17.05.2014 Views

Party Autonomy in International Property Law - Peace Palace Library

Party Autonomy in International Property Law - Peace Palace Library

Party Autonomy in International Property Law - Peace Palace Library

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

4. <strong>Party</strong> <strong>Autonomy</strong> and <strong>Property</strong> Rights<br />

4.4. <strong>Party</strong> autonomy<br />

Given then that English law, like all systems, has a numerus clausus <strong>in</strong><br />

relation to all rights which are exigible aga<strong>in</strong>st all others, <strong>in</strong>clud<strong>in</strong>g both<br />

rights <strong>in</strong> rem <strong>in</strong> the Roman sense and <strong>in</strong>tellectual property rights, and also<br />

that English law, like all systems, has several restrictions on the transfer of<br />

rights by agreement alone, it would at first sight appear to be the case that<br />

party autonomy is severely restricted. This would be, of course, commercially<br />

<strong>in</strong>convenient. That this is not so is because English law, like other<br />

legal systems, has transcended the Roman law dichotomy between rights<br />

<strong>in</strong> rem and rights <strong>in</strong> personam. This is also true of legal systems outside of<br />

the common law world but the pattern is neither uniform nor (unfortunately)<br />

widely understood.<br />

The essential concept to grasp is that of rights to rights.<br />

If A, the owner of Blackacre declares himself a trustee of the right to his<br />

land <strong>in</strong> B’s favour, English law does ‘not say that [B is] the owner of the<br />

land, it says that the trustee was the owner of the land, but adds that he is<br />

bound to hold the land for the benefit of [B]’. 16 We may illustrate this by<br />

the fact that B has no stand<strong>in</strong>g to sue for violation of the right to the land<br />

itself: only A may sue a trespasser or the creator of a private nuisance. B<br />

has no right to the land, and does not have a right exigible aga<strong>in</strong>st the rest<br />

of the world but only one as aga<strong>in</strong>st the person with title to Blackacre from<br />

time to time. B does not, therefore, acquire <strong>in</strong> the narrow sense employed<br />

by the Romans, a right <strong>in</strong> rem.<br />

B’s right that A holds the title to the land for his benefit (which is simply<br />

the converse of A’s duty to hold the title to the land for B’s benefit) is<br />

not simply a right aga<strong>in</strong>st A personally, a right <strong>in</strong> personam <strong>in</strong> the sense<br />

employed by Roman lawyers. Rather the subject matter of B’s right is A’s<br />

right to the land. 17 If, therefore, A gives the (right to) Blackacre to his<br />

16<br />

F.W. Maitland, Equity – a course of lectures (A.H. Chaytor and W.J. Whittaker,<br />

eds., revised by J. Bunyate), Cambridge, 1936, 17-18.<br />

17<br />

See also R. Chambers, An Introduction to <strong>Property</strong> <strong>Law</strong> <strong>in</strong> Australia (2 nd ed.,<br />

<strong>Law</strong>book Co, 2008) at [13.90]; L Smith, ‘Unravell<strong>in</strong>g Proprietary Restitution’,<br />

Canadian Bus<strong>in</strong>ess <strong>Law</strong> Journal, (2004), 317; L Smith, ‘Philosophical Foundations<br />

of Proprietary Remedies’ <strong>in</strong>: R. Chambers et al. (eds.), Philosophical<br />

Foundations of The <strong>Law</strong> of Unjust Enrichment (Hart, 2009); L Smith ‘Trust<br />

and Patrimony’, Revue générale de droit 38 (2008), 379-403; L. Smith, Estates,<br />

Robert Stevens<br />

89<br />

© sellier. european law publishers<br />

www.sellier.de

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!