04.03.2014 Views

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

3 2 4<br />

I n t e r p r e t a t i o n<br />

as long as that religion satisfied his standards of enlightened rationalism:<br />

“Jefferson believed America to be embroiled in a battle between religious<br />

superstition and intolerance on the one hand and reason and freedom on<br />

the other. He sought to achieve a decisive victory by using state power to<br />

nurture the rational religious beliefs…and to suppress the irrational dogmas<br />

and institutions that he believed to be hostile to liberty” (116).<br />

It is possible to pause here and quibble about whether<br />

their namesakes would fully own up to these characterizations, or question<br />

whether it is fair to settle on what Madison said (in the Memorial and<br />

Remonstrance) versus what he did (in declaring days of prayer when he was<br />

President, for example) while doing just the opposite with Jefferson, whose<br />

actions (in setting up the University of Virginia) speak louder than his words<br />

(in the Virginia Statute for Religious Freedom). But Muñoz disarms this line<br />

of attack in the Introduction, where he sets out his version of originalism:<br />

“The Founders’ ideas should govern us today only to the extent that they are<br />

persuasive,” not because “a powerful elite voted for the Constitution more<br />

than 200 years ago” (5). As a result, it is less critical to fully explicate any<br />

particular founder’s entire church-state record than to identify principles of<br />

religious freedom that can compete for our—or the Supreme Court’s—attention<br />

as potential constitutional philosophies.<br />

Muñoz then turns to the Court’s church-state jurisprudence,<br />

where he accomplishes a feat that has eluded judges and scholars alike: he<br />

finds a consistent theme running through most of the establishment clause<br />

cases—Madisonianism. Irrespective of the rationale cited by the Court in<br />

these cases, which span three score years, Madisonianism predicts the result<br />

nearly 75 percent of the time—and in one of the non-matched cases (over<br />

legislative chaplains), the Court went with what Madison actually did rather<br />

than what Muñoz’s Madisonianism would require. That is, the prevailing<br />

judicial approach to the establishment clause has given us a largely Madisonian<br />

non-cognizance standard that forbids the government from giving<br />

aid or support to religion qua religion, even though the Court itself has not<br />

advanced overtly Madisonian reasons. Meanwhile, Washingtonianism, and<br />

even Jeffersonianism, would put more religion in the public schools than<br />

the Court has allowed, although there would be a rationalism litmus test<br />

in Jefferson’s schools by which old-time religion would be supplanted by an<br />

appropriately enlightened faith.<br />

One of the most intriguing elements of Muñoz’s link between<br />

current establishment clause jurisprudence and these founding fathers is

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!