09.03.2015 Views

Final Report (all chapters)

Final Report (all chapters)

Final Report (all chapters)

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

(principle (e)). 43 Canada affords equal access to ART technologies to any (presumably adult)<br />

individual independent of sexual orientation and marital status. Accordingly, couples –<br />

heterosexual or not – as well as singles are granted equal access to ART technologies.<br />

A deductive approach to ethical controversies is not without problems however, especi<strong>all</strong>y<br />

for the regulators charged with implementing the provisions of the AHRA. For example,<br />

principle (a) is clearly intended to protect the health and well-being of children. As a matter of<br />

principle, very few would disagree that the health and well-being of children is a moral good<br />

worthy of protection, yet any attempt to give the terms “health” and “well-being” a precise<br />

operational meaning is likely to be controversial. Principle (b) identifies human dignity and<br />

human rights as two moral goods deserving protection, but leaves entirely unspecified the notion<br />

of human dignity, and does not bother to identify which human rights should be protected.<br />

Again, it would be only too easy to fault regulators for not adequately protecting human rights,<br />

or for taking too expansive a view of human dignity for that matter. Furthermore, it is quite<br />

possible that some of these principles may inspire conflicting regulatory interventions.<br />

That guiding principles leave considerable room for interpretation does not justify<br />

dismissing a deductive approach to modern ethical dilemmas as irrelevant or impracticable. It is,<br />

however, a good reason for establishing specific rules and institutions for addressing these<br />

interpretive ambiguities. In this regard, the AHRA leaves much to be desired, as it does not<br />

include any provisions as to how regulators may go about resolving the ambiguities that a<br />

principled approach inevitably will produce.<br />

The principles themselves are only in minimal part derived from a consistent ethical<br />

framework, and they seem to reflect the outcome of a political compromise. An American<br />

observer might regard them as politic<strong>all</strong>y liberal, for example, when they afford gay and lesbian<br />

couples equal access to reproductive technologies. On the other end, the principles prohibit the<br />

commercial trade of human gametes and embryos, a measure many Americans would find too<br />

restrictive. Being the result of a political compromise, these principles ignore some important<br />

issues. For example, the distinction between therapeutic and enhancing applications of new<br />

reproductive technologies has not been formalized, though it seems to inform several provisions<br />

of this act. At the same time, the fact that these principles represent a political compromise<br />

suggests that they will likely enjoy broad public support.<br />

Prohibited Activities<br />

AHRA Sections 5 through 9 enumerate proscribed reproductive procedures and research<br />

activities. Taken together, these prohibitions suggest a restrictive approach to reproductive<br />

medicine; the act prohibits many reproductive treatments now common in the United States.<br />

These prohibitions are remarkable for two main reasons. First, they apply to certain procreative<br />

ends, not to the specific technological means to achieve them. While scientific and medical<br />

43<br />

Principle (e) does not completely resolve this thorny issue. For example, it is not entirely clear whether this<br />

principle would afford a woman the right to become impregnated with the sperm of her deceased husband.<br />

162

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!