27.12.2012 Views

BoundedRationality_TheAdaptiveToolbox.pdf

BoundedRationality_TheAdaptiveToolbox.pdf

BoundedRationality_TheAdaptiveToolbox.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

110 Gary Klein<br />

reasonable level. The point is to find the right answer. The concept of optimization<br />

may not be meaningful for mathematics or logic, where the solution is either<br />

correct or incorrect, not optimal versus nonoptimal. Questions of fact do permit<br />

optimization (e.g., the third longest river in the world, the empty weight of a<br />

Boeing 757 aircraft) because the accuracy of the answer can be scaled.<br />

Questions of value do not permit optimization. If I have three job offers and<br />

need to select one, I cannot optimize because there is no way to demonstrate<br />

whether I have made the optimal choice. I can use some form of decision analysis<br />

to compare the options. However, methods such as multiattribute utility analysis<br />

do not address the difficulty of generating options (perhaps I should<br />

continue to seek more job offers rather than settling for these three). They do not<br />

help me find accurate values for the evaluation dimensions I select or the ratings<br />

I assign.<br />

2. The decision maker's values must be stable. For researchers such as<br />

Fischhoff (1991), Slovic (1995), and March (1978), this is a troubling require<br />

ment. If values are not stable, then the exercise of decision analysis loses much<br />

of its force. The choice made at time^ (e.g., which of three job offers to accept)<br />

will not necessarily match the choice at time,4 plus one hour. Fischhoff s reading<br />

of the data is that values are labile, rather than stable. If that is true, then one's<br />

choice will vary depending on one's mood, and, in the worst case, one's values<br />

at the end of a long session of decision analysis may depart from one's values at<br />

the beginning, calling the whole analysis into question. We might try to salvage<br />

things by suggesting that the session was successful in helping the person clarify<br />

values, but, whether or not this was true, it is not the same thing as helping the<br />

person make the optimal choice.<br />

March goes further. He is concerned about the need to generate accurate predictions<br />

of future states but is even more concerned about the stability of future<br />

tastes. Optimization assumes that tastes and values are absolute, relevant, stable,<br />

consistent, and precise. Experience suggests that these assumptions are unrealistic.<br />

The difficulty may be in the concept of "values" as decomposable elements<br />

of a decision analysis equation.<br />

Further, if we do not trust decision makers to select an option directly, without<br />

decomposition, because we do not trust these judgments, why would the<br />

smaller judgments of value for each option on each evaluation dimension be any<br />

more reliable? The advantage gained by decomposing the problem into smaller<br />

units is to reduce the cognitive complexity of the task, but this advantage may be<br />

canceled because the task of rating options on evaluation dimensions is less<br />

practiced.<br />

3. The situation must be stable. Pitz (1992) has noted that decision analysis<br />

is not suited for decisions that dynamically adapt, such as the hedge clipping described<br />

by Connolly (1988). Connolly contrasted hedge clipping, in which we<br />

make each cut on the basis of the results of the previous cut, to tree felling, in<br />

which we decide in advance how to cut down the entire tree. In practice, if

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!