12.07.2015 Views

1 Studies in the History of Statistics and Probability ... - Sheynin, Oscar

1 Studies in the History of Statistics and Probability ... - Sheynin, Oscar

1 Studies in the History of Statistics and Probability ... - Sheynin, Oscar

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Mendelian laws. It is not sufficiently clear which conclusion has morenatural scientific sense: ei<strong>the</strong>r that <strong>the</strong> data do not agree with thoselaws, but that <strong>the</strong> discrepancy can be understood by a slight change <strong>of</strong>p (equal to 10%); or, that somewhat reluctantly we may suppose that<strong>the</strong>re is no obvious contradiction with those laws.However, En<strong>in</strong> provides some explanation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> possiblediscrepancy: <strong>the</strong> plants <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> hothouse sown <strong>in</strong> February suffered froma shortage <strong>of</strong> heat <strong>and</strong> light <strong>and</strong> a considerable part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sproutedseeds perished. Plants hav<strong>in</strong>g a recessive <strong>in</strong>dication could have wellhad a somewhat lower probability <strong>of</strong> survival (which should bechecked by a special experiment). The f<strong>in</strong>al results <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first seriescan be considered as some modest confirmation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> Mendelianlaws.We turn now to <strong>the</strong> second series. The pert<strong>in</strong>ent empiricaldistribution function on Fig. 3 is only badly smoo<strong>the</strong>d by a straightl<strong>in</strong>e (accord<strong>in</strong>g, however, to my somewhat subjective op<strong>in</strong>ion). In anycase, <strong>the</strong> scatter <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> observations is essentially less than supposed by<strong>the</strong> st<strong>and</strong>ard normal distribution. The most simple way to show it by astatistical criterion is to calculate <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> squares <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>observations. It is equal to 2.85 whereas its distribution (if <strong>the</strong> checkedhypo<strong>the</strong>sis is valid) is <strong>the</strong> chi-squared law with 14 degrees <strong>of</strong> freedom.As <strong>in</strong>dicated by <strong>the</strong> tables <strong>of</strong> that law, that value is thus practicallyimpossible. The value <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> statistics (2.7) is 0.33; with n = 14 that issignificant at about <strong>the</strong> 5% level.The shift <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> first series <strong>of</strong> observations was <strong>in</strong> some wayreasonably expla<strong>in</strong>ed; <strong>the</strong> second series has an <strong>in</strong>significant shift (<strong>the</strong>sample mean is − 0.21) but an essentially smaller than supposedvariance. The Mendelian laws are thus obeyed more precisely thansupposed which is hardly possible. The most probable statisticalconclusion is that <strong>the</strong> results were tampered with deliberately or not.The corruption <strong>of</strong> normality <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> distribution (<strong>the</strong> impossibility <strong>of</strong>smooth<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> empirical distribution by a straight l<strong>in</strong>e) also <strong>in</strong>dicatessome defect; however, for <strong>the</strong> given number <strong>of</strong> observations thisconclusion would be difficult to justify by a statistical test.In general, as far as was possible to ascerta<strong>in</strong>, <strong>the</strong> trouble isapparently that <strong>the</strong> experimental data are not provided <strong>in</strong> full. And so,it is possible to confirm <strong>the</strong> Mendelian laws while <strong>in</strong>tend<strong>in</strong>g to refute<strong>the</strong>m, <strong>and</strong> it is also possible to throw <strong>the</strong>m <strong>in</strong>to doubt when <strong>in</strong>tend<strong>in</strong>gto confirm <strong>the</strong>m, <strong>and</strong> all <strong>of</strong> this is revealed by a purely statistical<strong>in</strong>vestigation.Here, we encountered a curious violation <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> order be<strong>in</strong>gestablished <strong>in</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical statistics. When act<strong>in</strong>g strictlyscientifically, statistical tests should be chosen beforeh<strong>and</strong> <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong>experiment carried out <strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> verdict passed only afterwards.Actually, <strong>the</strong> tests are more <strong>of</strong>ten chosen by issu<strong>in</strong>g from peculiarities<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> material noted by naked eye. They serve for check<strong>in</strong>g whe<strong>the</strong>r<strong>the</strong>se peculiarities are statistically significant or not. However, hav<strong>in</strong>gestablished <strong>in</strong> our case that useful are tests based on <strong>the</strong> sample mean<strong>and</strong> <strong>the</strong> sum <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> squares <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> sample values, we could have, whenanalyz<strong>in</strong>g new similar material, strictly followed statistical science.105

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!