09.03.2015 Views

Final Report (all chapters)

Final Report (all chapters)

Final Report (all chapters)

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

elatively modest. Canada and Australia recently have established similar regulatory bodies, but<br />

their enabling legislation does not assign bioethicists a prominent role, and their composition<br />

does not reflect efforts to professionalize broad societal conflicts.<br />

It is undeniable that this strategy has a considerable appeal, most likely fueled by a deepseated<br />

mistrust in the ability of modern democracies to resist their worst temptations. Even such<br />

a fervent defender of representative democracy as Ralf Dahrendorf has come to the conclusion<br />

that parliaments are ill-suited to resolving complex ethical dilemmas, and has recommended a<br />

politic<strong>all</strong>y independent body of highly regarded individuals as a preferable alternative. 16<br />

The professionalization of modern bioethical dilemmas would be a mistake for several<br />

reasons. Bioethics, just like other disciplines in the social sciences and humanities, has seen the<br />

development of numerous and conflicting theoretical perspectives. As a discipline, bioethics is<br />

simply incapable of providing politicians with uncontroversial answers. For why should a<br />

particular ethical paradigm be preferred to another? It is fair to say that no rules exist to select<br />

one ethical paradigm from the plethora of available ethical positions. And a plethora it is. Even a<br />

cursory examination of the bioethical literature brings to the light such perspectives as<br />

principlism, specified principlism, casuistry, and narrative ethics, just to name a few. 17 The<br />

plurality of approaches in bioethics is a testimony of the richness of this relatively new academic<br />

field, but it also makes it impossible for bioethics to play a privileged role in policy-making.<br />

A genuinely pluralistic ethics advisory board could play a useful role in contemporary public<br />

debates about reproductive technologies and biomedical research provided that it does not<br />

attempt to produce consensus positions on questions for which a consensus simply does not<br />

exist. Making majority and minority recommendations available to policy-makers and ensuring<br />

that the underlying assumptions informing these positions are made transparent would be much<br />

more valuable than a thinly disguised consensus report. As we have argued in chapter 2, poor<br />

policy choices are more likely to be induced by a dearth of ethical positions rather than by a<br />

plurality thereof.<br />

A second concern is the rapid transformation of the field of bioethics from a discipline<br />

focused on broad substantive questions into a largely technical field preoccupied with<br />

fundamental principles and with procedural considerations rather than outcomes. The shift of<br />

professional bioethics toward technical, narrowly defined questions also has legitimized many<br />

hitherto controversial biomedical developments. The currently dominant bioethical perspective<br />

16<br />

17<br />

Ralf Dahrendorf, Dopo La Democrazia. Intervista a Cura Di Antonio Polito (Roma: Laterza, 2001).<br />

Tom L. Beauchamp, "Reply to Strong on Principlism and Casuistry," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25,<br />

no. 3 (2000); Bernard Gert, Charles M. Culver, and K. Danner Clouser, "Common Morality Versus Specified<br />

Principlism: Reply to Richardson," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3 (2000); Albert R. Jonsen,<br />

"Strong on Specification," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3 (2000); Henry S. Richardson,<br />

"Specifying, Balancing, and Interpreting Bioethical Principles," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3<br />

(2000); Ana Smith Iltis, "Bioethics as Methodological Case Resolution: Specification, Specified Principlism and<br />

Casuistry," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3 (2000); Carson Strong, "Specified Principlism: What<br />

Is It, and Does It Re<strong>all</strong>y Resolve Cases Better Than Casuistry?," Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25, no. 3<br />

(2000).<br />

252

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!