04.03.2014 Views

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Political Science and the Irrational<br />

2 4 3<br />

to be good for himself (and at best incidentally so for his fellow Athenians).<br />

Any concern for justice he might have seems to be, to put it anachronistically,<br />

purely Machiavellian. If, then, this is indeed the case, then it would inevitably<br />

follow that the admittedly simple suggestion that Socrates is indeed a<br />

civic-minded moralist in his dealings with the haughty and hubristic youth<br />

is essentially correct, and that this is indeed why he introduced the question<br />

of justice in his present discussion (Plato 2001, 216d-e, 219d).<br />

What is more, as their conversation here unfolds there is<br />

further evidence for this interpretation of Alcibiades’ greedy and Socrates’<br />

virtuous intent. We thus seem to be moving ever-further away from the putative<br />

Platonic reduction of the two extremes that were mentioned before as the<br />

hallmark of both this dialogue and human nature. For even though Alcibiades<br />

is compelled to admit that he, just like everyone else, does not truly<br />

have knowledge of a “weightier” matter such as justice (Plato 1987, 106d-e,<br />

109d-112d, 113b), he seemingly diminishes the importance of this assertion<br />

by supposing that Greeks<br />

[l]et these matters go and consider which things will be advantageous<br />

to those practicing them. For just and advantageous things are not,<br />

I suppose, the same, but many have profited from committing great<br />

injustices, and I suppose there are others who performed just acts that<br />

were not to their advantage. (113d)<br />

However, this latter assertion about the possible antonymy between the just<br />

and his own good is not only a perhaps nascent Machiavellianism, but, what<br />

is more important, it inevitably implies that Alcibiades in fact does have<br />

some knowledge of each of them. Yet such an implication cannot possibly be<br />

consistent. For Socrates has by now already coaxed Alcibiades into partially<br />

consenting to the proposal that one can only learn what one has discovered<br />

for one’s self or been taught by another. Thus, whether one has discovered<br />

or been taught something, in order to have learned that something one<br />

must first have been made aware of one’s own ignorance or need to learn<br />

it. Admittedly, Alcibiades initially resists this proposal in part by claiming<br />

that he learned justice just as he learned the Greek language, i.e., without any<br />

prior knowledge of ignorance. Socrates, however, had already gotten Alcibiades<br />

to agree that, even if such knowledge is indeed possible, this is not so for<br />

a “weightier” matter such as justice. For while it may be true that the many<br />

know the Greek language and are thus capable of teaching it, they are capable<br />

of doing so only because they are, as “knowers,” necessarily in agreement<br />

with one another with respect to what they name when they name it. But

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!