01.06.2014 Views

FOUNDATIONS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS

FOUNDATIONS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS

FOUNDATIONS OF QUANTUM MECHANICS

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

146 CHAPTER VII. BELL’S INEQUALITIES<br />

suitably chosen spin directions. This enables an experimental test of these statements, and therefore<br />

of the correctness of the philosophical bases of both theories. A. Shimony (1989) spoke, concerning<br />

the experimental testing of the Bell inequalities, of ‘experimental metaphysics’.<br />

However, the question of experimental testing puts the derivation of the Bell inequalities in another<br />

perspective. We no longer want to compare a HVT with quantum mechanics, but with experimental<br />

results. In this respect (VII. 6), implying perfect anti - correlation when ⃗a = ⃗ b, is overly<br />

idealized. In a real experiment the particle detectors are not perfectly efficient, in the sense that not<br />

all particles are registered. Imagine a detector which, even if A(⃗a, λ) = 1, sometimes gives 0, i.e. not<br />

measured, or even −1, i.e. wrongly measured. Moreover, in a contextual HVT the outcomes could also<br />

be dependent of the measuring context, i.e. of (possibly hidden) variables of the detectors. But also in<br />

this generalized situation it is possible to derive the inequality (VII. 13) from a locality assumption.<br />

We will show this by proving the next theorem.<br />

BELL’S SECOND THEOREM:<br />

A local deterministic contextual HVT is empirically inconsistent with quantum mechanics.<br />

Proof<br />

Assume that the quantities A and B are functions of three arguments,<br />

A = A(⃗a, λ, µ), B = B( ⃗ b, λ, ν) where A, B ∈ {− 1, 1}. (VII. 21)<br />

Here the local deterministic character of the HVT is expressed; the outcome of the measurement<br />

at the measuring apparatus measuring ⃗a · ⃗σ is determined by λ ∈ Λ, describing the source, by the<br />

local hidden variables of that measuring device, expressed symbolically by µ ∈ Λ a , and by the<br />

position ⃗a of the meter pointer. Therefore, the requirement of locality is that A does not depend<br />

on ⃗ b and ν, and B does not depend on ⃗a and µ. We also assume that the hidden variables of the<br />

apparatuses are independent of each other and of λ,<br />

Defining<br />

ρ(λ, µ, ν) = ρ(λ) ρ 1 (µ) ρ 2 (ν). (VII. 22)<br />

and<br />

⟨A(⃗a, λ)⟩ :=<br />

⟨B( ⃗ b, λ)⟩ :=<br />

∫<br />

A(⃗a, λ, µ) ρ 1 (µ) dµ (VII. 23)<br />

Λ a<br />

∫<br />

B( ⃗ b, λ, ν) ρ 2 (ν) dν, (VII. 24)<br />

Λ b<br />

we have, instead of assumption (VII. 2), the much weaker requirements<br />

|⟨A(⃗a, λ)⟩| 1 and |⟨B( ⃗ b, λ)⟩| 1, (VII. 25)<br />

and we will show now that from this it is again possible to derive the Bell inequality (VII. 13).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!