27.12.2012 Views

BoundedRationality_TheAdaptiveToolbox.pdf

BoundedRationality_TheAdaptiveToolbox.pdf

BoundedRationality_TheAdaptiveToolbox.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

312<br />

WulfAlbers<br />

AGGREGATION OF UTILITY ON ONE DIMENSION<br />

Below we consider individual and interpersonal choice conflicts that can be described<br />

by numerical variables as payoffs of different persons under different<br />

conditions, or opinions of different persons concerning state outlays, or estimates<br />

of different persons of probabilities of events. We only consider the case<br />

that all variables of a given problem are on the same dimension. We present a<br />

collection of rules of boundedly rational aggregation of the utility of such variables.<br />

The key tool is the utility approach of prominence theory. The approach<br />

could meanwhile be successfully applied to a variety of different interpersonal<br />

conflict situations.<br />

Principles of Aggregation<br />

As standard task we consider the decision between two alternatives, A, B. The<br />

decision is performed via a preference function P(A, B\ which measures the<br />

preference of alternative^ over B.A is preferred to B, if P(A,B) > 0, mdBtoA if<br />

P(A, B) < 0; these inequations are denoted as the preference criterion. Sometimes<br />

it makes sense to split the preference criterion up into two terms of which<br />

each aggregates the arguments for one alternative as P(A, B) = F(A) -F(B\<br />

thenP^, B) > 0 is equivalent to F(A) > F(B). In two-person situations it can<br />

also make sense to split the arguments according to the persons ij as P(A,<br />

B) = P"(i) -P"(j). The function P(A, B) is constructed according to:<br />

Principles of Aggregation of Utility on One Dimension<br />

(1) utility is measured according to prominence theory<br />

(2) utility is aggregated in an additive way<br />

(3) the utilitiy of a variable has weight +1, -1, or 0<br />

(4) no variable can be selected twice<br />

(5) P(a, b) can be presented as a sum of differences of utility values<br />

The restriction to additive aggregation is surprising, since the literature offers<br />

criteria of the type (M(JC) - u(a))/(u(y) - u(b)). On the other hand, the combination<br />

of linear and logarithmic elements in the utility function 12 suggests that<br />

subjects do not distinguish relative and absolute differences, and therefore only<br />

use one kind of operator, here the addition.<br />

The restriction of weights to+1, -1, or 0, and the condition that every variable<br />

can be used at most once are formally identical to the conditions of the construe<br />

tion of numerical responses. We assume that every important attribute has nonzero<br />

weight. The dependence of this evaluation on individual judgments could<br />

be confirmed under experimental conditions. In situations where two persons<br />

For example, the step structure 0, 10, 20, 50 indicates linear shape in the range of 0,<br />

+10, +20, and logarithmic shape in the range of+10, +20, +50.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!