06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 4. Negligence St<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

Notes<br />

1. Learned H<strong>and</strong>’s formula. The so-called H<strong>and</strong> Formula for determining negligence rounds<br />

out the considerations cited in the opinions from Stone v. Bolton, <strong>and</strong> it adds an additional factor:<br />

the burden of adequate precautions. But the algebra doesn’t by itself supply all the elements<br />

needed to make the negligence inquiry. For example, to estimate the probability of the injury’s<br />

occurrence, we need to know something about the temporality of the H<strong>and</strong> Formula. Is it the<br />

probability ex ante or ex post—before or after the fact? The typical Learned H<strong>and</strong> test adopts an<br />

ex ante perspective, comparing the cost of a precaution with the risk of loss at the time the<br />

decision about whether to take the precaution in question ought to have been made. Ex post, the<br />

probability of injury is typically 100%, since we only have a torts question if there has been some<br />

injury. (Though note that we will see an ex post version of the H<strong>and</strong> Formula when we get to<br />

products liability in Chapter 9.)<br />

Another element needed to operationalize the H<strong>and</strong> Formula is to identify the kind of<br />

person making this ex ante analysis. An expert with perfect information will often come to a<br />

different conclusion than a layperson about the reasonableness of a particular course of conduct.<br />

Typically, however, the H<strong>and</strong> Formula imposes no such obligation of perfect information.<br />

Instead, it asks what a reasonable person in the position of the party whose conduct is under<br />

evaluation would have thought about the likely costs <strong>and</strong> benefits in question; in other words, it<br />

asks what values the reasonable person would have inserted into the equation.<br />

Two additional points round out our first pass at the Learned H<strong>and</strong> approach. The first is<br />

to observe that in the common law’s adversary system it is the party charging negligence—often<br />

but not always the plaintiff—who sets the agenda by identifying the precaution that the defendant<br />

allegedly ought to have taken. Judge <strong>and</strong> jury need not comb the world for precautions that might<br />

have been taken in any given situation. They need only consider precautions that the party<br />

charging negligence contends ought to have been taken. The second is that the cost-benefit<br />

calculations required by the H<strong>and</strong> formula are social cost benefit calculations, not private ones.<br />

The question is whether the social costs of the precaution at issue seemed at the time to a<br />

reasonable person in the position of the relevant party greater or less than its social benefits. We<br />

are interested in the costs <strong>and</strong> benefits to society of taking any given precaution, not merely the<br />

costs <strong>and</strong> benefits borne or captured by the decision-maker.<br />

So there we have it! Taking a deep breath we can say that the Learned H<strong>and</strong> test is an ex<br />

ante, reasonable person formula for evaluating by reference to precautions identified by the parties<br />

the social advisability of risky conduct. Whew!<br />

The test has been influential in part because, as Judge Richard Posner observed in one of<br />

his early articles, it can be read to embody an economic approach to tort law:<br />

H<strong>and</strong> was adumbrating, perhaps unwittingly, an economic meaning of negligence.<br />

Discounting (multiplying) the cost of an accident if it occurs by the probability of<br />

occurrence yields a measure of the economic benefit to be anticipated from<br />

incurring the costs necessary to prevent the accident. The cost of prevention is what<br />

H<strong>and</strong> meant by the burden of taking precautions against the accident. It may be the<br />

cost of installing safety equipment or otherwise making the activity safer. . . . If the<br />

cost of safety measures . . . exceeds the benefit in accident avoidance to be gained<br />

164

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!