06.09.2021 Views

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

Torts - Cases, Principles, and Institutions Fifth Edition, 2016a

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Witt & Tani, TCPI 4. Negligence St<strong>and</strong>ard<br />

activities whose undesirability consists only in the fact that they result in accidents<br />

<strong>and</strong> then only to the extent that people would, if they knew the costs of these<br />

accidents, prefer to abstain from the activity rather than pay those costs. . . .<br />

The question then is, Can we not deter these acts or activities more effectively than<br />

through a system of fault liability which, together with insurance, merely raises<br />

somewhat the cost to those who as an actuarial class tend to do these acts or<br />

activities? I suggest, <strong>and</strong> it is not a particularly original suggestion, that a system<br />

of noninsurable tort fines assessed on the individual doer of the “useless” act,<br />

together with general nonfault liability, would do a far better job of deterring<br />

valueless activities of this type.<br />

This leaves those acts or activities that, as a society, we are unprepared to call<br />

valueless—those activities that, subject to some subsequent political<br />

reconsideration <strong>and</strong> modification, we want to permit to the extent that they can pay<br />

for their accident costs. I would suggest, though it is not crucial to my analysis, that<br />

these comprise the bulk of the decisions as to accidents. Despite Learned H<strong>and</strong>’s<br />

formulation that negligence is a balancing of the “danger of an activity” against<br />

what must usefully be given up to avoid that danger, it is altogether too clear that a<br />

system of fault liability is designed to deal only with “useless” conduct <strong>and</strong> not with<br />

the more subtle interests involved in measuring the value <strong>and</strong> danger of an activity.<br />

If using a threshold of terrazzo is not deemed careless, then a system based on<br />

fault—as an all-or-nothing proposition—will have no effect whatever on this<br />

activity. The best way we can establish the extent to which we want to allow such<br />

activities is by a market decision based on the relative price of each of these<br />

activities <strong>and</strong> of their substitutes when each bears the costs of the accidents it causes.<br />

This can be done by a system of nonfault enterprise liability, a system that assesses<br />

the costs of accidents to activities according to their involvement in accidents. By<br />

contrast, our fault system, with insurance, assesses the cost of an activity not<br />

according to the number of accidents it causes but according to the number of<br />

accidents it causes in which certain predetermined indicia of fault can be attributed<br />

to it. This results in a deterrence of only faultily caused accidents in an area where<br />

by hypothesis we are interested in deterring activities not because of some moral<br />

implications but because of the accidents they cause.<br />

Guido Calabresi, The Decision for Accidents: An Approach to Nonfault Allocation of Costs, 78<br />

HARV. L. REV. 713, 718-20 (1965).<br />

Elsewhere, Calabresi makes the point that the nonfault or strict liability st<strong>and</strong>ard for<br />

accidents would accomplish the same economic goals as Learned H<strong>and</strong>’s negligence test:<br />

If we make the assumptions under which the Learned H<strong>and</strong> test would work<br />

adequately, the fascinating thing is that as good a result in terms of reducing primary<br />

accident costs could be achieved by a liability rule which is the exact reverse of the<br />

Learned H<strong>and</strong> test. Under such a “reverse Learned H<strong>and</strong> test,” the costs of an<br />

accident would be borne by the injurer unless accident avoidance on the part of the<br />

victim would have cost less than the accident. If a reverse contributory negligence<br />

test were added, the victim would bear the accident costs only if the injurer could<br />

not also have avoided the accident at less cost than the accident entailed. . . .<br />

177

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!