14.01.2014 Views

Johannes Althusius: Politica - Hubertlerch.com - HubertLerch.com

Johannes Althusius: Politica - Hubertlerch.com - HubertLerch.com

Johannes Althusius: Politica - Hubertlerch.com - HubertLerch.com

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

<strong>Althusius</strong>_0002<br />

9/10/05 4:09 PM<br />

others bring against him, as the Golden Bull of Charles IV teaches. The king of France is under the judgment of the Parliament of<br />

Paris, and the princes of the German imperium are under the judgments of other princes, of counts, or even of<br />

their counselors.<br />

62<br />

Bartolus asserts that a king also can be subjected to someone less than himself or to his equal.<br />

63<br />

Therefore,<br />

these persons— Caesar, king, and prince—are over ( praeesse) in one relationship and are under ( subesse) in another, but not<br />

over and under in the same relationship; they are, nevertheless, over and under at the same time and with reference to the<br />

same interpretation. [§ 99] The king is over and rules in those things for which he receives the power of ruling and governing,<br />

not in those things that have been reserved to the power and judgment of the ephors. He is over when he governs and<br />

administers lawfully, justly, and piously; that is, he ceases to be the administrator when he does not care what happens, but<br />

loses, squanders, and destroys, and ceases to be a living law, just as a pastor ceases to be a pastor who flays, divides, and loses<br />

his sheep.<br />

Barclay continues by developing his argument from examples. Thus he says cardinals constitute a pope above them, priests a<br />

bishop above them, and monks an abbot above them. Whence the former are inferior in power and authority, and the latter are<br />

superior. The former are devoid of the imperium and power that the latter have. [§ 100] But I say that such persons—the pope,<br />

bishop, abbot, or anyone else—can be removed for just reasons by those who constituted them, and can be deprived of their<br />

power. For what if such a pope, bishop, or abbot should be<strong>com</strong>e a heretic, or in any manner be<strong>com</strong>e unfit or untrustworthy in<br />

office? Canonical laws ( jura canonica) pronounce such persons to be restrained from the authority and administration of the office<br />

entrusted to them.<br />

64<br />

And often such persons have been deprived of their office, as history bears witness and practical experience<br />

teaches. [§ 101] For who, to the detriment of the church and to the damage and loss of man’s salvation, would long endure<br />

such unfit men, heretics, schismatics, sorcerers, incapacitated persons, those who live a shameful life and provide not at all for<br />

the functions of their office, or those who do not tend their sheep but flay them? If they lose their mind or develop another<br />

disorder of soul or body, so that henceforth they be<strong>com</strong>e altogether unfit or incapacitated, will not the church be <strong>com</strong>mitted to<br />

the government of other ministers? Or does the church so fall into their power, care, and protection that while they are living its<br />

government never can be <strong>com</strong>mitted to another? Or in emergencies is the order, authority, and power of one man—of a pope,<br />

bishop, or abbot—greater and stronger than that of the church, the cardinals, or the monks? Or is the power of one greater than<br />

the power of many? No one will maintain this. Or in these emergencies is the right of one pope, bishop, or abbot greater,<br />

stronger, and in better condition than that of all the cardinals and monks of the entire church? Nor will anyone affirm this. For<br />

whatever the right, power, and authority such ecclesiastical overseers have, it is not their property, nor do they derive it from<br />

themselves. Rather they have received it from the church, the collegium of cardinals, and the chapter of monks. Those who die<br />

or lay aside their office resign this right, power, and authority into the hands of the church, collegium, or chapter by which they<br />

were constituted. They restore this right to its owners, so that these overseers are considered to be nothing more than<br />

usufructuaries of it, and the collegia indeed to be its proprietors. [§ 102] Whence it is that the right of these overseers is<br />

temporal. On the other hand, the right of the collegia is permanent and immortal to the extent that these collegia, because of<br />

their constant succession of persons in place of those who depart, are considered to be immortal.<br />

When we consider the office and administration of kings, we find that their nature and constitution are not unlike those of<br />

ecclesiastical overseers. [§ 103] The right of a king consists in the faithful and diligent care and administration of the<br />

<strong>com</strong>monwealth entrusted to him by the people. For this reason the people transfers to him as much authority and power as it<br />

judges necessary. By the <strong>com</strong>munication, sharing, and contribution of individual persons from the people, the king be<strong>com</strong>es rich<br />

and powerful. By their counsel he be<strong>com</strong>es wise. By the aid of his subjects he excels in strength, vigor, and might. If the people<br />

denies these to the king, he again be<strong>com</strong>es weak, poor, needy, and a private person. The king holds, uses, and enjoys these<br />

riches—and this might, wisdom, and authority—as a usufructuary. When the king dies, or is denied the regal throne by any<br />

legitimate means, these rights of the king, as we have said, return to the people as to their proprietor. The people then reassigns<br />

them as it thinks wise for the good of the <strong>com</strong>monwealth. [§ 104] Therefore, the right of the king is one thing, and the right of<br />

the people is another. The former is temporal and personal; the latter is permanent. The former is the lesser; the latter is the<br />

greater. The former is a precarium given by contract to the <strong>com</strong>missioned king, and undertaken by him; the latter is an<br />

in<strong>com</strong>municable property.<br />

[§ 105] Moreover, Barclay says that as the husband who is constituted over his wife is her superior, so the king is superior to<br />

the <strong>com</strong>monwealth and realm. But I say that the superiority and power the husband has over his wife he derives from the<br />

marriage. And this is only for a time and with a condition, namely, that it lasts as long as the marriage endures, that is, as long<br />

as the marriage is not dissolved by adultery, desertion, or death. When the marriage is dissolved, every marital power he<br />

exercises over his wife is ended. Of equal seriousness with desertion is the intolerable cruelty of a husband that makes it<br />

impossible to live with him. Because of incurable cruelty, and its hazard to life and health, theologians concede a dissolution of<br />

http://oll.libertyfund.org/Home3/EBook.php?recordID=0002<br />

Page 74 of 132

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!