04.03.2014 Views

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Book Review: Greek Tragedy and Political Philosophy 3 0 9<br />

Oedipus is judged noble because of his efforts to accomplish<br />

the common good of his adopted country. But his nobility only heightens<br />

his sense of desperation, since true nobility requires that he succeed, and not<br />

just try. He therefore feels himself obliged to pursue every means of saving<br />

Thebes, including the uncovering of Laius’s killer. Nobility, put to the test by<br />

necessity, leads to piety as a last resort.<br />

Still, noble sacrifice for the good of others proves not to<br />

be Oedipus’s deepest concern. Ahrensdorf maintains—and convincingly<br />

argues—that Oedipus is actuated more by the desire that he be the savior of<br />

Thebes than that Thebes be actually saved. For after the confrontation with<br />

Teiresias, Oedipus thinks no more of Thebes but of his own innocence, forgetting<br />

to ask the lone witness to the incident at the cross-roads whether one<br />

or more killers were involved. Ahrensdorf also notes that Oedipus welcomes<br />

news of the death of his Corinthian father, lest it somehow turn out that<br />

Oedipus is the person responsible, as was prophesized by an oracle; Oedipus<br />

tries killing Jocasta, seemingly in an effort to fulfill an oracle; and by blinding<br />

himself he does lasting harm to his sons and daughters. (Somewhat less convincing<br />

is Ahrensdorf’s contention that Oedipus leaves Corinth to further his<br />

political ambition.)<br />

Why does Oedipus blind himself? The blinding signifies<br />

that Oedipus accepts the judgment of the gods, even to the point of applying<br />

additional punishment to himself. In return, Oedipus expects to receive<br />

everlasting life as a reward and blessing of the gods. Oedipus’s turn to piety<br />

is at bottom self-interested. And because even Oedipus—the paradigmatic<br />

rational man—seeks solace in the hope of immortality, the lesson drawn by<br />

Sophocles—or by Ahrensdorf on the poet’s behalf—is that immortality is the<br />

hope of nearly every man; and that piety, therefore, is an irrepressible fact of<br />

political life requiring deft management by those in charge.<br />

Oedipus does indeed seem divinely favored in the succeeding<br />

play. At Colonnus he is wise for being blind, whereas in Thebes he was<br />

foolish despite his sight. Sight—or reason—is unseeing, while blindness—or<br />

piety—sees all. The gods now approve of Oedipus, chastened and dependent,<br />

and at the end of the play they transport him to Hades. But the only witness<br />

of the event, King Theseus, does not exactly confirm the apotheosis; in<br />

fact, Theseus implies that Oedipus died a natural death and that his body lies<br />

buried in a secret spot. Divine judgment—which if known would settle the<br />

reason-piety debate—seems no more certain than the mystery of Oedipus’s<br />

disappearance.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!