03.12.2012 Views

Sartre's second century

Sartre's second century

Sartre's second century

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Sartre, Intentionality and Praxis 95<br />

must now grasp the human subject in its historically determined situation<br />

as a radically embedded spontaneity that accomplishes the rebirth of its<br />

inherited world in its own self-projection, an embedded spontaneity whose<br />

"objectification" must be understood as its substantial "truth": "[T]he<br />

objectified subjective must be considered as the only truth of the<br />

subjective." 24<br />

It is clearly beyond the scope of this chapter to treat <strong>Sartre's</strong> various<br />

nuanced treatments of the "objectified subjective", spanning, as they do,<br />

recently published manuscripts as well as major late works such as Search<br />

for a Method (1960), The Critique of Dialectical Reason (1960) and the<br />

multi-volume work on Flaubert, The Family Idiot. However, an insightful<br />

and compelling path into <strong>Sartre's</strong> later thought is provided by an example<br />

that Sartre himself offered in 1966, an example that responds to our<br />

culture's almost obsessive preoccupation with language:<br />

There was a time when thought was defined independently of language, as<br />

something intangible and ineffable that pre-exists expression. Today<br />

people fall into the opposite error. They would have us believe that thought<br />

is only language, as if language itself were not spoken.<br />

In reality, there are two levels. On the first level, language presents<br />

itself, in effect, as an autonomous system, which reflects social unification.<br />

Language is an element of the 'practico-inert', a sonorous substance<br />

unified by a set of practices. The linguist takes this totality of relations as<br />

an object of study, and he has a right to do this because it is already<br />

constituted. This is the stage of structure, in which the totality appears as a<br />

thing without man [...]. But this thing without man is at the same time<br />

matter worked by man, bearing the trace of man [...]. If you admit the<br />

existence of such a system, you must also admit that language exists only<br />

as spoken, in other words in act. Each element of the system refers to a<br />

whole, but this whole is dead if nobody takes it up for his own purposes,<br />

makes it work. 25<br />

Peter Caws writes that "the (concept of the) practico-inert strikes me as<br />

one of the most useful additions to the conceptual repertoire of social<br />

philosophy in the last <strong>century</strong>". 26 This may well be true. For the moment, I<br />

will suggest that <strong>Sartre's</strong> various comments on spoken language, today<br />

largely unappreciated, yield valuable illustrations of the meaning and<br />

significance of the "practico-inert".<br />

Ibid., 98.<br />

Sartre, L'Arc, no. 30,88-89, cited in Peter Caws, "Sartrean Structuralism?", 299.<br />

Caws, 309.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!