04.03.2014 Views

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

Spring 2010 - Interpretation

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Book Review: Aristotle’s Dialogue with Socrates<br />

3 2 1<br />

If Aristotle intends, as Burger’s noticing reminder suggests<br />

strongly, that he is not satisfied with two realms, practical and theoretical, but<br />

that he wishes to unite the two into a complete activity and a complete life,<br />

the question we must consider, and which Burger turns to in her concluding<br />

section, is, how are theoria and praxis to be conjoined? what might it mean to<br />

put theoria into action? On the one hand, “To picture the theoretical life in its<br />

purity, we must think of the gods” (203). The life of pure contemplation would<br />

appear to be the life of a god, it “is at home only on the Isles of the Blessed,”<br />

and “its exemplar is Thales” (205). But this model in general does not concern<br />

itself, and Thales in particular did not concern himself, with “philosophy of<br />

the human things.” That concern belongs to Socrates and Socratic philosophy.<br />

And Aristotle identifies his investigation of the highest human good,<br />

eudaimonia, and the best life for a human being as part of the philosophy of<br />

the human things.<br />

At this point we must look back to the beginning and remember<br />

that a part of Aristotle’s work—indeed, perhaps his entire work—involved<br />

examining speeches (logoi), the things people say and believe, to try to discover<br />

the truth. From early on Burger pointed out how Aristotle cited the<br />

Socratic formula “turn to the logoi” to critique those who take refuge in logoi<br />

and avoid the hard work of action. Her careful reading indicates that Aristotle<br />

means us to remember this point at the end, which, she argues, means that<br />

we are meant to apply the same caution to Aristotle’s words themselves. If we<br />

do this, Burger suggests, we will walk away understanding the Ethics not as a<br />

treatise declaring the supremacy of sophia and contemplation over phronesis<br />

and action, but as a philosophic discussion exploring both the promise and<br />

the challenge of sophia and phronesis together for human life and human<br />

action. That promise and challenge are played out not in assertoric fashion,<br />

but in dialogue: the dialogue that Aristotle is engaging in with Socrates and<br />

Plato, but also, and in a sense more profoundly, the invitation to dialogue that<br />

Aristotle extends to the reader. And it is on this last point that Burger’s book<br />

is most to be commended. For as she discovers and discloses the evidence<br />

in the text for Aristotle’s dialogue with Socrates, she herself practices and<br />

illustrates how we, the readers, may enter into and engage in a philosophic<br />

dialogue with Aristotle.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!