other distinctions, “consistently<br />

develop[s] Catholic tradition,” 87 their assertion is certainly<br />

debatable. 88<br />

The second methodological difference is in how each theory<br />

defines and classifies a norm. Determining whether or not a specific<br />

natural law norm has been taught infallibly by the ordinary<br />

universal magisterium depends, in large part, on this definition.<br />

89 Many revisionists recognize three types of moral norms,<br />

material, formal, and synthetic. Material norms are premoral,<br />

non-absolute norms that indicate certain premoral disvalues (or<br />

values) that tend to have a negative (or positive) impact on human<br />

well-being, and pertain to rightness and wrongness. Formal<br />

norms are moral, absolute norms that indicate a morally good<br />

or bad character, motive, or disposition and pertain to moral<br />

goodness (i.e., truths of salvation) or badness. Synthetic norms<br />

are moral absolutes that describe an act (killing) the motive<br />

(malevolence) and circumstances (unjustified) such as do not<br />

murder.<br />

The BGT recognizes revisionism’s distinction between various<br />

types of norms (material and formal), but <strong>propos</strong>es another<br />

type of specific moral norm. “The description of the act goes beyond<br />

mere behavior [material norm], yet does not go so far as to<br />

build in the moral determinant [formal or synthetic norm].”<br />

Such norms can be absolute norms if they are “formulated with<br />

respect to the moral act, which includes the wrongful choice.” 90<br />

87<br />

GRISEZ and BOYLE, “Response to Our Critics and Our Collaborators”<br />

231.<br />

88 See for example, MAHONEY, Making of Moral Theology ch. 5.<br />

89 See my “The Basic Goods Theory and Revisionism: A Methodological<br />

Comparison on the Use of Reason and Experience as Sources of Moral<br />

Knowledge.”<br />

90<br />

GRISEZ, Christian Moral Principles 257.


200 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

Therefore, any choice of an act prohibited by the norm would<br />

necessarily be morally bad. Since a specific norm entails a presumption<br />

about the nature of the will that chooses an act proscribed<br />

by the norm, there can be absolute specific natural law<br />

norms. Such norms would be the proper object for the magisterium’s<br />

teaching on the primary (part of revelation) or secondary<br />

(truths closely associated with revelation) object of infallibility.<br />

Revisionists, however, refer to such norms as synthetic<br />

norms. For example, whereas murder and lying are always<br />

morally bad, killing and falsehoods are not always such, precisely<br />

because the former include a description of a disordered<br />

will whereas the latter do not.<br />

For revisionism, the possibility of evolution, change, and development<br />

– in a word, historical consciousness – within the human<br />

experience, rules out, by definition, material natural law<br />

norms that could be taught infallibly by the magisterium. A necessary<br />

prerequisite for infallibility is that a teaching is irreformable,<br />

that is, “the formulation [of an infallible teaching]<br />

can be improved, but the meaning must be retained.” 91 According<br />

to SULLIVAN, however, “we can never exclude the possibility<br />

that future experience, hitherto unimagined, might put a moral<br />

problem into a new frame of reference which would call for a revision<br />

of a norm that, when formulated, could not have taken<br />

such new experience into account.” 92 In response, GRISEZ cites<br />

genocide as a specific moral norm that is an absolute and, therefore,<br />

could be considered the subject of an infallible judgment<br />

by the magisterium. 93 No future experience could put genocide<br />

into a new frame of reference that would transform the norm<br />

prohibiting genocide from an absolute to a non-absolute norm.<br />

As noted above, however, the point of contention here would not<br />

be on whether or not genocide is an absolute norm, but on the<br />

nature of the norm being debated. Revisionism denies the existence<br />

of absolute material norms, not absolute synthetic norms<br />

that include both a description of the act and the moral nature<br />

91 SULLIVAN, “‘Secondary Object’” 546.<br />

92 SULLIVAN, Magisterium 152.<br />

93 See GRISEZ, “Infallibility and Specific Moral Norms” 274.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 201<br />

of the will choosing the act. Genocide, like murder, by definition<br />

contains its very moral condemnation in the term itself. Both<br />

schools would agree that the norm prohibiting genocide is a<br />

moral absolute, yet they would disagree on the appropriate actdescriptions<br />

in other specific moral norms.<br />

In GRISEZ’S quotation cited above on AQUINAS’ use of ARISTO-<br />

TLE, there is some ambiguity in how we are to interpret GRISEZ’S<br />

final sentence. What does GRISEZ mean when he writes: “The really<br />

unique aspects of one’s action make no difference whatsoever<br />

to the morality of what one does”? This question reveals the<br />

third methodological distinction between the BGT and revisionism.<br />

While both schools agree that certain actions are always<br />

wrong (e.g., murder, theft, or adultery), they disagree fundamentally<br />

on the morally relevant circumstances that can determine<br />

whether or not an individual situation corresponds to the<br />

act defined and prohibited by a norm. 94 Much of this debate centers<br />

on the definition of the object and the traditional sources of<br />

morality. 95 Why is it that the unique aspect that a person is becoming<br />

intoxicated in lieu of an anesthetic in preparation for a<br />

painful operation is morally significant to the description of the<br />

act and the application of the norm prohibiting the act (“one<br />

should not drink oneself into a stupor”) 96 whereas the fact that a<br />

married couple is using a condom to prevent the spread of an<br />

STD is not an aspect that justifies redefining the act and the<br />

norm prohibiting that act? 97 Is that not precisely what AQUINAS<br />

94 AQUINAS, S.T., I-II, q. 100, a. 8, ad 3. See MCCORMICK, Critical Calling<br />

150; MAHONEY, Making of Moral Theology 190; and GRISEZ, Christian Moral<br />

Principles 268-69.<br />

95 See BRUNO SCHÜLLER, S.J., “Die Quellen der Moralität: Zur systematischen<br />

Ortung eines alten Lehrstücks der Moraltheologie,” Theologie und<br />

Philosophie 59 (1984) 535-559; JOSEPH SELLING, “Veritatis Splendor and the<br />

Sources of Morality,” Louvain Studies 19 (1994) 3-17; “The Fundamental Polarity<br />

of Moral Discourse,” in TODD SALZMAN, ed., Method and Catholic Moral<br />

Theology: The Ongoing Reconstruction (Omaha, NE: Creighton University<br />

Press, 1999) 21-43, at 26-37; and my Deontology and Teleology: An Investigation<br />

of the Normative Debate in Roman Catholic Moral Theology (Leuven:<br />

Peeters Press, 1995) 267-503.<br />

96 GRISEZ, Christian Moral Principles 258.<br />

97 GRISEZ, Difficult Moral Questions 160; and WILLIAM E. MAY, “AIDS,


202 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

means in asserting that, while general principles hold, their specific<br />

application varies according to the unique context or circumstances?<br />

Certainly revisionism would agree that unique aspects<br />

make no difference to morality if those aspects are not<br />

morally significant. However, GRISEZ does not provide a clear definition<br />

for what he considers to be the “unique aspects of one’s<br />

actions” or criteria for determining whether or not they affect<br />

the morality of what one does. For if it is the case that “one’s<br />

morally significant act will include only what one deliberately<br />

chooses to do and permit – that is, what one understands about<br />

what one is doing – and one’s practical understanding can be<br />

wholly determined by moral principles,” 98 what purpose do specific<br />

norms play? In addition, does not this open the door to<br />

rampant subjectivism and voluntarism that the BGT clearly rejects?<br />

For the BGT, it seems that dispensing from some (but not<br />

all) of the “unique aspects of one’s action” is essential to posit<br />

certain specific norms as absolutes and, therefore, as the appropriate<br />

object of the secondary object of infallibility taught by the<br />

ordinary magisterium.<br />

Conclusion<br />

Some have claimed that the methodological debate between<br />

the BGT and revisionism is interminable due, in large part, to a<br />

“theoretical gulf” between the principles and methods of each<br />

theory. 99 An investigation into the methodological differences<br />

between these two theories tends to support this claim. Not only<br />

is it clear that the BGT and revisionism have very unique understandings<br />

of Tradition and tradition as sources of moral<br />

knowledge that shape their ethical theories, but also the other<br />

Marriage and Condoms,” Ethics and Medics 13 (September 1988) 3-4. For revisionist<br />

perspectives on this issue, see JAMES F. KEENAN, ed., Catholic Ethicists<br />

on HIV/AIDS Prevention (Maryknoll, N.Y.: Orbis, 2001).<br />

98 GRISEZ, Christian Moral Principles 269.<br />

99 See for example, GRISEZ and BOYLE, “Response to Our Critics and Our<br />

Collaborators” 229. One must note too, however, that fundamental theological<br />

and ideological differences divide these two theories and shape their respective<br />

methods.


THE BASIC GOODS THEORY AND REVISIONISM 203<br />

sources of moral knowledge (reason, experience, and Scripture)<br />

and the hermeneutic of those sources impact their perception of<br />

Tradition and tradition as well. Methodology is a dialectical<br />

process of creating a synthetic whole out of the various sources<br />

of moral knowledge. As a theological ethic, the BGT has a clear<br />

hierarchy of the sources of moral knowledge. Tradition, specifically<br />

the magisterium as the teaching authority in the Church on<br />

faith and morals, is at the pinnacle of this hierarchy and functions<br />

as a hermeneutical lens for its interpretation of revelation<br />

and human experience. For revisionism, while recognizing the<br />

preeminence of the magisterium as a source of moral knowledge,<br />

it must be evaluated in its teaching capacity on moral issues<br />

in light of all the other sources of moral knowledge. The<br />

theological justification for revisionism’s perspective lies in Tradition<br />

and the fundamental shift in ecclesiology at Vatican II<br />

from a hierarchical model to a communio model.<br />

Throughout the history of Christianity, polarity has been an<br />

essential dimension of Catholic moral discourse. 101 It is necessary<br />

to recognize the polarity in ethical discourse and the<br />

methodological sources that are at the root of it in order to open<br />

up possible lines of discourse for discovering common ground<br />

between the two theories. While this paper has attempted to<br />

shed light on the former issue, the prospects for discovering<br />

common ground between the two theories requires further investigation.<br />

102<br />

TODD A. SALZMANN<br />

100 See RAPHAEL GALLAGHER on his discussion of polarity in moral theology<br />

since Vatican II (“Change and Continuity in the Human Condition: The<br />

Implications of GS paras. 4-10 for Moral Theology,” <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> 35 (1997)<br />

49-69, at 63-66).<br />

101 I would like to thank my colleague at Creighton University, DR. JULIA<br />

FLEMING and DR. ROBERT J. CAIN and MRS. BARBARA CAIN, as well as the anonymous<br />

reader from <strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> for their comments and suggestions in reviewing<br />

this manuscript. I am also indebted to the Summer Faculty Development<br />

Grant provided by Creighton University Graduate School for its generous<br />

financial support to facilitate the completion of this article.


204 TODD A. SALZMAN<br />

—————<br />

Todd A. Salzman is Associate professor in the Department of<br />

Theology at Creighton University, Ohama, Nebraska, USA.<br />

Todd A. Salzman es professor asociado en el departmento de theología<br />

de la Universidad Creighton, Ohama, Nebraska, USA.<br />

—————


StMor 40 (2002) 205-236<br />

JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

PHILOSOPHY IN THE ONGOING RENEWAL<br />

OF MORAL THEOLOGY:<br />

DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED<br />

Introduction<br />

In the wake of Pope John Paul II’s encyclical, Fides et ratio, 1<br />

the relationship between philosophy and theology has moved to<br />

the forefront of discussion – a discussion which likewise sheds<br />

light on the contribution of philosophy to the ongoing renewal<br />

of moral theology.<br />

Indeed, the Holy Father calls for a revitalized relationship<br />

between philosophy and theology in which philosophy will once<br />

again assist theology in discovering the proper place of faith in<br />

understanding our very existence. It is necessary to recover the<br />

fundamental understanding that at the heart of life and faith<br />

there is an “encounter, unique in kind,” by which, “God chose to<br />

reveal Himself,” and make His will known to us, so that,<br />

“through Christ, the Word made flesh, man has access to the Father<br />

in the Holy Spirit and comes to share in the divine nature.” 2<br />

This is the defining reality for the human person, originating<br />

completely in God’s gratuitous goodness, “moving from God to<br />

men and women in order to bring them to salvation. As the<br />

source of love, God desires to make himself known; and the<br />

knowledge which the human being has of God perfects all that<br />

the human mind can know of the meaning of life.” 3<br />

It was for this reason that Jesus came into the world: to live<br />

among men and women, speaking in a human way the very<br />

words of God, the intimate desire of God to bring all people to<br />

1 JOHN PAUL II, Fides et ratio: On the Relationship between Faith and Reason<br />

(Vatican City: Libreria Editrice Vaticana, 1998) (hereafter FR).<br />

2 FR, 7, citing Dei Verbum, 2.<br />

3 FR, 7.


206 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

salvation. 4 Such knowledge is not contrary to reason, yet it is beyond<br />

the grasp of reason alone. It is this encounter or “dialogue”<br />

between God and man that even philosophically grounds human<br />

existence and meaning.<br />

Philosophy will assist fundamental theology in demonstrating<br />

that while faith, as a gift from God, is not based on reason,<br />

faith nonetheless finds expression through reason. At the same<br />

time, reason on its own has limitations: “it becomes apparent<br />

that reason needs to be reinforced by faith, in order to discover<br />

horizons it cannot reach on its own.” 5<br />

Likewise, moral theology may have, “an even greater need of<br />

philosophy’s contribution,” 6 for Christian life in the Spirit requires<br />

the use of reason and the exercise of conscience for the<br />

application of both general and specific teachings and precepts<br />

to the concrete situations of life. For this reason, “moral theology<br />

requires a sound philosophical vision of human nature and<br />

society, as well as of the general principles of ethical decisionmaking,”<br />

7 if it will assist the believer to grow in this freedom and<br />

responsibility.<br />

What is needed is a philosophy that is authentic and autonomous<br />

in its own proper method, yet does not prescind from<br />

or exclude the significance of faith. However, much of the philosophy<br />

of recent centuries stands in stark contrast to the biblical<br />

sense of the human person as founded in relationship with<br />

God and the community. Specifically, there has been such a radical<br />

shift in philosophy toward the autonomous subject, that the<br />

way to understanding the “things above,” the transcendent,<br />

seems at times to be closed.<br />

Yet, for the brief period from World War I through World<br />

War II, a philosophical thread emerged which spoke to some of<br />

these issues: dialogical personalism. The failure or limits of sci-<br />

4 FR, 11.<br />

5 FR, 67, citing JOHN PAUL II, Letter to Participants in the International<br />

Congress of Fundamental Theology on the 125th Anniversary of “Dei Filius”<br />

(30 September 1995), 4: L’Osservatore Romano, 3 October 1995, 8.<br />

6 FR, 68.<br />

7 FR, 68.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 207<br />

ence experienced in the horrors of the First War provided the<br />

immediate backdrop for this dialogical philosophy to emerge, as<br />

a reaction to the universal doubt of Cartesian thought and to<br />

German Idealism, which knows the idea or representation but<br />

not the reality of “things-in-themselves.” Consequently, modern<br />

man and woman are left with a great inward focus on thought,<br />

reason and idea, but little sense of relationship with God and<br />

neighbor as foundational for the human person.<br />

However, in light of the tremendous evils experienced in<br />

World War II, the dialogical personalism of the interwar years<br />

was eclipsed, on the one hand, by existentialist philosophies that<br />

tended in many cases towards nihilism and despair, and on the<br />

other hand by analytic philosophies which took up narrower<br />

questions such as the limits and functions of language and logic.<br />

Because such philosophies either prescind from faith, are<br />

neutral or even dismissive of faith, philosophy after World War<br />

II once again offered little avenue for dialogue with theology.<br />

This article will not take up the relative merits of any of<br />

these philosophies, but rather, will simply revisit the dialogical<br />

philosophy of the interwar years. Dialogical philosophy will not<br />

of itself meet every need of a modern dialogue between philosophy<br />

and theology, but its recovery will offer several fruitful avenues<br />

of discussion and reflection for theology in general, as<br />

well as for moral theology in particular.<br />

A brief overview of dialogical philosophy, focusing on the<br />

thought of Franz Rozensweig and Martin Buber, two key figures,<br />

will precede a more detailed treatment of the work of Ferdinand<br />

Ebner. Although little known, especially among English language<br />

readers, Ebner’s thought is seminal and, as the only Roman<br />

Catholic of the group, his frame of reference provides some<br />

specific orientation for our topic. Finally, some implications and<br />

avenues for dialogue and reflection will be drawn from Ebner’s<br />

work as helpful in the dialogue between faith and reason, philosophy<br />

and theology, to which the Holy Father invites us.<br />

Over the last century or more, philosophers of various<br />

stripes have examined the issue of the isolated autonomous subject<br />

in the world of ideas. Pragmatists, such as C. S. Peirce,<br />

William James and John Dewey, each examined the close link<br />

between thinking and doing. “Analytical” philosophers – from<br />

Bertrand Russell, to the Vienna Circle, to Ludwig Wittgenstein –


208 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

examined the complex of problems surrounding the imprecise<br />

use of language (opening the way to critical theory, structuralism<br />

and semiotics). In the attempt to step back from experience<br />

in order to understand it, the phenomenology of Edmund<br />

Husserl and others is an influence and a bridge to the existentialist<br />

philosophies that were to come. Meanwhile, such varied<br />

thinkers as Wilhelm Dilthey, Martin Heidegger, Hans-Georg<br />

Gadamer, Gabriel Marcel and Paul Ricoeur take up diverse<br />

hermeneutical issues of interpretation and their relationship to<br />

human historicity.<br />

These diverse contemporary philosophies offer a backdrop<br />

against which to situate the work of the “dialogical philosophers,”<br />

who viewed dialogue in authentic relationship as constitutive<br />

of the human person.<br />

The Dialogical Philosophers<br />

While earlier thinkers such as Blaise Pascal, Ludwig Feuerbach,<br />

Søren Kierkegaard and Max Scheler had all struggled with<br />

the turn to the subject and its implications for the reality of the<br />

“I” and the “other,” and their place in the universe, dialogical<br />

personalist philosophy as such only began to take shape in the<br />

wake of World War I. At issue was a loss of confidence in the sufficiency<br />

of reason and the possibilities of human and social<br />

progress, a confidence which had begun with the Enlightenment<br />

and endured as Idealism into the twentieth century.<br />

The drastic experience of the war put an end to the optimism<br />

of Idealism and was, perhaps, the spark for a general renewal<br />

of faith life which accompanied a new attitude of realism,<br />

in which God is not a mere “idea,” nor man a mere “moment”<br />

within that idea. Rather, God and man are two realities, infinitely<br />

different and unequal, but nonetheless, in essential relation<br />

one with the other. The “I” of each man is fully constituted only<br />

by entering into personal relation with the “thou” of others, and<br />

above all, with the Thou of God; true “reality” is to be found in<br />

this dialogical environment.<br />

The most prominent dialogical philosophers – Franz Rosenzweig,<br />

Martin Buber and Ferdinand Ebner – share a remarkable<br />

similarity of thought due not to the limited contact they had


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 209<br />

with one another’s work, but rather deriving from das neue<br />

Denken, “the new thinking,” Rosenzweig’s term for this reaction<br />

against the Cartesian and German Idealism of the time.<br />

While in the trenches of Macedonia during World War I, witnessing<br />

the daily death of his companions, Rosenzweig wrote<br />

his major work, The Star of Redemption, in which he made his<br />

break with philosophical Idealism. 8 At the heart of this shift, Idealism<br />

could not provide Rosenzweig with an explanation for the<br />

carnage of war with its death, loneliness and hate. He came to<br />

see Idealist optimism as merely utopian and instead found authentic<br />

reality in the nearness of concrete beings, and in particular,<br />

in the profound mystery of living relationships between persons.<br />

His system requires one to start from experience, to recognize<br />

speech as the entrance to the essence of being, and the rejection<br />

of a monism that would deny reality. Thus it hinges on<br />

concrete dialogue in relationship rather than solitary, abstract<br />

thought.<br />

There is a threefold reality of Man-World-God, which is not<br />

known by rational deduction and which is beyond our rational<br />

understanding – a threefold working of God, prior to reason, of<br />

creation, revelation and redemption. While God is beyond human<br />

knowledge, the believer experiences God’s working by being<br />

receptive to it; he encounters God by being God’s trusted<br />

child. For Rosenzweig, creation is a dialogical process: it begins<br />

with God’s address to man, which is the source of dialogue between<br />

God and humans. Thus, a key element of God’s creation<br />

as a dialogical process is his gift of speech which is, “the creator’s<br />

morning gift to mankind, and yet at the same time it is the<br />

common property of all the children of men, in which each has<br />

his particular share and, finally, it is the seal of humanity in<br />

man.” 9<br />

The better known Martin Buber sums up the core of dialogical<br />

philosophy right in the title of his seminal work, I and<br />

8 FRANZ ROSENZWEIG, The Star of Redemption (Stern der Erlösung), trans.<br />

William W. Hallo of 2nd edition, 1930 (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,<br />

1971).<br />

9 ROSENZWEIG, The Star of Redemption, 110.


210 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

Thou 10 : one comes to self-identity only in relation to the other.<br />

His starting point is the reality of the “I” and the “Thou” which<br />

pertain to a personal world of “relation” and “meeting,” in contrast<br />

to an impersonal world of “experience” which is the reality<br />

of “I-It”:<br />

Basic words are spoken with one’s being. When one says You,<br />

the I of the word pair I-You is said, too. When one says It, the I of<br />

the word pair I-It is said, too. The basic word I-You can only be<br />

spoken with one’s whole being. The basic word I-It can never be<br />

spoken with one’s whole being. 11<br />

There is risk in the I-Thou relation for there can be no withholding<br />

of self for the whole being is involved. If not, it becomes<br />

an I-It relation because part of the self is holding back as a spectator.<br />

Everything is risked, because the I addresses the Thou<br />

with the whole self, with no defensive position to run to. At the<br />

same time, the Thou must be met in the freedom of otherness,<br />

which means, to respond with total unpredictability. If responses<br />

are calculated, if the I asks itself what kind of impression it is<br />

making on the Thou, then the relation is to an It, not a Thou. So,<br />

the I-Thou relation requires a total listening, always in the present,<br />

without calculating with prejudgements from the past.<br />

What makes such an I-Thou encounter possible is the zwischen<br />

(the Between), a grace that is between the I and the Thou,<br />

and which overcomes their isolation, which Buber interprets in a<br />

religious sense. God is the origin of this grace and He makes every<br />

encounter of the I and the Thou possible: “Every particular Thou<br />

is a glimpse through to the eternal Thou; by means of every particular<br />

Thou the primary word addresses the eternal Thou…” 12<br />

The centrality of God as “the eternal Thou” or “absolute<br />

Thou,” addressed in the second person rather than spoken about<br />

10 MARTIN BUBER, I and Thou, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York:<br />

Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1970); earlier English 2nd edition, trans. Ronald<br />

Gregor Smith (New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons, 1958).<br />

11 BUBER, I and Thou, 54.<br />

12 BUBER, I and Thou, 75.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 211<br />

in the third person, is emblematic of Buber’s thought in I and<br />

Thou, an insight he owes directly to Ferdinand Ebner. Although<br />

Buber himself maintained that he encountered Ebner’s work,<br />

“too late to affect my own thought,” 13 his dependence on Ebner<br />

for this key insight has now been well documented. 14 Because<br />

Buber’s name is practically synonymous with I-Thou thought,<br />

what would merely be an historic footnote is significant here because<br />

it demonstrates the decisive influence of the lesser known<br />

Ferdinand Ebner as foundational and decisive to any understanding<br />

of dialogical philosophy.<br />

Ferdinand Ebner: Dialogical Personalism<br />

While the carnage of World War I caused Ferdinand Ebner<br />

13 RIVKA HORWITZ, “Ferdinand Ebner as a Source of Martin Buber’s Dialogic<br />

Thought in I and Thou,” in Martin Buber: A Centenary Volume, eds.<br />

Haim Gordon and Jochanan Bloch (New York: KTAV, 1984), 122.<br />

14 See HORWITZ, “Ferdinand Ebner,” 123: the concept of God as “the eternal<br />

Thou” or “the absolute Thou” appears in Buber for the first time in early<br />

1922, in a series of lectures entitled, Religion as Presence, delivered just as<br />

Buber was reading Ebner. In these lectures Ebner’s influence is very clear,<br />

but became less obvious later for, “a few months later, when composing the<br />

lectures into a book, Buber took out the concepts closest to Ebner’s, so that<br />

they are less evident in I and Thou.” In HORWITZ’S judgment, “Buber received<br />

the concept of divinity as developed in I and Thou from Ebner. On every page<br />

of the book, Ebner recognizes God as the ‘true Thou’ who cannot be God in<br />

the third person; but this is one of the decisive innovations of I and Thou,<br />

that God can never be grasped in the third person, but only in presence. The<br />

similarity exists not only in the substance of the concept, but also in the<br />

whole structure and development of the idea… ‘Thou’ as the basic and fixed<br />

name of God is found in Buber’s writings only after his encounter with the<br />

writings of Ebner.” See also RIVKA HORWITZ, Buber’s Way to I and Thou: An<br />

Historical Analysis and the First Publication of Martin Buber’s Lectures Religion<br />

As Presence, (Heidelberg: 1978). See also JOHN OESTERREICHER, The Unfinished<br />

Dialogue: Martin Buber and the Christian Way, (Secaucus, NJ: Citadel<br />

Press, 1987), 31.: “Rivka Horwitz has pointed to Ferdinand Ebner as the<br />

source of Buber’s own dialogic thought, particularly the postulate that God<br />

must be addressed not as the remote ‘He,’ but as the ever present ‘Thou.’ In<br />

my opinion, Ebner and Rosenzweig even outrank Buber.”


212 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

(1882-1931) to despair of the value of philosophy as he had<br />

known it, the scandal of Christian fighting against Christian,<br />

brought Ebner to an interior conversion toward Christ. A sickly<br />

man, both physically and psychologically, Ebner became a daily<br />

reader of the Gospel Word, yet remained somewhat aloof from<br />

the institutional Church until returning to the sacraments near<br />

the end of his life.<br />

Ebner would bristle at being called a “philosopher” or a<br />

“theologian”; his thought and his sometimes polemical, aphoristic<br />

style do not fit neatly into any one discipline. He attempts no<br />

“system” of philosophy or theology but he hits the core of dialogical<br />

thought by offering a particular way to “read” some<br />

philosophical and theological questions.<br />

The core of Ebner’s major work, Das Wort und die geistigen<br />

Realitäten (The Word and the Spiritual Realities), 15 is the notion<br />

15 FERDINAND EBNER, Das Wort und die geistigen Realitäten. Pnuematologische<br />

Fragmente (Innsbruck, 1921), republished in Schriften, vol. 1: Fragmente,<br />

Aufsätze, Aphorismen. Zu einer Pneumatologie des Wortes, ed. FRANZ SEYR (Munich:<br />

Kösel Verlag, 1963), 75-342 (hereafter WR); English translations are taken<br />

and used with permission from HAROLD JOHNSON GREEN, “The Word and the<br />

Spiritual Realities: A Translation of and Critical Introduction to FERDINAND<br />

EBNER’s Das Wort und die geistigen Realitäten and a Comparison with Martin<br />

Buber’s Ich und Du” (Ph.D. diss., Northwestern University, 1980), (hereafter<br />

Green). Part I is the “Critical Introduction” and is paginated in Roman numerals;<br />

Part II is the actual translation, paginated in arabic numerals.<br />

Throughout his life, Ebner made “aphoristic” notes on his wide-ranging<br />

studies, some of which were published posthumously as Wort und Liebe (Regensburg:<br />

Friedrich Pustet, 1935), a title given by the editor, HILDEGARD JONE,<br />

which contains Ebner’s 1916-17 diaries, Aus dem Tagebuch 1916/17, and his final<br />

work, Aphorismen, written in 1931 at the request of his friends, Hildegard<br />

Jone and Josef Humplik. Both were republished in EBNER, Schriften, vol. 1, 19-<br />

74 and 909-1014 respectively. In 1949, HILDEGARD JONE edited another selection<br />

from Ebner’s 16 diary notebooks, entitled Das Wort ist der Weg (n.p.: Herder,<br />

1949), but it was not included in the Schriften, nor is it any longer in print, and<br />

thus the Italian translation of Ebner’s Das Wort ist der Weg will be used here: La<br />

parola è la via, edited and translated by EDDA DUCCI and PIERO ROSSANO (Rome:<br />

Anicia, 1991). Translations into English are my own, except where noted.<br />

While there is little written in English on Ebner, an Italian journal has<br />

recently devoted an entire issue to his thought. See the Italian edition of<br />

Communio: Rivista Internazionale di Teologia e Cultura 175-176 (January -<br />

April 2001).


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 213<br />

that human speech is constitutive of human existence: humans<br />

are given the “word.” It is only in the word, in language, that an<br />

“I” meets a “Thou,” that relationship and self-identity can occur,<br />

and this word is given in Jesus Christ, the Word made flesh: Jesus,<br />

the Logos of St. John’s Gospel, mediates between God and<br />

man and “stands” between I and Thou. It is through Jesus that<br />

it is possible to address God in the human thou.<br />

For Ebner, the key to the meaning of life, to the centrality of<br />

relationship, and to God’s continuous action in His creation, is<br />

found in the I-Thou question: why the I can never be found in itself,<br />

and so must look in the thou, while the false I will try to<br />

possess the thou as an object of power. This is the heart of Ebner’s<br />

critique of idealist philosophies and thought: reality, truth,<br />

and personal identity are not ideas, nor are they to be found in<br />

ideas, therefore, Descartes’ cogito must be rejected, for the existence<br />

of the I can’t be founded or proved by solitary thinking, but<br />

only in relation with a thou.<br />

While philosophy had focused so much on the abstract<br />

problem of how the I might reach the world and the world might<br />

reach the “I,” the question remained of how the “authentic” relation<br />

is individualized – this is the concrete problem for man:<br />

just how might the I reach the thou and the thou reach the “I.”<br />

Ebner rejects any access to the true self through the world of<br />

ideas. Likewise, man cannot know another person through an<br />

idea, but only in the spirit; and further, man cannot know God<br />

without knowing his fellow man:<br />

The man whose I has found his thou in God, finds his thou also<br />

in every man whom he encounters along the road of life. Jesus<br />

ought to have said: “You have seen your brother, therefore you have<br />

seen your God.” But the I of the one who cannot find his thou in<br />

man has not yet found it in God either… The relationship of man<br />

with man cannot and should not be based on anything other than<br />

a spiritual base. The idea is never capable of being the link between<br />

the I and the thou, between man and man. In the final analysis a<br />

man’s relationship with the other must be based on his relationship<br />

with God. 16<br />

16 EBNER, Aus dem Tagebuch 1916/17, in Schriften 1:56.


214 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

Man’s own existence presupposes the existence of God: the<br />

fact that man for himself can neither choose to be born nor<br />

refuse ever to die (nor can he choose his height, race, eyes and<br />

hair, etc.) makes his limitedness or creatureliness available to<br />

his own experience. Though man may struggle for more control<br />

over his existence, he experiences himself as created, and must<br />

seek to know his creator, the one whose existence, unlike his<br />

own, is not relative, but absolute.<br />

For Ebner, the path of discovery begins in the word which,<br />

in its being spoken, presupposes the Thou to whom it is spoken,<br />

and since the Thou in its ultimate basis is God, then the existence<br />

of man in his spirituality (as opposed to his I-aloneness)<br />

has the existence of God as its presupposition. Man, created by<br />

God, discovers his own identity in relationship with the Eternal<br />

Thou, in Jesus who is the Word. Only this I-Thou relationship<br />

with God equips man to encounter the other, not in the realm of<br />

ideas, but as a true thou in authentic relationship. Ultimately, for<br />

Ebner, the solution of this question of idea and reality is found<br />

in Jesus who is the Word and who by His word shows man the<br />

way from the I toward God:<br />

The idea is not a spiritual reality but only the dream of one...<br />

There are only two spiritual realities: God and the I. The life of the<br />

spirit in man moves between these two. Through his teaching Jesus<br />

has prepared the end… of every idealism; through his life he<br />

has given a start to what could be called the realism of the spirit.<br />

He has showed man the way from the I toward God. He is, according<br />

to His precise word, the way, the truth and the life. 17<br />

Ebner’s dialogical philosophy is a response to the problems<br />

of Cartesian and German Idealism, and to the whole modern<br />

philosophical tradition which is stuck in what he calls Icheinsamkeit,<br />

or “I-aloneness”: the philosophy of the ego locked in upon<br />

itself. Thus, classical philosophy, which in its reflection discovered<br />

only the “idea,” did not properly grasp the significance<br />

and meaning of the I, which came to be known only later<br />

17 EBNER, Aus dem Tagebuch 1916/17, in Schriften 1:63-64.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 215<br />

through the “religious factor,” through the spirit of Christianity.<br />

Even with the turn of philosophy toward the subject, the I has<br />

been examined only in relation to itself, in its “I-aloneness,”<br />

which is not the real I, but only Pascal’s moi, 18 an infinitely small<br />

man in the universe – grammatically speaking, not a first person<br />

subject, “I” (je), but merely a smaller, third person object, “me”<br />

(moi).<br />

For Ebner, this I-aloneness is the result of an action of the I:<br />

the I secluding itself from the Thou. The existence of the real I,<br />

then, “does not lie in its being related to itself, but rather... in its<br />

relation (Verhältnis) to the Thou.” 19 Outside the I-Thou relation,<br />

there is no I at all.<br />

The true I, then, can never be the abstract, “ideal” I of philosophy.<br />

The real I “comes to expression in the fact that I am and<br />

that I can say that of myself,” 20 that is, because man is given the<br />

word. The I exists in relation to the Thou. The I depends on the<br />

Thou and the Thou depends on the word. It is this I-Thou relation<br />

which shows man his relation to God: in the ultimate<br />

ground of our spiritual life, God is always the true Thou of the<br />

true I in man. Conversely, at the same time, God makes of man<br />

His Thou:<br />

In the spirituality of his origin in God, man was not the “first”<br />

but the “second person” – the first was and is God. And here this<br />

“first” and “second” actually express the spiritual hierarchy, in contrast<br />

to their grammatical usage. Man was the “person addressed”<br />

by God, the Thou of the divine Word which created him. Yet since<br />

18 In searching for the meaning of his own personal existence in a rational,<br />

Cartesian I, what Pascal found was not man in dynamic relation as a<br />

self-affirming subject, “I am,” but the contrary, insignificant man, an infinitely<br />

small and limited moi over against the vastness of the universe. For<br />

Pascal, the I’s aloneness is not due to its self-sufficiency and autonomy, but<br />

rather, in its smallness it is the I of despair. The moi only moves beyond this<br />

meaningless aloneness through the spiritual activity of the heart: “The heart<br />

has its reasons, which reason does not know… It is the heart which experiences<br />

God, not the reason.” See BLAISE PASCAL, Pensées, bilingual edition,<br />

trans. H. F. Stewart (London: Routledge, and Kegan Paul, 1950), 627.<br />

19 GREEN, 10; WR, Schriften 1:84.<br />

20 GREEN, 13; WR, Schriften 1:86.


216 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

it was God himself who spoke, the Thou was not the one it otherwise<br />

always ultimately is, God, but precisely man. 21<br />

God is always the true Thou of man’s I. But in creating man,<br />

God “addressed” him, so here man becomes the thou of the divine<br />

Word which created him. In this one case the perspective<br />

for understanding the spiritual is reversed.<br />

In Ebner’s view, it is unlikely that a truly godless person or a<br />

true atheist could exist, because man’s existence, created by<br />

God, presupposes God, for it is still based on the “God-relationship,”<br />

even when man acts in a godless manner:<br />

We all live by the grace of God, and there is not a man who, in<br />

the innermost part of his heart, does not know of God, does not believe<br />

in God. Yet there are others who cannot put their trust in divine<br />

grace, who secretly do not know how to live, and therefore in<br />

their hidden helplessness and concealed from the eyes of all others,<br />

suffer continually. 22<br />

Those who deny their belief in God to themselves – denying<br />

what dwells in the depths of their consciousness and constitutes<br />

its essence and core – do not recognize God’s spirit present within.<br />

This is their affliction and torment. How to discover the presence<br />

of God’s spirit in man?<br />

Having the Word: the Miracle of Language<br />

For Ebner, the key fact that reveals the presence of the spirit<br />

in man is that man “has the word” (Wort haben). Distinctive in<br />

Ebner is the word as the “objective” vehicle that constitutes a<br />

person and mediates the I-thou relationship. If “having the<br />

word” is key to our human, “speaking nature,” what caused the<br />

passage from nothingness to being? How is it that we “have the<br />

word”? “Man has the word because Someone has called to him,<br />

Someone who is word. Man is one called, one addressed: a proof<br />

21 GREEN, 24; WR, Schriften 1:97.<br />

22 GREEN, 27; WR, Schriften 1:100.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 217<br />

is the ‘nature of the thou’ (Duhaftigkeit) of his consciousness,<br />

synonymous with having the word.” 23<br />

The very heart of Ebner’s thought is found in the first words<br />

of the Gospel of John: “In the beginning was the Word.” 24 This is<br />

the originating, creative, divine Word, which is before all things<br />

– before history, before man – through which everything was<br />

made, but was made flesh and became man: “everything that is,<br />

is by means of the word,” 25 and Jesus Christ is the Word that<br />

founds that word.<br />

This creative, Johannine inspired word is the “body” of interhuman<br />

dialogue, which constitutes or “places” (setzt) man’s<br />

being. The Word (Verbum), the divine Thou of the Father, gives<br />

origin to being. The word that “places” (setzt) being acquires its<br />

meaning in the midst of a phrase (Satz). This is the foundation<br />

of Ebner’s pneumatological thought: “The word is the primary<br />

fact, the ‘place’ [position] of spiritual being – the relation between<br />

the I and the thou – and of being in general. The logos is<br />

not only a presupposition for thought but also for being.” 26<br />

God created man by speaking to him: “I am and through me<br />

Thou art.” 27 Thus, God placed the I in man: the I, created in the<br />

relationship to his true Thou, to God, becomes conscious that he<br />

exists and that God does not cease to address the word to him.<br />

And man responds: “You are, and through You I am.” 28<br />

The Prologue to John also announces the Word made flesh,<br />

as a second creation for man, a rebirth, which reveals the ultimate<br />

spiritual meaning of being for man as interpersonal life in<br />

dialogue: “the light of man is in the word. Through it, consciousness,<br />

as a fact of natural life, is transformed into self-con-<br />

23<br />

EDDA DUCCI and PIERO ROSSANO, in the introduction to their Italian<br />

translation of EBNER’S Wort und Liebe, entitled Parola e Amore (Milan: Rusconi,<br />

1983), 28, citing Ebner without further reference.<br />

24<br />

JOHN 1:1.<br />

25<br />

EBNER, Notizen (16. Juni 1922), in Schriften 2:301.<br />

26<br />

EBNER, Zum Problem der Sprache und Des Wortes, in Schriften, 1:65.<br />

27<br />

GREEN, 23; WR, Schriften 1:96.<br />

28<br />

DUCCI and ROSSANO, introduction to Parola e Amore, 28, citing Ebner<br />

without further reference.


218 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

sciousness, as a fact of spiritual being.” 29 Consciousness of God’s<br />

existence, placed within the essence of man is, “nothing other<br />

than language, understood in the depth of its essence…, the spiritual<br />

fact of ‘having the word...’” 30<br />

In the word man has knowledge of God, but with the Fall,<br />

consciousness of God’s existence darkened again. The “human”<br />

word created by man begins here, and with it, his history: “This<br />

‘human’ word is not the same, though presupposing it, as the<br />

word through which the spiritual life in man, the I in its relation<br />

to the Thou, is created. The human word testifies to that word<br />

which..., since it constitutes all history, has no kind of history itself.”<br />

31 The divine, originating Word became historical; the divine<br />

Word meets the human word in human history, in the Incarnation<br />

of Jesus Christ: “And the Word was made Flesh and<br />

dwelt among us.” 32<br />

The I exists in relation to the Thou, and the word is the spiritual<br />

essence of language which takes place between the I and the<br />

Thou. In Ebner’s view, the fact that language happens at all is always<br />

a miracle, for in order to be myself I have need of the other,<br />

and the other likewise has need of me, yet neither of us can<br />

ever create the conditions of communication: “We remain<br />

locked in mutual need. Nevertheless, language and communication<br />

happens. I do not create this language, but receive it as a<br />

gift. In this sense language has a transcendent origin.” 33<br />

Language is a miracle whose origin is beyond the I or the<br />

thou, yet language is the vehicle between the I and the thou; we<br />

should be astonished at the fact that language exists. In its deepest<br />

ontological sense, Ebner considers language to be the gift of<br />

being, for it is through language that being reveals itself, in conversation<br />

and in temporal events. Thus, in Ebner’s very particular<br />

use of the terms, the origin of language is word.<br />

Ebner distinguishes between the Word, which is divine, and<br />

29<br />

EBNER, Zum Problem der Sprache und Des Wortes, in Schriften, 1:654.<br />

30<br />

GREEN, 24; WR, Schriften 1:97.<br />

31<br />

GREEN, 20-21; WR, Schriften 1:96.<br />

32<br />

JOHN 1:14.<br />

33<br />

JOHN O’DONNELL, “The Trinity as Divine Community,” Gregorianum 69,<br />

1 (1988), 12.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 219<br />

words, which are the condition needed for human language and<br />

dialogue to be possible. Because the human person has the<br />

Word, he can speak. It is God, always the true Thou of the true<br />

I in man, who ultimately addresses man in and through the<br />

word, which, “in the ultimate ground of its being-given-to-man,<br />

is from God.” 34<br />

The I-Thou relation, which arises in man from the divinely<br />

originated word, expressed as language, does not occur at some<br />

point after the I has existed for itself in aloneness. Rather, the I-<br />

Thou relation is the pre-condition: for the existence of the I, “is<br />

objectively identical with the fact that man ‘has the word.’” 35<br />

While some evolutionary theories claim that language is a<br />

process of imitating animal sounds, Ebner insists that language<br />

itself is what separates man from the animals. It is not the simple<br />

process of the brain getting larger that causes consciousness.<br />

There must be a “leap” which animals will never make. “The animal<br />

screeches, howls, roars, etc., but nonetheless remains<br />

mute… Man, on the other hand, ‘has the word.’ And only because<br />

he has the word can he also be silent.” 36 Conversely, animals<br />

have no I because they lack word and language: “It is characteristic<br />

for man that he can express something, and also has<br />

something to express. The animal can express nothing precisely<br />

because it ‘does not have the word.’ But it also has nothing to<br />

express – and for the same reason.” 37<br />

The word makes man free. Animals must obey instincts, but<br />

man, because he can name or concretize his experience in word,<br />

can gain a distance of perspective and then choose in freedom.<br />

In this sense, Jesus the Word frees man in the word.<br />

Word and Love: The Spiritual Realities<br />

Having the word is that leap from animal to man, and it is a<br />

miracle, yet invisible to science, for God becomes visible only in<br />

the eyes of faith, in the interiority of prayer. God is grasped in<br />

34 GREEN, 17; WR, Schriften 1:90.<br />

35 GREEN, 18; WR, Schriften 1:90.<br />

36 EBNER, Aphorismen, in Schriften 1:914.<br />

37 GREEN, 18n.; WR, Schriften 1:90n.


220 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

the intimate bond between word and love, which Ebner describes<br />

as two great miracles in which the spirit is at work, and<br />

which encompass all of reality:<br />

The Word embraces and carries language – not only language,<br />

but the whole man, and not only man, but the being of the whole<br />

world – and therefore it is more than language, more than our spoken<br />

words. It embraces everything which we cannot express, for<br />

which our language does not have the right word. It embraces God,<br />

because God embraces the Word. And it embraces Love. 38<br />

In His will to save man communally, God sent His word and<br />

His love. Ebner argues that authentic community is based on<br />

trust in the word, which makes it possible to relate with others<br />

as persons – a personal dialogue that always leads to God. In<br />

true community, the word is accompanied by love, which is the<br />

Spirit allowing men to live in communion with God and in true<br />

reciprocal relation with one another.<br />

For Ebner this combination of word and love is the linchpin<br />

of man’s I-Thou relation: man knows the reality of God not by<br />

logical proof, but rather in recognizing his absolute dependence<br />

on God, in the fact that the I in man is dependent upon a relation<br />

to the Thou, outside of which it does not exist at all. God becomes<br />

more palpable for man when his I-Thou relation with<br />

God comes to living expression in word and love: We are “hearers<br />

of the word” because God gave us the word; we are “doers of<br />

the word,” insofar as the word we have heard endures as love,<br />

which the word demands we fulfill in our lives. In this way, word<br />

and love are the two key realities of the spiritual life; they form<br />

the link between the I and the thou and bring man to salvation<br />

for they save him from being closed within himself.<br />

Bringing to Speech: Thought Becomes Word<br />

This spiritual significance of language begins with the fact<br />

38 EBNER, Aphorismen, in Schriften, 1:1009, cited and translated in<br />

HAROLD STAHMER, Speak That I May See Thee!: The Religious Significance of<br />

Language (New York: Macmillan, 1968), 236.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 221<br />

that the word “occurs” between the first and second persons. In<br />

being spoken, language presupposes that the relation of the I to<br />

the Thou is a personal one. Precisely because man “has the<br />

word,” the very potentiality of “speaking” brings with it the possibility<br />

of “being addressed” as a person, as the Thou, “the ‘addressability’<br />

in the other, and this belongs just as much to the<br />

essence of personality as the potentiality to express ‘self,’ in<br />

which the ‘I’ emerges.” 39<br />

Bringing thought to speech, in words, liberates the I, for the<br />

strong desire and longing to be known and to express oneself to<br />

the other demonstrates that one’s spiritual life is always oriented<br />

to the spiritual in the other person. The vehicle of this spiritual<br />

relation is the word. Even one’s own solitary thinking is in<br />

the word: “Even if I were closed within myself before others and<br />

I were to occupy myself only with the clarification of my<br />

thoughts, I would desire that relationship – whose vehicle is the<br />

word – because I need it for this clarification.” 40<br />

In the relationship between thought and word, Ebner does<br />

not believe that there are thoughts which cannot be expressed.<br />

Bringing one’s interior life into word regulates thought, especially<br />

the content, for in coming into word, thoughts are discovered<br />

and understood, in an immediate sense, as an expression of<br />

one’s interior life, as an immediate sense of being, consciousness<br />

and existence.<br />

Allowing thoughts to come into speech brings them out of<br />

the private realm and into the public realm – consciously before<br />

God. Word adds a “communicative tension” to the concept of<br />

mere thought, a tension that is the urge or desire to communicate,<br />

so the word brings thought up to the brink of dialogue and<br />

allows the thought to take root in the person’s being.<br />

Word mediates reason but it also founds our origin and<br />

communal existence in relation. Yet, thought which is not<br />

grounded in authentic relation may remain at the level of monologue.<br />

Not to experience a communicative tension to move beyond<br />

monologue of thought and into speech means to ignore the<br />

39 GREEN, 14; WR, Schriften 1:87.<br />

40 EBNER, La parola è la via, 123.


222 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

thou, to stay closed in my thoughts, closed to the world and others,<br />

to let thought remain mere abstract thinking, unconnected<br />

in relation with others. In this sense, the word can be abused using<br />

it idly for chatter, instead of speaking only those words born<br />

of interior silence animated by the mystery of the spirit.<br />

Sin: Failure to Open to the Thou<br />

For Ebner, the dialogical word gives life to relationship, so<br />

that even in silence the word is authentic and directed to a dialogue<br />

partner. We can retreat from this encounter into “I-aloneness”<br />

(Icheinsamkeit), an inauthentic world of idea or “dream of<br />

the spirit” (Traum vom Geist), a kind of slumber from which<br />

modern culture cannot awake on its own – but only by waiting<br />

for and responding to God’s call. Such a “closing of oneself to the<br />

Thou” (Duverschlossenheit) is the heart of sin.<br />

This has a bearing on how good and evil will be understood.<br />

“The fundamental error of idealist ethics: that good and evil<br />

have to do with the individual founded in himself. But all good<br />

and all evil have to do with the I with respect to the thou. One is<br />

good or bad only in relation to another.” 41 Sin, then, is not an<br />

“idea,” but is in the realm of broken relation:<br />

Every experience convinces that the full realization of the I is<br />

in the vital discovery of the authentic Thou, the dialogue partner<br />

that makes all the richness of his own being resound and that<br />

shows the true sickness of closure, of isolation; the seriousness of<br />

a spiritual sickness that can weaken the I to the point of death<br />

without having found the Thou. The Light calls this darkness by its<br />

true name: sin. 42<br />

In Jesus darkness is overcome. In the Word made flesh,<br />

“contempt for man” (Menschenverachtung) is definitively elimi-<br />

41<br />

EBNER, La parola è la via, 196.<br />

42<br />

DUCCI & ROSSANO, introduction to Parola e Amore, 30, citing Ebner<br />

without further reference.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 223<br />

nated, not by the force of ideas but by lived reality. Jesus definitively<br />

shows how the I reaches the thou and the thou reaches the<br />

I: each moves along two routes – towards God and towards man.<br />

Because of Christ’s Incarnation, between God and man there is<br />

now man, and in man there is now the privileged manifestation<br />

of God.<br />

Ebner’s thought is profound: any attempt to find the thou in<br />

God alone is destined to fail because one doesn’t know how to<br />

find the thou in man. Any road toward God that does not pass<br />

through man is blocked. Man must search for God not only within<br />

himself, but also in his neighbor, for man’s relationship with<br />

God always begins by relating to concrete man. This means that<br />

the I of man must make the leap from the experience of the<br />

“Thou-God” to the experience of the “thou-man.” God is not metaphysically<br />

remote from us but rather quite near and accessible:<br />

We are therefore not to dream of Him. Whoever does that does<br />

not want to see Him in the reality of His nearness. One could thus<br />

even say that God is near to us not only spiritually but also physically:<br />

near to us in everyone, and above all in the man next to us,<br />

the neighbor… God is near to us in the man whom we, emerging<br />

from our I-aloneness, make the true Thou of our I, which obviously<br />

does not mean simply to look at him in his humanity as God.<br />

What you have done to the very least of my brethren, you have<br />

done to me… 43<br />

The nearness of God is discovered in the I-Thou relation<br />

with the neighbor. The true I is always in relation to a Thou such<br />

that the “being-for-itself” of the I in its aloneness is not an authentic<br />

part of the spiritual life of man, but is a consequence of<br />

“secluding himself from the Thou,” which is, “nothing other<br />

than the ‘fall from God,’ the attempt of man to exist in godless<br />

‘inwardness’ (Innerlichkeit)…; it is the first abuse and perverted<br />

use of the ‘freedom,’ of the ‘personality’ of existing, implanted into<br />

man by God.” 44<br />

43 GREEN, 210-211; WR, Schriften 1:268.<br />

44 GREEN, 18; WR, Schriften 1:91.


224 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

Where the Fall is acknowledged, man’s predicament in the<br />

world, especially in his spiritual existence in the world, can be<br />

properly understood. Man became the “slave to sin,” forfeiting<br />

that aspect of his personality that exists only in its relation to<br />

God: by trying to be “free,” in the sense of absolute independence<br />

or “I-aloneness,” man turns away from the other, and<br />

avoids the Thou, in violation of the very definition of being a<br />

person, an I, given by God in the word. This is the Fall. In trying<br />

to be more free and independent, man ends up less so. Yet, when<br />

the I moves out of this “I-aloneness,” there is an unfolding and<br />

openness to the Thou which,<br />

… has the meaning of an offering. God is the “being to whom<br />

we sacrifice.” What does man sacrifice? Everything which he has<br />

grasped as his own in his I-aloneness and taciturnity before the<br />

Thou… The I must give up all that belongs to it, everything that it<br />

grasped or willed to grasp… 45<br />

For Ebner, there is not sin as such; there is sin only in man,<br />

and then only insofar as it is revealed to him in faith. This is not<br />

a theological consideration of objective matter, but rather an assertion<br />

that sin is a “relational” reality. Therefore on the part of<br />

the subject, sin is only subjectively possible once the reality of<br />

the I-Thou relation is recognized, and in the final analysis, this<br />

is always in reference to the I-Thou relation with God: “Man discerns<br />

his ‘mortal sin’ in that action through which … he consciously<br />

and deliberately affirms and approves of his fall from<br />

God, the I-aloneness of his existence, the ‘original sin.’” 46 While<br />

in reality there are many transgressions,<br />

there is only one sin, the sin: only the single sin of interior closing<br />

before God and before men… Born into evil itself is the fact<br />

that man closes himself off and “does not come to the light…” All<br />

evil happens in the “closure” of the I to the thou, in “aloneness.” 47<br />

45 GREEN, 211; WR, Schriften 1:268-269.<br />

46 GREEN, 252; WR, Schriften 1:307.<br />

47 EBNER, Aphorismen, in Schriften 1:997-998.


Return to the Word<br />

DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 225<br />

Every aspect of spiritual life, even sin, has a direct and essential<br />

relationship to the word, because that life was created<br />

through the word: “All being, which has fallen from God and has<br />

become wordless, is destined to return again to the word – in<br />

man and through him.” 48<br />

There is a concrete moral dimension to Ebner’s thought in<br />

the fundamental premise that we are created in the Word: God<br />

calls to us in love, and we are free to respond to that love or not.<br />

The call-response dynamic of I-thou relationship has an ethical<br />

content in the sense that the moral life is our response to God,<br />

and at the same time one’s behavior is good or bad mainly in the<br />

context of relationship with others. Humans are the animals<br />

that speak, but there is an ethical or “responsible” dimension<br />

such that speaking orients our existence toward the thou, that is,<br />

we do not speak as isolated individuals but within relationships,<br />

which presumes an orientation toward communal life.<br />

While Ebner does not develop the theme, if the moral life is<br />

a lived response to God’s address, this suggests a “moral” dimension<br />

to sacraments. Ebner’s understanding of the “dialogical”<br />

power of the word coincides with the Church’s traditional<br />

understanding of the sacraments as “efficacious.” Aware of the<br />

necessity for formal expressions of man’s I-Thou relation with<br />

God, Ebner is sensitive to the the risk that the sacraments might<br />

be celebrated as empty, external forms if they lack a contact with<br />

life. On the other hand, in Ebner’s view, when an institution, as<br />

a “sacrament,” in its spiritual reality, is structured in a way that<br />

engages the personal and dialogical dimensions of life in the<br />

faith, then it truly is an authentic Christian sign.<br />

Ebner offers no extensive application of his thought to the<br />

sacraments which, from a post-Vatican II vantage point, seems<br />

a weakness in his thought. Still, Ebner points in this direction:<br />

in sin, being falls from God and thus loses the word, and is destined<br />

to return again to the word – in man and through him.<br />

This “return to the word” suggests an opening to sacraments in<br />

48 GREEN, 266; WR, Schriften 1:320.


226 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

general, and to Eucharist and Confession more specifically, for<br />

in Ebner’s sense of the word, external signs and gestures have a<br />

place in interpersonal communication, for the word is perceptible<br />

and real when persons encounter and communicate with<br />

each other. In a wide sense all sacrament can be seen as word,<br />

as a medium for the encounter of man with God. However, Ebner<br />

does not go this far, but leaves this fruitful avenue for later<br />

reflection by others.<br />

Ebner Appraised<br />

It is difficult to sum up the work of this rather original<br />

thinker, as his work does not fit neatly into any single category.<br />

Without question, the serious reader will find difficulties in Ebner’s<br />

fragments, discovering that they are:<br />

… inchoative and polemical in nature, and require that the reader<br />

think through the thoughts only begun in them, and systematize<br />

for argumentation’s sake that which is frequently confessional<br />

rather than conceptual. Further, the fragments evidence<br />

through[out] a fundamental inconsistency, one which Ebner himself<br />

was deeply aware of yet could not avoid: the mode of presentation,<br />

namely philosophical discourse, stands in diametrical opposition<br />

to the content therof, namely the word and the spiritual realities<br />

of the I and the Thou. 49<br />

Methodologically, although Ebner rejects philosophy, he is<br />

in the predicament of making his case using philosophical argument<br />

and speaking in the “objective,” third person as philosophy<br />

demands. Likewise, in Ebner’s thought, the relationships between<br />

reason and faith and between philosophy and theology ultimately<br />

remain somewhat fluid and are not completely resolvable.<br />

Because the centrality of the word is the basis of reason in<br />

man, Ebner fluctuates between the philosophical and the theo-<br />

49 GREEN, Part I, 100 [c]; citing and trans. BERNHARD CASPER, Das Dialogische<br />

Denken: Eine Untersuchung der religionsphilosophischen Bedeutung<br />

Franz Rosenzweigs, Ferdinand Ebners und Martin Bubers (Freiburg: Herder,<br />

1967), 259f.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 227<br />

logical: that man is addressed by the word means that man’s existence<br />

has a religious basis such that, “the existence of<br />

man... has the existence of God as its presupposition. In other<br />

words, it means that man was created by God.” 50<br />

Ebner’s understanding of the centrality of word is theological,<br />

but at the same time anthropological in the sense that it defines<br />

man, but the precise line between the divine, creative Word<br />

and the human word is unclear. Likewise, the line between Godhuman<br />

relation and strictly human relations is unclear: it is<br />

clear in Ebner that the God-human relation is somehow different<br />

than strictly human relations, but it is not clear how, other<br />

than to say that the human to human relation concretizes the<br />

God-human relation.<br />

Despite his aphoristic style and the difficulties of his<br />

thought, Ebner undertook a most challenging task: in trying to<br />

overcome the limits in idealistic thought and move beyond the<br />

possibilities of the “sciences,” he circles around and around his<br />

points, trying to express something spiritually elusive, beyond<br />

the immediate sense of his words. The reader, having entered into<br />

Ebner’s mode of expression and style, is rewarded by the originality<br />

and richness of his thought.<br />

Even with his ambiguities, Ebner makes a substantial<br />

achievement in his presentation of I-Thou relation, an advance<br />

that is somewhat taken for granted, having now been assimilated<br />

by other thinkers. 51 It is Ebner who places the origin of all relation<br />

squarely in God, identifying God as the “eternal Thou,”<br />

who reveals Himself as such to man. This revelation awakens<br />

man from his “dream of the spirit”; in recognizing the eternal<br />

Thou, man discovers the I in himself, and so can recognize the<br />

other as his thou.<br />

More than this, Ebner moves beyond other dialogical<br />

philosophers, with his very original presentation of the word as<br />

the centerpiece of this revelation and discovery within I-Thou<br />

50 GREEN, 23; WR, Schriften 1:96.<br />

51 Directly in such authors as Romano Guardini, Bernard Häring, and<br />

Hans Urs von Balthasar; indirectly in many authors right up to the present<br />

such as René Latourelle, Edward Schillebeeckx, Karl Rahner, Walter Kasper,<br />

Joseph Ratzinger and John Paul II.


228 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

relations. Here, Ebner breaks some new ground. He accepts the<br />

view of the eighteenth century Sturm und Drang philosopher, Johann<br />

Georg Hamann, that logos is reason, and thus to be human<br />

is to speak. 52 Language philosophers take up this theme as well,<br />

trying to explain the workings of language in human interaction,<br />

but Ebner asks instead: why, and from where, does man have the<br />

word?<br />

This is Ebner at his most original and his key contribution<br />

to this study: God spoke creation into existence, for His Word is<br />

action. Man’s “forgetfulness” of God in the Fall and his concomitant<br />

“dream of the spirit” are remedied in the same creative<br />

Word, who was in the beginning and is God. Jesus, the Word<br />

made Flesh, is God’s self-revelation as eternal Thou, the Word<br />

spoken to man to “re-awaken” him from his “dream of the spirit,”<br />

from his state of I-aloneness (Icheinsamkeit) which is isolation<br />

and monologue. The Word breaks through such that man<br />

discovers the Other, the eternal Thou, and in so discovering, his<br />

isolation ends; monologue becomes dialogue in man’s discovery<br />

of his own “I” necessarily reflected by the discovery of the Thou.<br />

In the same discovery, man’s relation with human “thous” is redefined<br />

by the very same Word.<br />

For Ebner, while the word is clearly foundational for human<br />

identity, the question of how language operates as such remains<br />

pending. The relationships between word and language and between<br />

word and sacrament provide fruitful avenues for study in<br />

dialogue with language philosophy and sacramental theology.<br />

Implications<br />

Having examined the thought of Ferdinand Ebner in some<br />

detail, it is worthwhile to briefly highlight a few ways in which<br />

52 The Sturm und Drang (Storm and Stress) movement of 1770’s Germany<br />

<strong>propos</strong>ed that for life to be meaningful, it had to be lived with one’s<br />

full energies applied to religion, poetry and discourse, at the same time embracing<br />

nature, feelings and mystery. The movement has echoes in later<br />

19th century romanticism and 20th century existential and language<br />

philosophies.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 229<br />

the recovery of his dialogical personalism can contribute to the<br />

dialogue between philosophy and theology – including moral<br />

theology – called for in Fides et ratio.<br />

The Holy Father urges a recovery of philosophy’s relationship<br />

with theology so that the proper place of faith in understanding<br />

our very existence can likewise be recovered. In order<br />

to achieve a true global ethics, a philosophy in which is found,<br />

“even a glimmer of the truth of Christ, the one definitive answer<br />

to humanity’s problems, will provide a potent underpinning for<br />

the true and planetary ethics which the world now needs.” 53<br />

This relationship of philosophy and theology – reason’s contribution<br />

to faith – is a delicate one. The Holy Father is careful<br />

to note that faith and revelation do not negate or reduce the<br />

rightful autonomy and discoveries of reason, but at the same<br />

time, reason is not absolute in itself and must constantly question<br />

and be open to questioning. 54 In this way, philosophy and<br />

theology are necessarily linked in a mutual relationship by<br />

which each illuminates the other.<br />

Jesus came into the world as, “the eternal Word who enlightens<br />

all people, so that he might dwell among them and tell<br />

them the innermost realities about God. Jesus Christ, the Word<br />

made flesh, sent as ‘a human being to human beings,’ ‘speaks the<br />

words of God,’ and completes the work of salvation which his<br />

Father gave him to do.” 55 This is a knowledge that is not contrary<br />

to reason even as it is beyond the knowledge of reason alone.<br />

The Holy Father situates this encounter in dialogue between<br />

God and man within the Vatican II understanding of God’s revelation<br />

found in Dei Verbum, 56 an understanding with many<br />

points of reference in Ebner’s thought.<br />

As Joseph Ratzinger pointed out some years after the Council,<br />

Dei Verbum 2 reflects a very different understanding of God’s<br />

revelation, considerably influenced in this century by the dialogical<br />

personalism of Ferdinand Ebner, Martin Buber and oth-<br />

53 FR, 104.<br />

54 FR, 79.<br />

55 FR, 11, citing Tertio Millenio Adveniente (10 November 1994), 4; Jn<br />

1:1-18; 3:34; 5:36; 17:4.<br />

56 FR, 7-12: “Chapter 1: The Revelation of God’s Wisdom.”


230 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

ers in which, “we first have a reference to God Himself, ‘in his<br />

wisdom and goodness,’ thus giving a far greater emphasis to the<br />

personal and theocentric starting point when compared to Vatican<br />

I…” 57 Here, God’s will is “sacramentum,” “a sacramental<br />

view, which sees law and grace, word and deed, message and<br />

sign, the person and his utterance within the one comprehensive<br />

unity of the mystery.” 58 The mystery is the mystery of God which<br />

is, “ultimately nothing other than Christ himself – it is the person.<br />

From this there follows an understanding of revelation that<br />

is seen basically as dialogue….” 59<br />

In the reading of Scripture, “a dialogue takes place between<br />

God and man,” which reaches its highest point when the<br />

Church, “listens to the word of God in common in the sacred<br />

liturgy and within this framework itself experiences the active<br />

presence of the Logos, the Word in the words.” 60 God’s dialogue<br />

is always actual; as I-Thou dialogue it always takes place in the<br />

present tense. In Dei Verbum 2, Jesus’ words, “no longer do I call<br />

you servants... but... friends,” are given,<br />

here and now with the intention of forcing us to reply. Thus<br />

we can see how the idea of revelation also outlines a conception of<br />

man: man as the creature of dialogue who, in listening to the word<br />

of God, becomes contemporaneous with the presentness of God<br />

and in the fellowship of the word receives the reality which is indivisibly<br />

one with this word: fellowship with God himself. 61<br />

Likewise, in Vatican II there is a deepening understanding of<br />

revelation as, “a totality, in which word and event make up one<br />

whole, a true dialogue which touches man in his totality, not only<br />

challenging his reason, but, as dialogue, addressing him as a<br />

57<br />

JOSEPH RATZINGER, “Dogmatic Constitution on Divine Revelation,” in<br />

Commentary on the Documents of Vatican II, ed. Herbert Vorgrimler and others<br />

(New York: Herder and Herder, 1969), vol. 3, 170-171. See Dei Verbum, 2<br />

and Vatican I, Dei Filius in DS3004f.<br />

58<br />

RATZINGER, 171.<br />

59<br />

RATZINGER, 171.<br />

60<br />

RATZINGER, 271; citing Dei Verbum, 25.<br />

61<br />

RATZINGER, 171, citing John 15:15.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 231<br />

partner, indeed, giving him his true nature for the first time.” 62<br />

Thus in the New Testament, “instead of words, we have the<br />

Word. Christ no longer speaks merely of God, but he is himself<br />

the speech of God; this man is himself and as an entity the Word<br />

of God that has made himself one of us… In him God has, as it<br />

were, said himself.” 63 Therefore, God’s revelation does not talk<br />

about something that is somehow external to the person; rather,<br />

revelation is concerned with, “the relation of the human ‘I’ to the<br />

divine ‘thou,’ so that the purpose of this dialogue is ultimately<br />

not information, but unity and transformation.” 64<br />

In this understanding of revelation as dialogical, the considerable<br />

if indirect influence of Ferdinand Ebner is so apparent<br />

that Ebner has been called, “the secret philosophical inspiration<br />

of modern theology.” 65 Yet, as René Latourelle observed, it is surprising,<br />

given the symbolic aspect of Word as the mode of God’s<br />

self-communication that, “there are very few theologians who<br />

elaborate these notions of word.…” 66 It is this mystery that Ebner<br />

examines from so many perspectives – how the I-thou dynamic<br />

of God calling to us and our responding is constitutive of<br />

being.<br />

Philosophy is necessary to this theological enterprise for,<br />

without it, as the Holy Father maintains, “it would in fact be impossible<br />

to discuss theological issues such as, for example, the<br />

use of language to speak about God, the personal relations within<br />

the Trinity, God’s creative activity in the world, the relationship<br />

between God and man, or Christ’s identity as true God and<br />

62 RATZINGER, 172.<br />

63 RATZINGER, 175, commenting on the use of Hebrews 1 in Dei Verbum<br />

4, and citing René Latourelle, Theology of Revelation (Théologie de la Révélation)<br />

(New York: Alba House, 1966) and KARL RAHNER, “The Development of<br />

Dogma,” Theological Investigations 1 (London: Darton, Longman & Todd,<br />

1961), 39-78.<br />

64 RATZINGER, 175.<br />

65 JURGEN MOLTMANN, Anfänge der dialektischen Theologie, 1 (Mn: n.p.,<br />

1966), xvii, cited in HANS WALDENFELS, “La comprensione della rivelazione nel<br />

XX secolo,” in La rivelazione, trans. Maria Christina Laurenzi (Palermo: Edizioni<br />

Augustinus, 1992), 452.<br />

66 LATOURELLE, Theology of Revelation, 208.


232 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

true man.” 67 Although human language cannot completely express<br />

the reality of God, “faith clearly presupposes that human<br />

language is capable of expressing divine and transcendent reality<br />

in a universal way….” 68 In this way, the word of God is a divine<br />

word, although expressed in human language.<br />

However, philosophy needs to go beyond more limited existential,<br />

hermeneutical and linguistic questions, to examine the<br />

more radical questions about the fundamental meaning of personal<br />

existence, being and God. Otherwise, philosophy offers<br />

less to theology than it might for, in the Holy Father’s estimation,<br />

people are settling for, “partial and provisional truths, no longer<br />

seeking to ask radical questions about the meaning and ultimate<br />

foundation of human, personal and social existence. In short,<br />

the hope that philosophy might be able to provide definitive answers<br />

to these questions has dwindled.” 69<br />

As a Catholic thinker, Ebner’s notion of God as the Eternal<br />

Thou and his understanding of “Word” as foundational – to be<br />

echoed later in Dei Verbum – make a substantial contribution<br />

here: faith and reason meet in our human nature, we are created<br />

in the Word, the Word of faith who is Jesus Christ, while at<br />

the same time, it is “having the word,” which is the very manifestation<br />

of reason. Because the central reality of man and<br />

woman is the fact of being created by God, their very identity is<br />

found as dialogue partners with the Eternal Thou.<br />

Ebner does not substantially develop this relationship between<br />

word, language and reason, which is a central theme for<br />

language philosophy. Rather, Ebner’s significant contribution is<br />

to provide the theological link to Jesus Christ, the Word made<br />

flesh, as the foundational word that undergirds human language<br />

which mediates reason.<br />

The dialogical reality of the relationship between God and<br />

man founded in Jesus Christ, the Word made flesh, suggests an<br />

invitation both in God’s “call,” and at the same time, in man’s<br />

ability to “respond.” In Ebner’s thought, this “ability to respond”<br />

67 FR, 66.<br />

68 FR, 84.<br />

69 FR, 5.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 233<br />

– the very meaning of “responsibility” – suggests a fundamental<br />

moral dimension in our dialogical relationships with God and<br />

neighbor.<br />

The fact of “having the word,” makes man free. Animals do<br />

not speak and consequently do not possess reason with its capacity<br />

for abstraction, for stepping back to a “distance of perspective,”<br />

to make choices rather than respond to instinct. The<br />

fact that man speaks, as Ebner makes clear, is the manifestation<br />

of reason, of abstract thought, of perspective and of choice. Because<br />

man chooses, man is free. In the word, Jesus Christ, the<br />

Word made flesh, makes man free – a foundational condition of<br />

moral life.<br />

But man can hide from such freedom and retreat into a<br />

world of monologue and ideas. Where there is fragmentation of<br />

knowledge, as John Paul II notes, the sense that meaning can no<br />

longer be sought or found may lead to, “a kind of ambiguous<br />

thinking which leads it to an ever deepening introversion, locked<br />

within the confines of its own immanence without reference of<br />

any kind to the transcendent.” 70 In such a framework, there is no<br />

longer a basis for “moral” decisions, which are replaced by institutional<br />

or “pragmatic” considerations, by which the Holy Father<br />

explains, “anthropology itself is severely compromised by a<br />

one-dimensional vision of the human being, a vision which excludes<br />

the great ethical dilemmas and the existential analyses of<br />

the meaning of suffering and sacrifice, of life and death.” 71 The<br />

result is a kind of solitary nihilism in which, “the neglect of being<br />

inevitably leads to losing touch with objective truth and<br />

therefore with the very ground of human dignity.” 72 This in turn<br />

brings a loss of the sense that man and woman are made in the<br />

image and likeness of God, and leads, “little by little either to a<br />

destructive will to power or to a solitude without hope.” 73<br />

This “solitude without hope” is the very “I-aloneness” of<br />

which Ebner spoke, an “introversion” which hides from dialogue<br />

and encounter, a “closure to the thou” which is the very<br />

70 FR, 81.<br />

71 FR, 89.<br />

72 FR, 90.<br />

73 FR, 90.


234 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

heart of sin. Ebner argues that one is not good or evil in relation<br />

to oneself, but only in relation to another. Therefore, sin is not<br />

an “idea” but is concretely an issue of broken relation, of turning<br />

from authentic I-thou dialogue with God and neighbor. This<br />

has been the heart of the Fall from the beginning: in trying to be<br />

absolutely “free” in the sense of absolute independence, man<br />

turns away for the other, avoiding the Thou. In trying to be more<br />

free and independent, man ends up less so.<br />

The understanding that God’s word can be expressed in<br />

some fashion in human language, as the Holy Father notes,<br />

points up the importance of philosophy for moral theology’s<br />

treatment of, “moral law, conscience, freedom, personal responsibility<br />

and guilt, which are in part defined by philosophical<br />

ethics.” 74 All of these are mediated in language and the path back<br />

to God in the moral sphere is through the word. In Ebner’s<br />

terms, because every aspect of spiritual life, including sin, has a<br />

direct relationship to the word, because all life is created<br />

through the word: “All being, which has fallen from God and has<br />

become wordless, is destined to return again to the word – in<br />

man and through him.” 75<br />

Thus the moral core for Ebner is this: we are created in the<br />

Word, God calls to us in love, and we are free to respond to that<br />

love or not. Our choice to respond or not respond is a moral<br />

stance toward relationship with God and others, or toward a retreat<br />

into self. This is a freedom that can be misused. There is an<br />

ethical or “responsible” dimension in the fact that unlike animals,<br />

we speak: speaking orients us toward the thou; we do not<br />

speak as isolated individuals but within relationships and we are<br />

“good” or “bad” within relationships, which of itself suggests our<br />

human orientation not to solitary isolation, but to communal<br />

life.<br />

In considering the relationship between faith and reason<br />

and the need for a revitalized dialogue in which philosophy will<br />

once again assist theology in discovering the proper place of<br />

faith in understanding our very existence, this article has not at-<br />

74 FR, 66.<br />

75 GREEN, 266; WR, Schriften 1:320.


DIALOGICAL PERSONALISM REVISITED 235<br />

tempted to analyze the merits of the various philosophies of recent<br />

centuries. Rather, the goal has been the “recovery” of dialogical<br />

personalist philosophy, particularly as found in the work<br />

of the Catholic thinker, Ferdinand Ebner, as a helpful platform<br />

for such a dialogue today.<br />

Still, Ebner does not bring us all the way; his thought is not<br />

a destination. Rather he provides a bridge to further reflection –<br />

Ebner gives us the why of language, the underpinning of the<br />

faculty of reason, that is, why man has the use of language and<br />

why having the word is foundational to our identity as rational<br />

beings, why we are founded in the word, in Jesus Christ, the<br />

Word made flesh. But Ebner does not really provide the how of<br />

language, for this we must turn to the philosophy of language –<br />

how language operates and works as such – for language is needed<br />

to discuss theology, including these very moral issues.<br />

In this sense, Ebner clearly opens the way to fruitful dialogue<br />

between the operation of language in language philosophy<br />

and its efficacious use in sacramental theology, in which the reality<br />

of man, as a speaking being created by God in Jesus Christ,<br />

is made manifest in the intensive moments of sacramental celebrations.<br />

Further reflection is needed on the application of dialogical<br />

thought in the concrete relationship between language<br />

philosophies and sacramental theologies and their further implications<br />

for living out a moral life day to day, a topic to be taken<br />

up in a subsequent article.<br />

Immaculate Conception Seminary JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

School of Theology<br />

Seton Hall University<br />

South Orange, New Jersey 07079<br />

USA.<br />

chapeljo@shu.edu<br />

—————<br />

The author is a priest of the Archdiocese of Newark and Assistant<br />

Professor of Theology at Immaculate Conception Seminary<br />

School of Theology, Seton Hall University, South Orange, New Jersey,<br />

USA.


236 JOSEPH CHAPEL<br />

El autor es sacerdote de la arquidiócesis de Newark y profesor<br />

auxiliar de teología en la Immaculate Conception Seminary School<br />

of Theology en la Universidad de Seton Hall, South Orange, New Jersey,<br />

USA.<br />

—————


StMor 40 (2002) 237-258<br />

MARTIN MCKEEVER, C.SS.R.<br />

CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT<br />

OF POSTMODERNISM?: A READING OF ZYGMUNT<br />

BAUMAN’S POSTMODERN ETHICS<br />

IN THE LIGHT OF FIDES ET RATIO<br />

Fides et ratio (September, 1998) has recently emphasized the<br />

importance of studying philosophy for a more adequate articulation<br />

and communication of the christian faith in contemporary<br />

culture 1 . The encyclical conceives of the proper relationship<br />

between faith and reason, and hence between theology and philosophy,<br />

as a kind of virtuous circle in which each stimulates, enhances<br />

and perfects the other. Faith serves reason in these ways<br />

by proclaiming with conviction the truth of Revelation as the ultimate<br />

and universal truth about human life; reason serves faith<br />

by critically posing the ultimate questions about human life and<br />

by refining the articulation and systematic expression of the answers<br />

to these questions. While presenting this conception of the<br />

relationship between faith and reason as the ideal, Fides et ratio<br />

clearly laments the fact that this relationship rarely exists in<br />

practice in modern and postmodern culture.<br />

The concern of this piece is not with the broader question of<br />

the relationship between faith and reason, but is rather limited<br />

to the implications of this question for morality, understood<br />

here as the practical and theoretical pursuit of what is good. A<br />

superficial reading of the encyclical might lead one to conclude<br />

that it is not much concerned with morality, being focussed primarily<br />

on Revelation, epistemology and cultural change. Read<br />

with due attention, however, it becomes clear that what the en-<br />

1 This article was first published in Portugese in a recent number of<br />

Fragmentos de Cultura dedicated in part to the theme of faith and ethics, see:<br />

M. MCKEEVER, Alguma Coisa Boa Pode Sair do Pósmodernismo?: una leitura<br />

de ética postmoderna de Zygmunt Bauman à luz de Fides et ratio in Fragmentos<br />

de Cultura 11/4 (2001) 501-520.


238 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

cyclical has to say about Revelation, epistemology and cultural<br />

change has profound relevance precisely for morality. In fact, a<br />

good case could be made for arguing that one of the central concerns<br />

of Fides et ratio is the way in which morality has been affected<br />

by sweeping cultural change.<br />

The cultural change referred to in the encyclical is in the<br />

first instance what we might call modernity, meaning by this<br />

word the whole gamut of economic, political, social and philosophical<br />

mutations which have been in evidence since the Enlightenment.<br />

Given the broader theme of the encyclical, the aspect<br />

of modernity which receives most attention is philosophical<br />

thought, particularly in its relation to christian faith. While this<br />

remains a primary focus of the encyclical, there is no doubt that<br />

the more recent form of cultural change which is referred to as<br />

postmodernity also constitutes a major source of preoccupation.<br />

Both in general philosophical terms and in specifically moral<br />

terms postmodernism is seen as an ambiguous phenomenon<br />

which threatens to undermine confidence in reason and drive<br />

contemporary society into nihilistic attitudes.<br />

It is ironic that among the many postmodernist authors who<br />

write passionately about moral questions, there are so few who<br />

attempt to articulate a systematic account of ethics. Perhaps such<br />

a project appears inherently recidivist to the postmodern mind in<br />

that it is held to repeat the modernist mistake of trying to impose<br />

rational schemes on chaotic human reality. Whatever of that,<br />

amid the oceanic bibliography on postmodernism there is a noticeable<br />

dearth of studies which spell out the implications of postmodernism<br />

for ethics as a discipline. 2 The result is that one is gen-<br />

2 A selection of studies which at least broach the subject, albeit in diverse<br />

perspectives, might include: LEVINAS, E. Etica come filosofia prima (Milano:Guerini,<br />

1991); MÜLLER, D. L’éthique protestante dans la crise de la<br />

modernité (Paris: Les éditions du cerf, 1999); VATTIMO, G. Etica de la interpretación<br />

(Buenos Aires:Paidos, 1992); KEARNY, R. “Ethics and the Postmodern<br />

Imagination” in Thought: A Review of Culture and Ideas, 62:224 (1987)<br />

39-58; FRATALONE, R. “Etica teologica e le istanze della postmodernità” in<br />

Quaderni di Synaxis10, Prospettive etiche nella postmodernità (Milano:San<br />

Paolo, 1994) 52-82; MCKEEVER, M. “Postmodern with a difference: Simone<br />

Weil’s ethico-theological critique of totalitarianism in L’enracinement” in<br />

<strong>Studia</strong> <strong>Moralia</strong> 37 (1999) 185-214.


CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT OF POSTMODERNISM?... 239<br />

erally left to suppose or imagine what kind of understanding of<br />

ethics underlies the position which a given postmodernist author<br />

adopts on important moral questions such as social oppression in<br />

capitalist culture, conventional and nuclear war, biomedical research<br />

and techniques, feminist and gender issues, human rights<br />

and so forth. One of the few postmodernists who has attempted<br />

to articulate a postmodern ethics is the British sociologist Zygmunt<br />

Bauman. In his work Postmodern Ethics 3 , this author <strong>propos</strong>es<br />

a vision of morality which reflects the critique of modernism<br />

germane to postmodernist thought.<br />

This article will attempt a systematic comparative study of<br />

the understanding of morality articulated in Bauman’s work and<br />

that articulated in Fides et ratio. The method to be employed<br />

here will involve three stages: first, we will allow Bauman to<br />

“speak for himself”, as it were, through close reference to Postmodern<br />

Ethics (and at the same time to speak for other postmodern<br />

authors, upon whom he draws heavily). Second, we will<br />

attempt to articulate the moral import of the broader argument<br />

of Fides et ratio. Third, we will revisit Bauman’s account of<br />

morality in order to identify and analyse the key points of contrast<br />

with the Catholic position. A careful reading of these two<br />

texts in this light should afford some interesting answers to such<br />

topical questions as the following: What is the importance of<br />

postmodern philosophy for ethics in general and for theological<br />

ethics in particular? What aspects of postmodern ethical<br />

thought does christian ethics reject as incompatible with christian<br />

morality and why?<br />

Morality according to Zymunt Bauman’s Postmodern<br />

Ethics<br />

In this section, Bauman’s thought will be presented synthetically<br />

in the form of the following three tenets which, it is hoped,<br />

adequately present his argument:<br />

3 BAUMAN, Zygmunt. Postmodern Ethics. (Oxford UK & Cambridge USA:<br />

Blackwell, 1993). Portugese translation: Ética pósmoderna (São Paolo:<br />

Paulus, 1997).


240 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

a. The modernist project of making progress by regulating human<br />

conduct through the use of instrumental reason has<br />

been discredited<br />

b. Spontaneous moral impulse is the only source of morality<br />

c. The moral self is constituted by its responsibility for the<br />

Other<br />

Without for the moment offering any critique of Bauman’s<br />

position, we may summarize his thought by offering a gloss on<br />

each of these tenets in turn.<br />

The modernist project of making progress by regulating<br />

human conduct through instrumental reason has been unmasked<br />

and discredited<br />

It is important to notice that this tenet is actually a very<br />

short story. It expresses in telegraphic form a narrative of<br />

modernity and postmodernity which is recounted in the opening<br />

chapters of Postmodern Ethics. Perhaps the best way of introducing<br />

Bauman’s understanding of morality is to retell the story<br />

he recounts in these chapters in an abbreviated form.<br />

Modernity, according to Bauman, began with the dawning<br />

of Renaissance humanism, when western society cast off the<br />

shackles of an oppressive feudal, monarchical and ecclesiastical<br />

hegemony (22, 23). In the name of critical reason, the spurious<br />

authority of such institutions as the Church and the feudal system<br />

was challenged by the philosophes (25). Having emancipated<br />

themselves from clerical and monarchical domination, the<br />

thinkers of the Enlightenment set out to construct a new system<br />

of ethical and political authority based on their understanding<br />

of human nature (25). This newfound freedom was not, however,<br />

enjoyed by all: a “great schism” (23) opened between the enlightened<br />

élite and the uneducated and turbulent masses (23). In<br />

the course of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, teachers<br />

and legislators were assigned the task of formulating and promulgating<br />

the new codes which were to replace those of feudalism<br />

(27). In the absence of clerical authority, these codes and<br />

practices were to be based on the authority of reason itself.<br />

From then on, people would be good because they would see


CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT OF POSTMODERNISM?... 241<br />

that it is reasonable to be good, that is to say, they would be convinced<br />

that being good corresponded to their own interests and<br />

amour propre (27). Translated into the social and political realities<br />

of modern life this meant the production and imposition of<br />

laws which were to promote the good of all and ensure permanent<br />

stability and security (28). In the course of time, however,<br />

the modern state took on increasingly oppressive forms, often<br />

degenerating into colonialism and totalitarianism and thus ending<br />

up in contradiction with its own professed ideals.<br />

In Bauman’s narrative, it is at this point that postmodernist<br />

thought offers an alternative to the illusions of modernism, not<br />

least in the sphere of ethics. It is only in comparatively recent<br />

times, continues Bauman, that we have been able to see through<br />

the illusions of the project of modernity and challenge the new<br />

hegemony of reason and of the State:<br />

Postmodernity, one may say, is modernity without illusions (the<br />

obverse of which is that modernity is postmodernity refusing to accept<br />

its own truth). [...] The truth in question is that the ‘messiness’<br />

will stay whatever we do or know, that the little orders and ‘systems’<br />

we carve out in the world are brittle, until-further-notice, and as arbitrary<br />

and in the end contingent as their alternatives.(33)<br />

Like other postmodern authors, Bauman is quick to point<br />

out that the “post-” involved in postmodernism is not a merely<br />

chronological specification (10). It is rather a predominantly<br />

qualitative specification: postmodernism does not just look back<br />

at modernism, it looks down on it! To be postmodern is to locate<br />

oneself chronologically and qualitatively in a narrative which recounts<br />

modernism, it is to consider oneself among those who<br />

have passed beyond a wrongheaded vision of the world (“we<br />

now know...” is one of Bauman’s favourite phrases) and are in a<br />

position to see what was wrong with modernity.<br />

Bauman goes on to praise some of the characteristics of<br />

contemporary culture which, in his view, postmodernism has<br />

brought in its train. The abortive modernist effort to disenchant<br />

the world has been defeated and we are enjoying a new appreciation<br />

of mystery; passions and spontaneous human inclinations<br />

(107), the constituents of true personalism, have been rehabilitated<br />

after suffering under modernist suspicions and repression


242 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

(34); the destructive effects of technology on the social order<br />

have been exposed and are being challenged (201).<br />

The postmodern perspective consists in the conviction that<br />

not only did the modernist project fail but that it had to fail. In<br />

this perspective the history of the modern world, particularly in<br />

terms of the expansion of the State, the growth of colonial empires<br />

and the emergence of the various totalitarian systems, is<br />

reread as the story of a destructive form of civilization which<br />

should not be spread. In this sense postmodernism can be seen<br />

to include a powerful ethical critique of modernity.<br />

Spontaneous moral impulse is the only source of morality<br />

If the first tenet attempts to encapsulate the broad narrative<br />

of modernity as presented by Bauman, this second tenet expresses<br />

his moral vision in a more specific manner: it represents,<br />

that is, a conclusion about morality which Bauman arrives at in<br />

the light of the story just told.<br />

Bauman’s conclusion is based on a radical distinction he<br />

perceives between a discredited, systematic, universalist, foundationalist,<br />

heteronomous ethics (21, 60, 61) and a modest,<br />

spontaneous, responsible and autonomous morality (12, 32, 71).<br />

The reasons for his rejection of heteronomous ethics, already intimated<br />

in the narration of modernity, are developed by Bauman<br />

in his discussion of “elusive universality” and “elusive foundations”.<br />

The philosopher’s preoccupation with universals, he suggests,<br />

is a reflection of the legislator’s project of universalization.<br />

In other words, Bauman wishes to “unmask” the quest for universals<br />

in philosophy as a furtive collusion with the political authority<br />

of the modern State (38). In ethical terms, universal laws<br />

are presented as valid for every reasonable creature but in fact<br />

serve primarily as legitimizations of local political interests (42).<br />

With the demise of the claims of the modern State to regulate<br />

moral life, Bauman notes a developing tendency among<br />

“communitarians” to <strong>propos</strong>e norms not in the name of humanity<br />

but rather in the name of some particular grouping (44), defined<br />

by some specific characteristic (religion, gender, sexual<br />

orientation etc.).<br />

Bauman considers such claims a variation of the spurious


CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT OF POSTMODERNISM?... 243<br />

claims of the ethical systems of modernity in that they attempt<br />

to substitute “heteronomous ethical duty” for “autonomous<br />

moral responsibility.” All such attempts to universalize, he<br />

maintains, are inherently depersonalizing in that they reduce<br />

the human individual to an interchangeable entity (47) and<br />

thereby deny or curtail “individual moral discretion.”<br />

Over against this unacceptable attempt to control human<br />

behaviour through imposed ethical codes, Bauman <strong>propos</strong>es a<br />

concept of morality as “moral condition” and “moral impulse”.<br />

This condition begins where ethics ends. To be universalizable,<br />

that is to be expressable in terms of rules, morality would have<br />

to be “calculable” in the sense that it would involve purpose (54),<br />

reciprocity (56) and contractuality (58). Following Levinas, Bauman<br />

conceives of morality as being intrinsically uncodifiable because<br />

the moral subject is not interchangeable (the moral “we”<br />

is not the plural of “I”). The moral subject must respond to the<br />

Other not on the basis of rules formulated elsewhere but as a<br />

unique and irreplaceable individual prompted by his or here<br />

own moral impulse (86) which is of a thoroughly personal nature<br />

(60). The obligations of the moral subject are addressed “to<br />

me and to me only”(51) and my moral responsibility is not universalizable.<br />

A moral relationship is thus essentially asymmetrical<br />

and non-reciprocal, at least at the outset. In fact, the test of<br />

moral authenticity is the genuinely autonomous nature of any<br />

moral act: if it has been decided by others, or if it is calculated<br />

and reasoned, then it is not really a moral act at all (123).<br />

Morality, unlike ethics, Bauman argues, is inherently and<br />

profoundly ambivalent (42) and cannot be contained in the neat<br />

categories of modernist ethical thought. It is not the product of<br />

any code, it is not subject to being guided by rules, it is not<br />

founded on anything but itself, it is not a calculation or a purpose,<br />

but rather a spontaneous, pristine, brute fact. It does not<br />

alter the messiness and ambivalence of everyday life (78), but<br />

can nonetheless be discerned as a stubbornly perduring reality.<br />

It is only by replacing the modernist obsession with foundations<br />

and universals with the humble stone of moral impulse that we<br />

can rightly understand morality. Consequently morality is the<br />

realm of “perpetual and irreparable anomie” which defies all social<br />

regulation of an ethical kind.<br />

Despite these sweeping claims, Bauman insists that he does


244 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

not wish to join with those sceptics who celebrate the demise of<br />

any moral vision or value. Those who live in postmodern culture<br />

must simply accept the ambivalence inherent in morality and<br />

acknowledge the consequent impossibility of building a coherent<br />

ethical system, much less of imposing it.<br />

The moral self is constituted by its responsibility for the<br />

Other<br />

Having abandoned most of the categories in which ethics is<br />

traditionally construed (rationality, purpose, judgement, foundations<br />

and universality) Bauman proceeds to elaborate upon<br />

his conception of “morality beyond ethics”. This is based on the<br />

idea of “the moral self” construed in contradistinction to the calculating,<br />

rational, ethical self. The moral self is the unique, personal,<br />

autonomous being who precedes all reasoning, calculation<br />

and regulation and who transcends all roles imposed by heteronomous<br />

authorities. The morality of the moral self is precisely<br />

what remains when all such ethical considerations are<br />

eliminated or what is already there before they arise.<br />

This self is constituted by the spontaneous response to the<br />

Other as Other. To be a moral self is to accept the call of the Other,<br />

to acknowledge the Other as Face and therefore invested with<br />

an irreplaceable authority (75). It is precisely this response to<br />

the command of the Other which makes the moral subject an individual.<br />

The moral self is not just “with” the Other, but “for” the<br />

Other in that it recognises itself as responsible for the Other as<br />

Face, that is as a unique and mysterious presence rather than as<br />

an interchangeable social unit. In order to be true to his own declared<br />

principles, Bauman’s moral self must precede ontology<br />

(72), since ontology already implies reasoning, calculation and<br />

regulation. The moral self is located in a space “better” than being,<br />

in that being for is superior to simply being with. To be moral<br />

just is to be able to hear this command and respond to it (72).<br />

Thus far Bauman’s attempt to articulate his view of morality.<br />

In accordance with the plan outlined above, we will now proceed<br />

to study the very different vision of morality to be gleaned<br />

from Fides et ratio. Having done so it will be possible to revisit


CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT OF POSTMODERNISM?... 245<br />

these key themes of postmodern ethics and articulate a critique<br />

of them from the point of view of Catholic ethical thought.<br />

Morality according to Fides et ratio<br />

The subject of Fides et ratio, as noted above, is a good deal<br />

wider than the question of morality in that it treats the entire<br />

question of the relationship between faith and reason. It must be<br />

stressed, however, that the understanding of morality represented<br />

in the encyclical is fully integrated into, and inseparable<br />

from, a certain vision of the appropriate relationship between<br />

theology and philosophy. It would be a grave mistake to imagine<br />

that one could grasp the moral import of this encyclical by simply<br />

extracting the various sections in which the theme of ethics<br />

is explicitly broached. While it is beyond the purpose of this article<br />

to study the broader questions in depth, the only way to understand<br />

adequately the vision of morality being <strong>propos</strong>ed is to<br />

take note of the philosophical and theological context in which<br />

it is set.<br />

The key features of the teaching of Fides et ratio which have<br />

direct import for the understanding of morality presented in the<br />

encyclical might be articulated under the following major<br />

themes:<br />

a. reason is the key natural resource in the human quest for<br />

meaning<br />

b. the ultimate truth about human life is revealed in Christ<br />

c. the truth revealed in faith and the truth perceived by reason<br />

are not alone compatible but ultimately complementary<br />

Reason is the key natural resource in the human quest<br />

for meaning<br />

Although, in general, Fides et ratio could be described as expository<br />

and didactic in style, it includes a strong element of<br />

narration. This is particularly in evidence in the treatment of Sacred<br />

Scripture, the Fathers and Tradition, but is also present in<br />

the brief accounts of the history of human philosophical en-


246 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

deavour. It is worth reconstructing this “brief history of reason”<br />

which underlies the main argument of the encyclical.<br />

Stimulated by a native sense of wonder (§ 4) at the marvels of<br />

the created world, the human being, from earliest times, has posed<br />

himself (herself) questions about the ultimate meaning of his own<br />

existence and that of the world (§§1, 64). Human beings, in fact, are<br />

naturally philosophical in that they have an innate and profound<br />

desire for meaning. Faced with the perennial and lacerating questions<br />

of suffering, death and moral evil, they have searched relentlessly<br />

all through history for an overarching explanation of human<br />

life in which they can have confidence and trust (§ 26).<br />

At different times and in diverse cultures this natural tendency<br />

to reflect has taken on more rigorous and systematic<br />

forms which have issued in formal philosophical reflection (§ 7).<br />

Such reflection has been possible because of the remarkable capacity<br />

of the human individual not only to know, but also to<br />

know that he knows. A rigorous use of this capacity has allowed<br />

human beings progressively to establish laws of coherence and<br />

criteria of truth for their rational reflection. A practical demonstration<br />

of this universal capacity of reason to be critically selfreflective<br />

is seen in the convergence of various cultures in the establishment<br />

of certain commonly shared standards and moral<br />

norms (§§ 2, 4)<br />

Fides et ratio proceeds to recount some of the influences of<br />

contemporary cultural trends on this perennial quest for meaning.<br />

In so far as contemporary culture is thought of as modern, a number<br />

of alarming tendencies are noted: a disproportionate focus on<br />

the limitations and conditions of human subjectivity at the expense<br />

of the more ultimate questions (§ 5), the reduction of the<br />

role of reason to an instrumental and technical level (§ 47), the<br />

separation of philosophy and theology (§ 45 ), the excessive claims<br />

of autonomy on the part of individual reason (§ 80). While these<br />

negative aspects are preponderant, some positive developments<br />

are noted in terms of a deeper understanding of human beings and<br />

an improved respect for their dignity (§§ 38, 76).<br />

In more recent times, the encyclical continues, the culture in<br />

which we live has taken on many of the characteristics of “postmodernity”(§<br />

91). The alarming influences of this tendency are<br />

even more destructive: a loss of faith in the capacity of reason<br />

(§§ 5, 6), the fragmentary and sectorial nature of knowledge


CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT OF POSTMODERNISM?... 247<br />

(§§ 5, 85), a broad cultural tendency toward scepticism, nihilism<br />

and wilful pluralism (§§ 5, 90), the reduction of the quest for<br />

meaning to a provisional, ephemeral quest (§ 91) and so forth.<br />

In short, human reason, having made some progress<br />

through the centuries in the acquisition of truth, has suffered in<br />

modern times under the excesses of modern critical rationalism<br />

and is currently being exposed to the even more devastating assault<br />

of postmodern nihilism (§ 9).<br />

It is precisely in this cultural context, as a response to this history,<br />

that the encyclical wishes to affirm and encourage the role<br />

of reason in the quest for the meaning of human existence. There<br />

are numerous texts in which the value and dignity of this fundamental<br />

natural resource are affirmed: reason opens up the horizon<br />

of “ personal self-consciousness”(§ 1); if employed rightly, it<br />

is capable of grasping the first principles of truth (§§ 4, 49); of its<br />

own nature, it is capable of recognising the transcendent nature<br />

of truth (§ 49); it can and should aspire to the intelligible articulation<br />

of the fundamental and universal truths at the level of<br />

metaphysics and of theology (§§ 20, 77 ). Not least, reason is indispensable<br />

in guiding the human being in making moral choice:<br />

No less important than research in the theoretical field is research<br />

in the practical field – by which I mean the search for truth<br />

which looks to the good which is to be performed. In acting ethically,<br />

according to a free and rightly tuned will, the human person<br />

sets foot upon the path to happiness and moves towards perfection.<br />

(§ 25)<br />

If we recall the destructive and disorientating tendencies of<br />

modern and postmodern culture, the vital importance of reason<br />

in guiding the human quest for the good is all the more<br />

clear. Aware of its own dignity, reason will not limit itself to<br />

functional and technical matters but open itself to the deeper<br />

truths of its own being and of transcendence. The whole argument<br />

of Fides et ratio hinges upon the capacity of human reason<br />

to know the truth, both at a speculative and at a practical<br />

level. Only in the horizon of universal and objective truth can<br />

the questions of the good and the right be adequately posed<br />

and rightly answered. If reason can grasp the “truth of values”<br />

(§ 25), then this truth will prevent it falling victim to the mod-


248 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

ernist illusion of a completely self-founding autonomy or the<br />

postmodern reduction of all moral good to the ephemeral and<br />

the relative.<br />

The ultimate truth about human existence is revealed in<br />

Christ<br />

Against this background image of a needful and searching<br />

human being, open to the truth which reason can discover, the<br />

encyclical gradually articulates its central message: the ultimate<br />

and fundamental answer to the human quest for meaning is to<br />

be found in Revelation. Given all that has just been said about<br />

the importance of reason, this affirmation constitutes an audacious<br />

claim, which requires some justification and explanation.<br />

The fundamental justification of such a claim is that the author<br />

of this truth is not the speculative power of the human<br />

mind but God. The human mind seizes the truths of Revelation<br />

not by dint of its own power (§§ 7, 15) but in faith, by the grace<br />

of the Spirit (§§ 15, 61). Fides et ratio includes extensive narrative<br />

accounts of the ways in which God has revealed Himself in<br />

history and of the culmination of that Revelation in Christ. Such<br />

affirmations clearly ascribe a certain priority to Revelation with<br />

respect to reason, without denying the legitimate and important<br />

role of this later. This primacy of Revelation is articulated in<br />

terms of the two orders of consciousness (natural and supernatural),<br />

the saving purpose of Revelation, the authority of God as<br />

one who reveals Himself in history, obedience as the appropriate<br />

response and the role of the Church as the servant of the revealed<br />

truths of faith. The conclusion of the encyclical is that<br />

without recourse to faith, without the message of salvation in<br />

Christ, our human condition would remain an “insoluble enigma”(§<br />

12) which could easily conduce to despair.<br />

It is only within this context of faith in the Word of God as<br />

the source of revealed truth that the vision of morality presented<br />

in Fides et ratio can be understood. Germane to this vision of<br />

faith is the conviction that human beings are in need of salvation,<br />

that their natural powers of knowing the truth have been<br />

damaged through sin and that the highest good for human beings<br />

is to be more fully united with God, the Supreme good (§


CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT OF POSTMODERNISM?... 249<br />

41). This being so, the act of faith, by which the human being<br />

freely assents to the truth of Revelation, and entrusts himself to<br />

God (§ 33) is itself a profoundly moral decision:<br />

This is why the Church has always considered the act of entrusting<br />

oneself to God to be a moment of fundamental decision<br />

which engages the whole person. In that act, the intellect and the<br />

will display their spiritual nature, enabling the subject to act in a<br />

way which realizes personal freedom to the full. [...] It is not just<br />

that freedom is part of the act of faith: it is absolutely required. Indeed,<br />

it is faith that allows individuals to give consummate expression<br />

to their own freedom. Put differently, freedom is not realized in<br />

decisions made against God. For how could it be an exercise of true<br />

freedom to refuse to be open to the very reality which enables our<br />

self-realization? Men and women can accomplish no more important<br />

act in their lives than the act of faith; it is here that freedom<br />

reaches the certainty of truth and chooses to live in that truth. (§ 13)<br />

Fides et ratio thus <strong>propos</strong>es that the truth of Revelation,<br />

freely embraced in faith, can serve as a point of departure and a<br />

point of orientation for reason in its quest for meaning (§ 6). The<br />

ultimate and fundamental nature of revealed truth should inspire<br />

and reassure reason in its endeavour to confront the ultimate<br />

questions of life, particularly in a cultural context which<br />

tends to be marked by doubt and suspicion. The <strong>propos</strong>al of the<br />

encyclical at the level of ethical theory is that, assisted by the<br />

truth of faith, reason should aspire to develop a metaphysic of<br />

the good in the sense of a comprehensive, objective and universal<br />

understanding of who human beings are and what is good<br />

for them (§§ 36, 98, 105).<br />

The truth of faith and the truth of reason are not alone<br />

compatible but complementary<br />

In the Introduction to Fides et ratio, faith and reason are depicted<br />

graphically as the “two wings” upon which the human<br />

spirit raises itself up in search of the truth. In the course of the<br />

encyclical, the respective qualities and competencies of faith and<br />

reason are treated in some detail. While insisting on a legitimate


250 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

distinction, the encyclical is at pains to point out that this does<br />

not mean that there is a fundamental conflict or competition between<br />

the two.<br />

On the contrary, a harmonious relationship between faith<br />

and reason is presented in the form of a circularity within which<br />

reason can investigate, by means of its own resources and methods,<br />

the truth of Revelation affirmed by faith:<br />

In the light of these considerations, the relationship between<br />

theology and philosophy is best construed as a circle. Theology’s<br />

source and starting-point must always be the word of God revealed<br />

in history, while its final goal will be an understanding of that word<br />

which increases with each passing generation. Yet, since God’s<br />

word is Truth (cf. Jn 17:17), the human search for truth – philosophy,<br />

pursued in keeping with its own rules – can only help to understand<br />

God’s word better. [...] This circular relationship with the<br />

word of God leaves philosophy enriched, because reason discovers<br />

new and unsuspected horizons. (73)<br />

The underlying principle here is that the truth is one (§§ 34,<br />

53, 71), both in the sense that what is true must be true everywhere<br />

and necessarily, but also in the sense that the ultimate<br />

truths of faith cannot contradict the truths of reason (§§ 27, 34,<br />

51) and that human beings need some unitary, definitive explanation<br />

as the foundation of their thought and action (§ 27).<br />

Within this fundamental unity, complementary functions<br />

can be discerned. Reason is necessary both in order to receive<br />

the revealed message, auditus fidei, and in order to articulate the<br />

experience of faith, intellectus fidei (§ 65). When this later takes<br />

the form of a systematic and organic presentation, it needs philosophy<br />

in order to ensure its own internal intelligibility and coherence.<br />

In this sense we can speak of the need for philosophical<br />

mediation (§ 69) of the faith. At the same time faith helps<br />

reason not to become too narrow or too presumptuous, it both<br />

expands the horizons of enquiry and tempers the pride of the intellect.<br />

This complementarity of faith and reason has major implications<br />

for the understanding of morality presented in the encyclical.<br />

The point of departure of any such reflection is the acceptance,<br />

in faith, of the Revelation in Christ of God as the


CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT OF POSTMODERNISM?... 251<br />

Supreme Good (§ 57). The goodness of God is therefore both the<br />

ultimate horizon in which the goodness of human actions is to<br />

be discerned and the goal to which they aspire. Right reason<br />

guides the human being in the choice of particular actions<br />

which will lead to a life in conformity with the truth of Revelation.<br />

Within this schema the false autonomy of reason which<br />

leads to rationalism and possibly totalitarianism is replaced by<br />

the free choice of the human being to obey, in trust, the one authority<br />

of the truth (§ 79).<br />

Over against this account of how things should be the encyclical<br />

presents a description of the “nefarious separation” by<br />

which reason has assumed an illegitimate and destructive autonomy<br />

(§ 80). Cut off from the guidance and inspiration of the<br />

truths of faith, reason slips into various forms of aberration,<br />

most notably that of nihilism (§§ 90,98). This is construed as the<br />

denial that any universal truth can be known or that any opinion<br />

is of more value than another. Such a nihilistic stance within<br />

philosophy is thus an example of the kind of “presuppositions<br />

and conclusions” which are incompatible with christian faith<br />

(§ 50).<br />

The encyclical specifically rejects a concept of truth as consensus<br />

and the utilitarian and pragmatic modes of ethical thinking<br />

which follow from this:<br />

In brief, there are signs of a widespread distrust of universal<br />

and absolute statements, especially among those who think that<br />

truth is born of consensus and not of a consonance between intellect<br />

and objective reality. (§ 56)<br />

The ultimate expression of the harmony between faith and<br />

reason finds expression in such a science as moral theology. In<br />

view of the particular challenges presented by postmodern culture,<br />

the primary call has to be the production of a “metaphysic<br />

of the good” based on a recognition of the truth of Revelation<br />

and the truth of reason (§§ 67, 68, 98). Only such a vision of the<br />

good will be able to withstand the pressures of subjectivist, utilitarian<br />

and pragmatist ethics.<br />

Thus far our attempt to articulate the moral import of the<br />

teaching of Fides et ratio.


252 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

It is beyond the scope of this piece to enter into the profound<br />

and complex issues which this teaching raises both at an epistemological<br />

and theological level. 4 In the context of this article, the<br />

teaching of the encyclical as it pertains to ethics is intended to<br />

serve as a point of reference in the process of evaluating the vision<br />

of morality presented by Bauman. It is to this task that we<br />

now turn.<br />

Critical observations on Bauman’s position in the light<br />

of Fides et ratio<br />

It is abundantly clear from these two contrasting visions of<br />

morality that the differences between postmodernism and<br />

Catholicism on this score, at least as represented by Zygmunt<br />

Bauman and John Paul II, are very pronounced. We are confronted<br />

here not simply with differing opinions on specific<br />

moral questions, but with radically diverse ways of understanding<br />

morality itself. One might say that we are dealing with a<br />

metaethical rather than an ethical divergence. In this final section<br />

we will attempt to highlight and analyse some of the major<br />

aspects of Bauman’s thought which account for this stark contrast.<br />

A convenient way of arranging these observations will be<br />

to revisit the three tenets in which Bauman’s vision was originally<br />

articulated and note the main divergences with the<br />

Catholic position.<br />

The first of these tenets was: “The modernist project of making<br />

progress by regulating human conduct through the use of instrumental<br />

reason has been discredited”. As it stands, there is no<br />

patent contradiction between this tenet and the vision presented<br />

in Fides et ratio. One might even argue that there is a certain degree<br />

of convergence in so far as both Bauman and the encyclical<br />

express a negative judgement on the excessive rationalism of<br />

modernity. The idea that human technology and bureaucracy<br />

4 For a series of interesting current articles on the broader philosophical<br />

and theological issues raised by Fides et ratio see: Revista Eclesiástica<br />

Brasileira, Volume LIX, Fasc. 233, Março 1999, 30-66; Rivista di teologia<br />

morale 121 (1) gennaio-marzo 1999, 3-61.


CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT OF POSTMODERNISM?... 253<br />

are adequate to the task of organizing society in a just manner<br />

for the benefit of all is rejected in both texts. Furthermore both<br />

texts show an awareness of the way in which an excessive rationalism<br />

has been responsible for the establishment of totalitarian<br />

power systems. 5<br />

Such convergences of judgement, while interesting in their<br />

own right, prove to be of secondary importance relative to the<br />

divergences which emerge if one analyses the grounds upon<br />

which these judgements are based and the alternatives which<br />

are <strong>propos</strong>ed. Bauman’s conclusion, as we saw above, is to drastically<br />

reduce our expectations of human reason, abandon all illusions<br />

of universality and foundations in ethics and accept that<br />

morality is chaotic, ambivalent and sporadic. Such a stance is<br />

radically incompatible with the Catholic vision. It would represent,<br />

in fact, an instance of what Fides et ratio calls the kind of<br />

thought which encourages a “distrust” of reason and undermines<br />

confidence in the ability of human beings to discover the<br />

truth about themselves and about what is good for them. While<br />

sharing the judgement that modernity is excessively rationalistic,<br />

Fides et ratio <strong>propos</strong>es that reason has a legitimate and indispensable<br />

role in the moral life. The alternative to the approach<br />

of modernity is not a nihilistic abandonment of all confidence<br />

in reason, but a more moderate role for reason, which is<br />

open to the mystery of transcendence and has the humility to<br />

learn from other sources.<br />

The difference between Bauman and John Paul II as regards<br />

this first tenet, therefore, consists not in the critique of the excessive<br />

rationalism of modernity, on which point there is some<br />

convergence, but rather in the role reason is understood to play<br />

in ethics. We will examine this point more closely in our study<br />

of the second tenet, but it is important to note that this tenet is<br />

based on two fundamentally different ways of reading history.<br />

One way of expressing this would be to say that the two visions<br />

of morality have their roots in the different narratives examined<br />

above. The narrative within which John Paul II <strong>propos</strong>-<br />

5 If we interpret the relevant sections of Fides et ratio in the context of<br />

the social encyclicals of John Paul II this point is all the more obvious.


254 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

es his vision is none other than the history of Western culture<br />

and the history of salvation. From within these intertwined histories<br />

the Pope believes it is possible to arrive at a metaphysics<br />

of goodness which can provide the necessary objectivity and<br />

foundations for a contemporary morality.<br />

It we compare Bauman’s narrative with this one, a number<br />

of factors emerge which help us understand why his vision of<br />

morality is so different from that of Fides et ratio. One of the<br />

most obvious of these is the comparative brevity of Bauman’s<br />

narrative. At times he writes as if ethics, and indeed the world in<br />

general, began with modernity. There is scant reference to the<br />

centuries of moral reflection which precede the Enlightenment.<br />

A second characteristic of his narrative is the manner in<br />

which it divides history into epochs, most particularly those of<br />

modernity and postmodernity. Like many postmodernist authors,<br />

Bauman’s thought is defined in terms of what he wishes<br />

to reject, that is to say modernity. He does not explicitly suggest<br />

that in 1789, or 1871, or 1918, or 1945, or 1968 the world, or<br />

even the “western world”, suddenly stopped being modern and<br />

became postmodern. While avoiding such a preposterously<br />

crude idea, he does nonetheless suggest that we have moved into<br />

a new form of culture called postmodernity, without ever explaining<br />

what has happened to modernity, not to mention those<br />

forms of culture which existed before modernity. The primary<br />

problem here is not simply the vague chronological and thematic<br />

parameters but the reduction of history to a succession of<br />

epochs, which does not do justice to the complex relationship<br />

between past and present. Finally, we may note in passing the<br />

stridently “secular” nature of Bauman’s narrative. As John Milbank<br />

6 has argued so forcefully, the option of narrating history in<br />

terms of secular reason is not a neutral, self-evident and “objective”<br />

choice, but is itself a form of rationality which will shape<br />

and often predetermine the course of one’s narrative.<br />

As regards the first tenet, therefore, there is a limited convergence<br />

between Bauman and John Paul II on the excesses of<br />

5 MILBANK, J. Theology and Social Theory, Beyond Secular Reason. (Oxford:<br />

Blackwell Publishers, 1990).


CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT OF POSTMODERNISM?... 255<br />

rationalism, but a radical divergence on the role than reason<br />

should play in morality. If John Paul II disagrees with some of<br />

the excesses of modernity he is even more dubious about the<br />

kind of scepticism which leads to a total distrust of reason.<br />

Hence the irony of those passages in which the Pontiff of the<br />

Catholic Church exhorts philosophers to take courage and have<br />

confidence in the key resource of their science.<br />

The second tenet in which Bauman’s vision was articulated<br />

reads “Spontaneous moral impulse is the only source of morality”.<br />

Here the divergence with Fides et ratio becomes categorical and<br />

diametrical in that what Bauman is <strong>propos</strong>ing negates the possibility<br />

of ethics as understood in the encyclical. As we have<br />

seen, the Catholic vision of morality hinges on an acknowledgement<br />

of the truth and a realization of one’s autonomy by obedience<br />

to the truth about what is good. The two central themes in<br />

Bauman’s position which deny this possibility are his disassociation<br />

of morality and ethics and the idea of moral ambivalence.<br />

In his account of morality Bauman ascribes a kind of messianic<br />

role to “postmodern ethics” in that it saves and liberates<br />

people from the strictures of the ethics of modernity. The agenda<br />

here is again set by modernism, most obviously by the efforts<br />

of natural law theorists to establish the foundations of morality<br />

in nature or in history and by Kant’s effort to construct an ethics<br />

which can be universalized. It is important to notice that Bauman<br />

does not refute these theories but simply takes it for granted<br />

that they have been surpassed. He then goes on to debunk not<br />

natural law or the categorical imperative, but the very idea of<br />

foundations and universals, indeed the very idea of ethics. His<br />

attempt to separate ethics and morality is simplistic in itself and<br />

becomes highly tendentious when he seeks to set up an autonomous<br />

postmodern morality against a heteronomous ethics.<br />

This is to move too quickly from a partly justified critique of excessive<br />

codification in modernist ethics to a rejection of all<br />

codes and an identification of morality as that which lies beyond,<br />

or comes before, all codes. Operating on the presupposition<br />

that morality cannot be expressed in a code, he presents a<br />

postmodern morality as a kind of surrogate ethics. It is one thing<br />

to acknowledge the existence of a variety of codes, it is a second<br />

thing to induce from this fact that there are no standards of<br />

judgement between the codes and it is a third, and much more


256 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

serious thing, to say that morality is precisely no code.<br />

Perhaps the key word in Bauman’s ethical vocabulary is<br />

“ambivalent”. His use of this concept is at times quite equivocal.<br />

It not exactly a mind-blowing revelation to observe that human<br />

beings are neither simply bad nor simply good, but rather<br />

morally “ambivalent”. In so far as this phrase denotes this fact it<br />

states an important, if rather obvious, truth. But in order to be<br />

able to say even this, some measure of assessment, judgement<br />

and evaluation is necessary. It is one thing to acknowledge that<br />

human beings sometimes do what is good and sometimes do<br />

what is bad, it is quite another to conclude from this that they<br />

do not or cannot know what is good or bad. It is perfectly possible<br />

to acknowledge the moral ambivalence of human conduct, in<br />

the sense of acknowledging de facto that people do right and<br />

wrong, without accepting that morality is inherently ambivalent<br />

in the sense that Bauman suggests.<br />

As regards the second of the tenets, therefore, it can only be<br />

concluded that Bauman deludes himself in thinking that his<br />

“spontaneous morality” is an alternative to ethics. Ethical theories<br />

are distinguished from one another by the way they conceive<br />

of the good. Bauman’s <strong>propos</strong>al that the human good is a<br />

matter of spontaneous and ambivalent impulse is one theory<br />

among others, not an alternative to theory. Varieties of moral<br />

scepticism, relativism and nihilism are not peculiar to postmodern<br />

culture but have accompanied moral reflection from the earliest<br />

times. It may be true that they are more in evidence in contemporary<br />

culture than ever before, but this is to describe contemporary<br />

culture not to create a new ethical theory.<br />

The third tenet formulated above reads “The moral self is<br />

constituted by its responsibility for the Other”. As with the first<br />

tenet, there is nothing immediately and obviously objectionable<br />

in this statement from the point of view of a Catholic ethical vision.<br />

Indeed, Fides et ratio reminds us that a good deal of the<br />

personalist heritage of Western culture is owed to the prominence<br />

given to this theme by Christian theology. If this tenet is<br />

understood as emphasizing the centrality of altruism for ethics,<br />

as construing the human being as inherently social and only<br />

conceivable in relation to others and as stressing the mystery of<br />

personhood, then it can be said to converge with the christian<br />

ethical vision. It might be thought of as one of those germs of


truth which the encyclical acknowledges to be present in otherwise<br />

erroneous philosophical theories.<br />

Read, however, in the context of Bauman’s broader theory it<br />

is clear that the tenet could be interpreted as saying much more<br />

than what has just been indicated. Divergences emerge if, for instance,<br />

as Bauman clearly intends, the “moral self” does not include<br />

the capacity to reason, the capacity to evaluate one’s own<br />

actions relative to some objective standards of truth and goodness<br />

and the capacity to freely commit oneself to the obedience<br />

of an ethical code which one has not oneself formulated.<br />

Conclusion<br />

CAN ANYTHING GOOD COME OUT OF POSTMODERNISM?... 257<br />

There seems to be little doubt that, measured against such a<br />

vision of morality as we find in Fides et ratio, Bauman’s “postmodern<br />

ethics” proves to be quite incompatible with the mainline<br />

christian ethical tradition. Does this mean that “nothing<br />

good can come out of postmodernism”? Without denying the potentially<br />

destructive nature of this vision of morality, it is possible,<br />

by way of conclusion, to enumerate a certain number of positive<br />

aspects of a direct and indirect nature.<br />

Postmodernism, including the version of morality <strong>propos</strong>ed<br />

by Bauman, does constitute a critique of modernism. If it is true,<br />

contrary to what postmodernists believe, that the dominant cultural<br />

form is still modernity, then postmodernity can help the<br />

christian in formulating a critique of that culture.<br />

Even though Bauman’s understanding of morality proves incoherent<br />

and superficial by the standards of Catholic ethical<br />

thought, it can nonetheless be of service in describing (rather<br />

than prescribing) how considerable numbers of people live their<br />

lives in contemporary culture. The challenge to the christian,<br />

and particularly to the theologian, is then to achieve as much<br />

clarity as possible concerning the divergence between a postmodern<br />

understanding of ethics and a Catholic one. Only someone<br />

who is clear about this difference will be able to understand<br />

and possibly overcome the considerable obstacles which stand<br />

in the way of communicating a christain ethical vision in contemporary<br />

culture.<br />

Another good thing which might come out of postmod-


258 MARTIN MCKEEVER<br />

ernism is an enhanced appreciation of the way in which morality<br />

is influenced by broader cultural change, not least by changing<br />

philosophical thought. In this sense one good thing that has<br />

already come out of postmodernism is Fides et ratio itself in so<br />

far as it is an attempt to respond to the challenges of postmodernism<br />

by refining the articulation of the christian faith.<br />

—————<br />

MARTIN MCKEEVER, C.SS.R.<br />

The author is an invited professor at the Alphonsian Academy.<br />

El autor es profesor invitado en la Academia Alfonsiana.<br />

—————

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!