28.10.2014 Views

Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 9 (EISS 9 ... - CSSP - CNRS

Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 9 (EISS 9 ... - CSSP - CNRS

Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 9 (EISS 9 ... - CSSP - CNRS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

the addressee by virtue of l<strong>in</strong>guistic convention. However, this cannot be right, given that imperatives<br />

are also used with a weaker directive force <strong>in</strong> requests, pleas, warn<strong>in</strong>gs, etc. What<br />

directive uses have <strong>in</strong> common is that they are all attempts by the speaker to get the addressee<br />

to do someth<strong>in</strong>g (Searle 1975). Suppose we had an account of how this happens. Then we could<br />

construe order uses simply as attempts to get the addressee to do someth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> contexts <strong>in</strong> which<br />

the speaker happens to have authority over the addressee, where ‘authority’ means that the addressee<br />

is obligated to comply with such attempts of the speaker. Look<strong>in</strong>g at th<strong>in</strong>gs this way, it<br />

is only by extra-l<strong>in</strong>guistic circumstance that such directives sometimes create obligations.<br />

A directive utterance of an imperative (I) expresses a certa<strong>in</strong> content related to the addressee’s<br />

future actions; (II) conveys that the speaker wants the content to become reality; <strong>and</strong><br />

(III) acts as an <strong>in</strong>ducement for the addressee to br<strong>in</strong>g about the content. The imperative <strong>in</strong> (5a),<br />

<strong>in</strong>tuitively, has the overall effects <strong>in</strong> (5b).<br />

(5) a. Leave!<br />

b. (I) expresses: The addressee leaves; (content)<br />

(II) conveys that the speaker wants the addressee to leave; (speaker desire)<br />

(III) acts as an <strong>in</strong>ducement for the addressee to leave. (addressee <strong>in</strong>ducement)<br />

The content is presumably determ<strong>in</strong>ed by the system of semantic composition, 1 but what about<br />

(II) <strong>and</strong> (III)? Are they both determ<strong>in</strong>ed by l<strong>in</strong>guistic convention, or is only one of them so<br />

determ<strong>in</strong>ed, with the other aris<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> context where appropriate? In order to answer this question,<br />

we have to consider the full range of uses that imperatives can have <strong>in</strong> context, s<strong>in</strong>ce any effect<br />

that is present as a matter of l<strong>in</strong>guistic convention must be universally present.<br />

As observed by Schmerl<strong>in</strong>g (1982), imperatives have a wide range of uses go<strong>in</strong>g beyond<br />

even the extended sense of directive uses mentioned above: they can be used to merely express<br />

a wish, to permit, concede, offer or <strong>in</strong>vite, <strong>and</strong> also to give advice. We divide the uses of imperatives<br />

<strong>in</strong>to four groups, based on how they l<strong>in</strong>e up with respect to speaker desire <strong>and</strong> addressee<br />

<strong>in</strong>ducement <strong>and</strong> the k<strong>in</strong>ds of issues they raise about the proper analysis of imperatives.<br />

A l<strong>in</strong>guistic reflex of the fact that imperatives come with a variety of ‘illocutionary forces’<br />

<strong>and</strong> that utter<strong>in</strong>g them br<strong>in</strong>gs about the correspond<strong>in</strong>g k<strong>in</strong>d of speech act is that imperative<br />

utterances can be subsequently described, depend<strong>in</strong>g on the context they are uttered <strong>in</strong>, with<br />

various verbs for acts of communication. In the examples below, utterances of imperatives <strong>in</strong> (i)<br />

can be described after the fact with the correspond<strong>in</strong>g sentences <strong>in</strong> (ii).<br />

Group I: directives This group encompasses uses of imperatives that are <strong>in</strong>tended to get<br />

the addressee to do someth<strong>in</strong>g or refra<strong>in</strong> from do<strong>in</strong>g someth<strong>in</strong>g. It comprises orders, warn<strong>in</strong>gs,<br />

requests, as well as certa<strong>in</strong> k<strong>in</strong>ds of advice <strong>and</strong> pleas. The implications of speaker desire (II) <strong>and</strong><br />

of <strong>in</strong>tended addressee <strong>in</strong>ducement (III) are both present.<br />

(6) a. (i) St<strong>and</strong> at attention! (comm<strong>and</strong>)<br />

(ii) He ordered me to st<strong>and</strong> at attention.<br />

b. (i) Don’t touch the hot plate! (warn<strong>in</strong>g)<br />

(ii) He warned me not to touch the hot plate.<br />

c. (i) H<strong>and</strong> me the salt, please. (request)<br />

1 Throughout, we use ‘content’ to refer to the proposition that needs to become true for the imperative to be<br />

fulfilled. We leave it open whether the content should be identified with the denotation of the imperative, or be part<br />

of this denotation (as <strong>in</strong> Kaufmann 2012), or be derived from it (as <strong>in</strong> Portner 2005). We also set aside the question<br />

of the status of the understood second person subject.<br />

38

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!