28.10.2014 Views

Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 9 (EISS 9 ... - CSSP - CNRS

Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 9 (EISS 9 ... - CSSP - CNRS

Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics 9 (EISS 9 ... - CSSP - CNRS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

3. Imperatives as preferential attitudes<br />

In Condoravdi & Lauer 2011 we propose an account of explicit performatives that directly<br />

l<strong>in</strong>ks the illocutionary act performed by such utterances to their mean<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>and</strong> provide a straightforward<br />

answer to the question of how say<strong>in</strong>g so makes it so. Our analysis rests on the assumption<br />

that the conventional effect of assertions is to br<strong>in</strong>g about a doxastic commitment on the part<br />

of the speaker <strong>and</strong> takes explicit performative verbs to denote communicative events that br<strong>in</strong>g<br />

about speaker commitments to a belief or an <strong>in</strong>tention. We propose that the same constructs are<br />

<strong>in</strong>volved <strong>in</strong> the analysis of imperatives. We take imperatives to commit the speaker to a particular<br />

k<strong>in</strong>d of preference, 5 <strong>and</strong> to be bounded by a condition that limits his active <strong>in</strong>volvement <strong>in</strong><br />

mak<strong>in</strong>g the content true.<br />

Functional heterogeneity is captured through the <strong>in</strong>teraction of the constant mean<strong>in</strong>g of<br />

imperatives with vary<strong>in</strong>g contextual conditions. Imperatives do not create obligations as a matter<br />

of course by l<strong>in</strong>guistic convention, but give rise to obligations only <strong>in</strong>directly when the context<br />

is right.<br />

3.1. Effective preferences<br />

An agent is generally subject to a large number constra<strong>in</strong>ts <strong>and</strong> attitudes that <strong>in</strong>fluence his<br />

actions: desires, <strong>in</strong>cl<strong>in</strong>ations, personal moral codes, <strong>and</strong> obligations, to name but a few. All of<br />

these come <strong>in</strong> different degrees of importance (Condoravdi & Lauer 2011). We use preference<br />

structures, as def<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>in</strong> (28), to model ranked preferences <strong>and</strong> assume that, at any given time,<br />

an agent has a family of such structures represent<strong>in</strong>g the various sources of his preferences.<br />

(28) A preference structure relative to an <strong>in</strong>formation state W is a pair 〈P,≤〉, where P ⊆<br />

℘(W) <strong>and</strong> ≤ is a partial order on P. (Condoravdi & Lauer 2011)<br />

An agent may well have <strong>in</strong>consistent preferences, such as the simultaneous desires reported <strong>in</strong><br />

(16). However, if an agent is to act, he needs to resolve these conflicts as he cannot act on a<br />

preference for two <strong>in</strong>compatible th<strong>in</strong>gs. If the agent is to decide on a course of action, he needs<br />

to <strong>in</strong>tegrate all his preference structures <strong>in</strong>to a global set of preferences subject to a consistency<br />

constra<strong>in</strong>t, which the underly<strong>in</strong>g preferences do not necessarily obey. This is captured <strong>in</strong> the<br />

follow<strong>in</strong>g def<strong>in</strong>ition of consistency for preference structures.<br />

(29) A preference structure 〈P,≤〉 is consistent iff for any X ⊆ P, if ⋂ X = /0, there are<br />

p,q ∈ X such that p < q. 6<br />

A rational agent A at a moment (= world-time pair) w will have a dist<strong>in</strong>guished, consistent<br />

preference structure 〈 P w (A),≤ Pw (A)〉<br />

. We call this A’s effective preference structure at w. We<br />

write EP w (A, p) for ‘p is a maximal element of A’s effective preference structure at w.’ Due<br />

to the consistency requirement on effective preference structures, if p <strong>and</strong> q are believed to be<br />

<strong>in</strong>compatible, EP w (A, p) <strong>and</strong> EP w (A,q) cannot be jo<strong>in</strong>tly the case.<br />

5 In this respect, our analysis similar <strong>in</strong> spirit to the proposals by Bierwisch (1980), Wilson <strong>and</strong> Sperber (1988),<br />

<strong>and</strong> Davis (2009, 2011).<br />

6 This def<strong>in</strong>ition of consistency is a generalization of the def<strong>in</strong>ition <strong>in</strong> Condoravdi & Lauer 2011.<br />

45

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!