28.12.2012 Views

Redesigning Animal Agriculture

Redesigning Animal Agriculture

Redesigning Animal Agriculture

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

12 R. Bawden<br />

takes the opposing view and rejects the idea<br />

that explanation and prediction are ever<br />

symmetrical. Finally, where truth is seen to<br />

‘reside out there’ in the traditional paradigm,<br />

from a realist perspective the source of truth<br />

is neither ‘out there’ nor within the self, but<br />

in the dialectical relationship between the<br />

knower and the known. This latter position<br />

is therefore more likely to admit to normative<br />

influences where the former, traditional<br />

epistemology of science, eschews that.<br />

While all of these distinctions are significant<br />

in one manner or another, perhaps<br />

the most constraining element of traditional<br />

science, with respect to its role in development<br />

at least, is the rejection of the normative<br />

dimension, for, as Goulet (1995) submits,<br />

development is above all else a question of<br />

human values and attitudes. And as he further<br />

posits, it is about the self-definition of<br />

goals by societies and the collective determination<br />

of criteria ‘for determining what are<br />

tolerable costs to be borne, and by whom, in<br />

the course of change’. There is little doubt<br />

that this situation presents a significant epistemic<br />

challenge to those who would accept<br />

the need for the systemic development of<br />

animal agriculture but who have traditionally<br />

been captives of positivistic science.<br />

The next challenge is, in many ways,<br />

even more difficult to reconcile, for it relates<br />

not directly to science or to scientists but to<br />

the manner by which society has adopted<br />

scientific rationality to the apparent exclusion<br />

of virtually all other ways of knowing<br />

and all other epistemologies. In this manner,<br />

as Norgaard (1994) suggests, very significant<br />

constraints are being imposed on the process<br />

of development through the ‘narrowness of<br />

accepted patterns of thinking in the modern<br />

world’, with the instrumentality of technoscience<br />

thoroughly embroiled at the heart of<br />

the matter. So it is not so much how scientists<br />

go about their work of understanding<br />

the natural and social worlds, but how the<br />

citizenry have come to abdicate their own<br />

responsibilities for judgements about the<br />

way they live their lives in those worlds in<br />

deferring to the authority of scientists. This<br />

phenomenon extends beyond instrumental<br />

knowledge into the process of moral judgement.<br />

As Busch (2000) argues, we have<br />

spent several centuries now, secure in the<br />

abdication of our individual moral responsibilities<br />

to the care of what he refers to as<br />

‘one Leviathan or another’ such as ‘science’,<br />

or ‘the state’, or ‘the market’. We have been<br />

seemingly content, he submits, to place our<br />

trust respectively in scientists, authoritarian<br />

monarchs, or the market to tell us what<br />

is ‘good’ or ‘bad’. Similar arguments can<br />

be made for organized religion, with individuals<br />

abdicating their individual moral<br />

responsibilities to one ‘church’ or another<br />

whose dogmas have led to the loss of the<br />

will and/or the capacity for critical reflexivity.<br />

That which is ‘right and proper’ will be<br />

found in ‘the good book’ or will be revealed<br />

in some other spiritual manner, and a moral<br />

life then becomes that which is led under<br />

guidance of such revelations. The call for<br />

transformation in this context is based on<br />

the premise that there would seem to be too<br />

many instances where faith appears ‘blind’<br />

to contemporary circumstances or where<br />

it is being lost without the resumption of<br />

moral responsibilities by individuals.<br />

The instrumentalist dominance has thus<br />

been accompanied by the elevation of scientists<br />

to positions of social dominance as ‘public<br />

decision makers’ by virtue of their status<br />

as ‘experts’. Regrettably there is little doubt<br />

that some scientists have exploited what<br />

Gadamer (1975) has called ‘this peculiar<br />

falsehood of modern consciousness’. And<br />

regrettably, as Wynne (1996) has claimed,<br />

there are ample examples of situations<br />

where ‘experts’, including animal scientists,<br />

have ‘tacitly and furtively’ imposed prescriptive<br />

models of development upon lay<br />

people which have subsequently often ‘been<br />

wanting in human terms’. This has all led,<br />

as some see it, to the establishment of what<br />

Yankelovich (1991) calls a ‘culture of technical<br />

control’ and to an epistemic climate of<br />

‘cognitive authoritarianism’, where the rationality<br />

of thinking for oneself diminishes as<br />

the knowledge-gathering activities within<br />

societies expand beyond their capacities to<br />

deal with all they gather (Fuller, 1988).<br />

And so to the matter of what can and<br />

should be done in the face of these epistemic<br />

challenges to the systemic development<br />

of an animal agriculture, which both

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!