04.03.2014 Views

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Political Science and the Irrational<br />

2 4 7<br />

discovering it. Socrates is understandably apprehensive: Alcibiades is still<br />

unaware that he has in his way been caring for justice all along: and he still<br />

believes he knows what it is.”)<br />

It is consequently unsurprising that Socrates again has occasion<br />

to bring out Alcibiades’ own confusion and lack of reason. For having<br />

now reduced the question of the duty of a good man to the capability to rule<br />

in the city, and after having suggested that such rule requires citizens to make<br />

friends of one another through concord, Socrates solicits from Alcibiades the<br />

further assertion that concord cannot be reached amongst those who know<br />

different things (Plato 1987, 126; see Addendum 4). But because both justice<br />

and concord arguably arise from people practicing their own things and so<br />

what they in particular know—through a sensible division of labor such as the<br />

one outlined by Socrates in the Republic—it now seems to follow that friendship<br />

necessarily precludes justice (128b). Alcibiades had earlier conceded<br />

that, “when men…suppose they don’t know (some matter), they hand that<br />

matter over to others,” and so had conceded that a very common and sensible<br />

form of knowledge of ignorance averts the great evils that follow from the<br />

stupidity which, among other things, brings about injustice (118a-b1). Now,<br />

however, he flatly denies that such knowledge of ignorance is possible, and,<br />

mutatis mutandis, compatible with concord. He is thereby shown once again<br />

to lack concord with and so knowledge of himself.<br />

Aware of his own contradictory statements (127d), Alcibiades<br />

finally despairs of what to do or think. Socrates tries to reassure him by<br />

directing their conversation to the question of what it means to take trouble<br />

over oneself (128a). He thereby distinguishes between what belongs to us<br />

“externally,” e.g., shoes, etc., and “internally,” so that the proper art of taking<br />

trouble over oneself is not confused with any “external” arts. As it turns<br />

out, and sensibly so, to be able to take trouble over oneself means that one<br />

must first know what one is. Socrates thus warns Alcibiades that he, before<br />

approaching the Athenian assembly and so taking up political affairs, first<br />

train and so take care of himself by knowing what and who he is (132b; Plato<br />

2001, 216a).<br />

As to looking out for such self-knowledge, presumably this<br />

is best discerned and achieved while looking to a teacher who acts as a mirror<br />

to his or her pupil (Plato 1987, 132d-133a). The teacher and student in<br />

question, moreover, seem to be none other than Socrates and Alcibiades. Yet<br />

this means we are left with the unpromising suggestion that Alcibiades is<br />

uneducable, for assuming that what has transpired thus far is indicative of

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!