11.04.2013 Views

The Literary Mind.pdf

The Literary Mind.pdf

The Literary Mind.pdf

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

86 THE LITERARY MIND<br />

and what each is good for. None of them replaces another. Meanings, in this<br />

way, are not mental objects bounded in conceptual places but rather complex<br />

operations of projecting, blending, and integrating over multiple spaces.<br />

GENERIC SPACES<br />

We have often seen that an element in one input story can have a counterpart in<br />

the other. <strong>The</strong> donkey and Shahrazad are counterparts. So are Great America II<br />

and Northern Light, the two Buddhist monks, the two paths they travel, the rain<br />

and the message, and the reaper and Death. It is not possible to blend two stories<br />

without some counterpart connections between them to guide the blending.<br />

Input stories have counterparts because they share abstract structure. Consider<br />

the boat race. <strong>The</strong>re is a frame for a voyage by boat. It contains a boat, a<br />

path, a departure point, a destination, and so on. Each of the input stories for<br />

the boat-race blend has this frame structure, which provides counterpart relations<br />

between them. Different kinds of abstract structure can be shared by two<br />

stories: category structure, frame structure, role structure, image-schematic structure,<br />

and so on. Sometimes, two inputs will share abstract structure because a<br />

conventional metaphor has established that shared structure. Sometimes, two<br />

inputs will share more than one kind of abstract structure. For example, the inputs<br />

for the riddle of the Buddhist monk share frame structure (a person walking along<br />

a path) just as the inputs for the boat-race share frame structure (a boat voyage),<br />

but there is also identity structure shared in both cases: <strong>The</strong> monk in one space<br />

counts as "identical" to the monk in the other space, and San Francisco in one<br />

space counts as "identical" to San Francisco in the other space.<br />

Now consider the expression "If I were you, I would have done it," said by<br />

a man to a woman who declined earlier to become pregnant. <strong>The</strong> two input spaces<br />

share structure: In each there is a human being, with human intentionality, possibility,<br />

and standard relations between intentionality and action. This shared<br />

structure gives counterparts: <strong>The</strong> man and the woman are counterpart human<br />

beings, even though they have different identities; their preferences are counterparts,<br />

even though those preferences are not identical; their actions are counterparts,<br />

even though their actions are not identical. In short, there is a frame structure<br />

shared by the two input spaces, and it provides counterpart relations between<br />

them.<br />

I will say that the abstract structure shared by input spaces resides in a generic<br />

space. <strong>The</strong> generic space indicates the counterpart connections between the<br />

input spaces.<br />

<strong>The</strong> central question is, is this generic space just a name for structure shared<br />

by the input spaces, or does it have an actual conceptual existence of its own?<br />

Can this abstract structure be manipulated and used in away that does not entail

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!