04.03.2014 Views

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

3 1 0<br />

I n t e r p r e t a t i o n<br />

Ahrensdorf’s central observation regarding the Colonnus<br />

play is that Oedipus must prove himself deserving of human protection and<br />

divine reward. Apologetics, in other words, make up the action of the play,<br />

suggesting, says Ahrensdorf, that “if we human beings hope that the gods<br />

will reward us, we cannot simply reject reason but must have recourse to<br />

it” (57). Oedipus argues: (1) that he is not to be despised and cast out for his<br />

patricide and incest, because these actions were committed unknowingly; (2)<br />

that he is not to be punished for his angry violence at the cross-roads, because<br />

he was entitled to defend himself against the king’s party; and (3) that he is<br />

piteous and deserving of favor, because others abused him deliberately, such<br />

as his parents in exposing him and his sons in expelling him. Ahrensdorf<br />

explains that the second argument and the third are not consistent, since<br />

the second supposes that self-interest (self-preservation) exonerates, while<br />

the third supposes that the interests of others are culpable. (Of course the<br />

contradiction depends on a conflation of self-preservation with self-interest<br />

in all of its manifestations and thus on a denial of evil, which Sophocles<br />

might not intend.) Ahrensdorf concludes that Oedipus is rational (engaged<br />

in apologetics) up to the point where reason supports his case for immortality<br />

and divine approval; after which he resorts to anger to defend his sense<br />

of desert. Oedipus is angry in the Colonnus play, says Ahrensdorf, because<br />

anger “naturally gives rise to the heartening belief that justice demands that<br />

you be aided and that the unjust be punished, and hence that there be gods<br />

who favor you as you deserve and punish your enemies as they deserve” (71).<br />

Righteous indignation proves to be yet another avenue to religious piety.<br />

King Theseus stands in stark contrast to Oedipus the wanderer.<br />

Theseus is not angry, despite suffering exile himself. He is not angry<br />

with Oedipus for his polluting crimes nor with Creon for his contemptuous<br />

bullying. Theseus understands, remarks Ahrensdorf, that people act out of<br />

self-interest and that it makes little sense to be angry with them for doing<br />

as nature requires. Theseus’s own interest, as king of an insignificant city, is<br />

to establish its reputation for piety by providing protection to Oedipus. The<br />

reputation, however, is divorced from the reality, insofar as Theseus is not<br />

particularly pious himself—e.g., he shares power with no religious authority.<br />

Theseus is calculating and calm, unburdened by anger, piety, or patriotic zeal.<br />

And yet his rationalistic rule recognizes the importance of pious hopes in<br />

his subjects and pious fears in his enemies. Thus the extension of sanctuary<br />

to Oedipus is useful to Thebes even if the gods are unmoved, uninvolved, or<br />

non-existent. Moreover, the risks incurred by offending more powerful Thebes<br />

are less serious than they appear, since the Theban royal house is torn by

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!