27.12.2012 Views

BoundedRationality_TheAdaptiveToolbox.pdf

BoundedRationality_TheAdaptiveToolbox.pdf

BoundedRationality_TheAdaptiveToolbox.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

310 WulfAlters<br />

utility function, prospect theory explains 50% of the reduction by the concavity<br />

of the utility function, and the other 50% by rank-dependent devaluation of the<br />

lottery.<br />

Monetary equivalents of 105 binary lotteries [p, x; (IT—p),y] were investigated<br />

with/? = 1%, 10%, 20%, 50%, 80%, 90%, 99%, andx = 10000, y = 5000,<br />

1000, 500, 0, -500, -1000, -5000, -10,000, andy =-10,000, x = 5000, 1000,<br />

500,0, -500, -1000, -5000. To explain the median of the observed evaluations,<br />

the predictions of prospect theory (with the median parameters a = 0.88 and<br />

Y = 0.61 reported by Tversky and Kahneman [1992]) were worse than those of<br />

prominence theory, while both theories were about equally accurate when the<br />

probability evaluation function of prospect theory was replaced by that of prominence<br />

theory (see Albers 1998a).<br />

Two Crucial Experiments<br />

The following experiments test predictions that are uniquely devied from prominence<br />

theory. They address the main point of the theory, namely that subjects<br />

neglect the steps below the finest perceived full step. It is my intent to show that<br />

subjects — although they generally perceive these steps — neglect them when<br />

they are confronted with a task that creates a finest perceived full step cruder<br />

than these steps.<br />

Experiment 1 (new kind of preference reversal paradox): Consider the<br />

lotteries A = [1/2,5000; 1/2,-1000] and£ = [l/2,1000;l/2,0].<br />

1. Decide which of the two lotteries you would prefer.<br />

2. Then determine the certainty equivalents of both lotteries.<br />

Result: The majority of subjects prefer B to A, but evaluated higher than B.<br />

How can this be explained? Under the comparison condition, both lotteries are<br />

evaluated in a combined task. The finest perceived full step is two steps below<br />

the maximum of the absolute values of all payoffs, i.e., two steps below 5000 or<br />

1000. The values of the 50%-50% lotteries are obtained via the midpoints on the<br />

utility scales. For lottery .4, the steps are-1000, 0, 1000, 2000, 5000. Since the<br />

steps in the range of negative payoffs are counted twice, one obtains the mid<br />

point after 2.5 of 5 steps, i.e., the certainty equivalent of ^4 is 500. For Lottery B,<br />

we have the steps 0,1000. The certainty equivalent ofB is at the midpoint of this<br />

step, i.e., 500 (by linear interpolation). Thus, the two lotteries have the same values,<br />

and subjects may prefer B to A since it does not involve negative payoffs.<br />

When both lotteries are evaluated separately, they are evaluated in separate<br />

tasks, and the finest perceived full steps are determined separately. For Lottery<br />

A, the finest perceived full step does not change, since it contains the maximum<br />

absolute value of both lotteries. Its certainty equivalent is still 500. For Lottery<br />

B, the maximum absolute payoff is 1000. This gives the finest perceived full step

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!