09.07.2015 Views

Subjectivism and Economic Analysis: Essays in memory of Ludwig ...

Subjectivism and Economic Analysis: Essays in memory of Ludwig ...

Subjectivism and Economic Analysis: Essays in memory of Ludwig ...

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

LÁSLÓ CSONTOSBut what exactly do the terms ‘ideal type’ <strong>and</strong> ‘plan’ mean <strong>in</strong> thiscontext? 10 My purpose <strong>in</strong> propos<strong>in</strong>g a rational reconstruction <strong>of</strong>these notions is aga<strong>in</strong> tw<strong>of</strong>old. First, I want to substantiate myearlier claim that Lachmann misunderstood, <strong>and</strong> consequentlymisconstrued, Weber’s methodological legacy at least <strong>in</strong> oneimportant respect. Second, I want to show that the concepts <strong>of</strong> plan<strong>and</strong> ideal types can be fruitfully united under the methodologicalumbrella <strong>of</strong> the idea <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>tentional explanation.Let us return to the ‘Why did B do x?’ question. Suppose weknow from the outset that B wanted <strong>and</strong> managed to achieve y,where y st<strong>and</strong>s for some desired end. For simplicity’s sake, let’smake the further assumption that the only means to be taken <strong>in</strong>toaccount, if a means is to be taken <strong>in</strong>to account at all, or the onlymeans B had considered if she had considered any means at all, wasnoth<strong>in</strong>g else but the action x. Could we then put forward thefollow<strong>in</strong>g argument?1 B wanted to achieve y.2 The only means to achieve y was action x. Therefore,3 B did x.Clearly, we cannot always expla<strong>in</strong> B’s action this way. First, B maynot have known that x was a means to achieve y, <strong>in</strong> which case shedid x perhaps for some other reason, <strong>and</strong> obta<strong>in</strong>ed y only as a fluke.Second, B may have acted on a wrong reason, that is, she may havebelieved, mistakenly, that x was the only means to achieve y,whereas <strong>in</strong> fact x was not an effective means to this end at all.We can take care <strong>of</strong> these possibilities, Weber came to argue later,<strong>in</strong> either <strong>of</strong> the follow<strong>in</strong>g two ways. The first option is to show, byfactor<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong> the agent’s epistemic situation, 11 that B, given her beliefsabout the relevant means-ends relationships, acted <strong>in</strong> a subjectivelyrational way. The second route is to exam<strong>in</strong>e what B should or couldhave done, had she acted <strong>in</strong> accordance with the objective logic <strong>of</strong>the situation, that is <strong>in</strong> an objectively rational fashion. 12 It is easy tosee that construction <strong>of</strong> what Weber calls subjectively rational idealtypes, pace Lachmann, produces straightforward <strong>in</strong>tentional orteleological explanations <strong>of</strong> <strong>in</strong>dividual action. Objectively rationalideal types, however, as explanatory frameworks have only, asWeber po<strong>in</strong>ts out, <strong>in</strong>strumental <strong>and</strong> heuristic value. 13Thus the logical structure <strong>of</strong> a subjectively rational ideal type isthe same as that <strong>of</strong> an <strong>in</strong>tentional explanation. In the simplestpossible case the explanatory argument runs as follows:96

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!