11.04.2013 Views

The Literary Mind.pdf

The Literary Mind.pdf

The Literary Mind.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

166 THE LITERARY MIND<br />

understandable. <strong>The</strong>re is no obvious way in which a lone grammatical person<br />

would have a direct reproductive advantage in a community whose other members<br />

are completely incapable of recognizing or parsing grammar by any means,<br />

general or special. <strong>The</strong> utterances directed at her would not be grammatical. Her<br />

own grammar would have no audience, since none of the grammatical structure<br />

she produced could be recognized by companions. Of course, her grammatical<br />

utterance could still be understood as ungrammatical communication, and she<br />

could still attribute grammar to the ungrammatical communication directed at<br />

her, and there could surely be reproductive advantage conferred by communication;<br />

but it is difficult to see that there would be any additional advantage conferred<br />

by the grammatical component.<br />

In a brief moment in their argument, Pinker and Bloom do consider explicitly<br />

the right scenario their argument needs: a grammatical community of kin.<br />

<strong>The</strong>y write, "Geschwind, among others, has wondered how a hypothetical 'beneficial'<br />

grammatical mutation could really have benefited its possessor, given that<br />

such an individual would not have been understood by less evolved compatriots.<br />

One possible answer is that any such mutation is likely to be shared by individuals<br />

who are genetically related. Because much communication is among kin, a<br />

linguistic mutant will be understood by some relatives and the resulting enhancements<br />

in information sharing will benefit each one of them relative to others who<br />

are not related." This is the only suggestion Pinker and Bloom offer of a community<br />

in which grammar is not widespread. It is still not a picture of reproductive<br />

advantage to the lone grammatical individual in a community whose other<br />

members are completely incapable of recognizing grammar by any means, presumably<br />

because Pinker and Bloom can see no such advantage.<br />

But it is not true that such a mutation is likely to be shared by individuals<br />

who are genetically related. Consider the first genetically grammatical person.<br />

By definition, none of her ancestors or older siblings is genetically grammatical.<br />

If the genetic material expressed in her minimal grammatical competence arose<br />

by mutation from her parents' genetic material, as in a copying error in making<br />

a sperm or egg, it is extraordinarily unlikely that her younger siblings would have<br />

that mutation. If it arose because error-free sexual recombination of her parents'<br />

genetic material finally put together the right package, then later siblings would<br />

receive quite different genetic packages (especially if they do not have the same<br />

two parents). <strong>The</strong>re is also the important difficulty that even if a later sibling<br />

had the right package, the first genetically grammatical infant would nonetheless<br />

still live in grammatical isolation (under Pinker and Bloom's suggestion)<br />

during the period in infancy in which she develops grammar.<br />

If evolution could think ahead, it would certainly see that producing a genetically<br />

grammatical community, even a small one, would be enormously useful

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!