09.03.2015 Views

Final Report (all chapters)

Final Report (all chapters)

Final Report (all chapters)

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

and/or any organs derived from human fetuses. It also establishes substantial penalties for<br />

violating its provisions. However, legal scholars agree that this act does not reach the trade of<br />

human gametes. It appears that no judicial decision has ever construed the meaning of “human<br />

organ” to include gametes. 34<br />

Hence, for the purpose of this report, the National Organ<br />

Transplantation Act is immaterial.<br />

5.1.7 Regulation by Tort<br />

Conceivably, the practice of reproductive medicine could also be regulated through the tort<br />

system. Malpractice litigation is based on the notion that a plaintiff, in order to prevail, must<br />

demonstrate that he or she is owed a duty of care, and that the attending physician has harmed<br />

the plaintiff by violating this duty. Combined with often-draconian verdicts, this system is<br />

supposed to induce medical professionals to establish appropriate standards of care and to ensure<br />

that practitioners follow them scrupulously.<br />

An obvious limitation of this system is its focus on procedures rather than on the merits of<br />

an expected outcome. For example, whether sex selection for non-therapeutic uses is an ethic<strong>all</strong>y<br />

acceptable reproductive procedure cannot be decided through tort litigation. Litigation in this<br />

case can only determine whether a patient was harmed, and whether harm can be attributed to<br />

medical malpractice. In the case of many ethic<strong>all</strong>y controversial treatments, making these twin<br />

determinations is no easy task. For example, is it re<strong>all</strong>y possible to claim that failure to deliver a<br />

baby of the desired sex amounts to medical malpractice? Certainly the “outcome” was undesired,<br />

but can a baby of the “wrong” sex re<strong>all</strong>y produce harm? Assuming some notion of harm is<br />

recognized by the court, what standard of care has been violated in this case?<br />

One can easily imagine many variations on this scenario. Pre-implantation genetic diagnosis<br />

to screen for dreadful diseases and ooplasm transfer to treat extreme cases of infertility provide<br />

two examples. How the courts may decide these cases is an interesting question for legal scholars<br />

to ponder, but it is beyond the scope of the present discussion. Presumably, litigation in this area<br />

would prompt ART clinics to scrutinize more carefully the harm that novel reproductive<br />

technologies and innovative treatments might cause and to establish appropriate standards of<br />

care. 35<br />

This development certainly would be most welcome, but standards of care <strong>all</strong> by<br />

themselves are of little importance in adjudicating competing ethical claims.<br />

5.1.8 Regulation by the Market<br />

Regulation can occur through market mechanisms as well. There are many precedents in this<br />

area. Consumers may prefer products certified to have been produced in an environment<strong>all</strong>y<br />

34<br />

35<br />

President's Council on Bioethics, Reproduction and Responsibility: The Regulation of New Biotechnologies,<br />

p.151-52.<br />

In recent times, serious doubts have emerged about the effectiveness of malpractice litigation in improving<br />

medical standards of care. An excellent introduction to this issue is Atul Gawande, Complications: Decisions<br />

and Dilemmas of a Surgeon's Life (London: Profile Books, 2002).<br />

127

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!