12.07.2015 Views

1 Studies in the History of Statistics and Probability ... - Sheynin, Oscar

1 Studies in the History of Statistics and Probability ... - Sheynin, Oscar

1 Studies in the History of Statistics and Probability ... - Sheynin, Oscar

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

VI<strong>Oscar</strong> Sheyn<strong>in</strong>On <strong>the</strong> Bernoulli Law <strong>of</strong> Large NumbersBernoulli considered (<strong>in</strong>dependent) trials with a constant probability<strong>of</strong> success, <strong>and</strong> rigorously proved that <strong>the</strong> frequency <strong>of</strong> success tendsto that probability. Mises, however, treated collectives, totalities <strong>of</strong>phenomena or events differ<strong>in</strong>g from each o<strong>the</strong>r <strong>in</strong> some <strong>in</strong>dication, <strong>and</strong>characterized by <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> limit<strong>in</strong>g frequency <strong>of</strong> success <strong>and</strong>by irregularity. The latter property meant that for any part <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>collective that limit<strong>in</strong>g frequency was <strong>the</strong> same.Alimov noted that artificially constructed collectives proved that <strong>the</strong>empirical frequency <strong>of</strong> success can become more stable as <strong>the</strong> number<strong>of</strong> trials <strong>in</strong>creased, but have no limit. Therefore, <strong>the</strong> existence <strong>of</strong> thatlimit is an experimental fact. I have described his viewpo<strong>in</strong>t <strong>in</strong> somedetail <strong>in</strong> an Introduction to [v]. Tutubal<strong>in</strong> largely sided with Alimov.In <strong>the</strong> same Ars Conject<strong>and</strong>i, previous to prov<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> LLN,Bernoulli stated that his law was also valid <strong>in</strong> its <strong>in</strong>verse sense (<strong>and</strong> DeMoivre <strong>in</strong>dependently stated <strong>the</strong> same with respect to <strong>the</strong> first version<strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> CLT proved by him <strong>in</strong> 1733). In o<strong>the</strong>r words, an unknown <strong>and</strong>even a non-exist<strong>in</strong>g probability (one <strong>of</strong> Bernoulli’s examples) could beestimated by <strong>the</strong> limit<strong>in</strong>g frequency.In a little known companion paper (1765) to his ma<strong>in</strong> memoir(1764), Bayes all but proved his own limit <strong>the</strong>orem explicat<strong>in</strong>g that<strong>in</strong>verse LLN. He did not make <strong>the</strong> f<strong>in</strong>al step from <strong>the</strong> case <strong>of</strong> a largef<strong>in</strong>ite number <strong>of</strong> trials because he opposed <strong>the</strong> application <strong>of</strong> divergentseries which was usual <strong>in</strong> those times. That was done <strong>in</strong> 1908 byTimerd<strong>in</strong>g, <strong>the</strong> Editor <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> German translation <strong>of</strong> Bayes, certa<strong>in</strong>lywithout us<strong>in</strong>g divergent series.Bayes – Timerd<strong>in</strong>g exam<strong>in</strong>ed <strong>the</strong> behaviour <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> centred <strong>and</strong>normed r<strong>and</strong>om variable η, <strong>the</strong> unknown probability, (η − Eη)/var ηwhereas <strong>the</strong> direct LLN dealt with <strong>the</strong> frequency ξ, (ξ − Eξ)/varξ. Hisma<strong>in</strong> memoir became widely known <strong>and</strong> for a long time <strong>the</strong> Bayesapproach had been fiercely opposed, partly because an unknownconstant was treated as a r<strong>and</strong>om variable (with a uniformdistribution). Note that varη > varξ which is quite natural s<strong>in</strong>ceprobability is only unknown <strong>in</strong> <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>verse case. For atta<strong>in</strong><strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> sameprecision <strong>the</strong> <strong>in</strong>verse case <strong>the</strong>refore dem<strong>and</strong>s more trials than <strong>the</strong> directlaw. Mises could have called Bayes his ma<strong>in</strong> predecessor; actually,however, he only described <strong>the</strong> work <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong> English ma<strong>the</strong>matician,<strong>and</strong> <strong>in</strong>adequately at that. Bayes completed <strong>the</strong> first stage <strong>of</strong> <strong>the</strong>development <strong>of</strong> probability <strong>the</strong>ory.Alimov’s viewpo<strong>in</strong>t was largely correct s<strong>in</strong>ce he considered an<strong>in</strong>comparably more general pattern than Bernoulli <strong>and</strong> thought about<strong>the</strong> necessary checks, but he [iv] was too radical <strong>in</strong> deny<strong>in</strong>g importantparts <strong>of</strong> ma<strong>the</strong>matical statistics as also too brave <strong>in</strong> alter<strong>in</strong>g <strong>the</strong> Misesapproach. To borrow an expression from Tutubal<strong>in</strong> [end <strong>of</strong> ii], he<strong>in</strong>troduced <strong>the</strong> Mises approach <strong>of</strong> a light-weighted type.139

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!