04.03.2014 Views

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

3 2 6<br />

I n t e r p r e t a t i o n<br />

forms of religiosity, whereas Jefferson would only recognize faiths whose<br />

catechisms could pass his rational-basis test. It is worth asking, however,<br />

whether Jefferson would really be as willing to apply this element of Jeffersonianism<br />

to the nation, where the religious demographics were unfavorable<br />

for his desired outcome, as to “Mr. Jefferson’s University,” where his influence<br />

was much greater. As president, Jefferson typically acted and sounded more<br />

Madisonian than even Madison did. And so, while identifying this particular<br />

strand of Jeffersonianism is a useful tool for Muñoz’s analysis, it is difficult<br />

to align it as closely with the third president’s overall church-state philosophy<br />

as the other two approaches can reasonably be linked to Madison and<br />

Washington (as Muñoz recognizes in a clever index entry titled, “Jefferson,<br />

contradictions in”).<br />

In an important contribution to the current religious freedom<br />

debate, Muñoz describes how religious accommodation was not a<br />

particular concern of any of these framers. After a review of the three Virginians<br />

on the subject of indirect burdens—such as compulsory schooling<br />

requirements—and exemptions—whether there should be, for example,<br />

conscientious exemptions for military service—Muñoz concludes that none<br />

of them would support such constitutional rights, and only Washingtonianism<br />

would even allow legislatures to create statutory exemptions. Here the<br />

Supreme Court’s decisions to free the Amish from compulsory schooling<br />

or Jehovah’s Witnesses from saluting the flag are considerably more accommodating<br />

than the Virginia framers. In sum, it is difficult to find support<br />

from any of these three founders for insulating the devout from generally<br />

applicable laws.<br />

In the end, Muñoz concludes that there was no single comprehensive<br />

church-state viewpoint shared by the founding generation, but,<br />

nevertheless, the framers “can serve as a rich source of ideas and understandings<br />

about religion and the proper separation of church and state” (221). The<br />

same can be said of Muñoz’s own contribution to our study of religion and<br />

the republic, which is strikingly clear and well written for someone schooled<br />

deeply in political philosophy, yet thoughtfully nuanced for one so willing to<br />

plunge into constitutional controversies. Muñoz has provided us with one of<br />

the few genuinely original contributions to a field that has felt overcrowded<br />

and redundant for several decades. That every reader will find something<br />

interesting with which to wrestle is a tribute to his ability to shed new light on<br />

old subjects in a way that provokes a much needed reawakening of the field.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!