13.07.2015 Views

Contents - ResearchSpace@Auckland - The University of Auckland

Contents - ResearchSpace@Auckland - The University of Auckland

Contents - ResearchSpace@Auckland - The University of Auckland

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

natural world. This was a belief held earlier by the druids – and by the ancient Stoic philosophers whoalso accepted that the divinity could reside in the ‘mind <strong>of</strong> man’ and existed in nature, and as ‘Nature’,a divine power that did not exist apart from the physical world. This understanding was unacceptableto Augustine, who saw Pelagius’ beliefs as heretical, and instead preached a dualistic doctrine and theexistence <strong>of</strong> a transcendent deity. 4<strong>The</strong> Excursion, however, does not pursue an argument that arrives at any ‘certain’conclusions about theology, or about the mind <strong>of</strong> Man, Nature or Human Life. It is not dogmatic in itsphilosophising, and presents a philosophical dialogue set in ‘something <strong>of</strong> a dramatic form’ in whichthe characters speak their minds, and the reader is left to make his or her own conclusions, based onthe ‘evidence’ presented. <strong>The</strong> characters in the poem ‘invent’ a number <strong>of</strong> ‘arguments’ that arediscussed, at some length, as each <strong>of</strong> the eloquent speakers discourse on the matter at hand, addressingeach other, and also the mind <strong>of</strong> the reader. <strong>The</strong>re is no final resolution to this debate, or disputation,and readers are left to draw their own conclusions from the protracted dialogical display they have just‘witnessed’, in their mind’s eye, their imagination, as they read the poem.In this study I understand the term ‘imagination’ to refer, primarily, to the image-makingfaculty <strong>of</strong> the mind, the traditional understanding described by Aristotle in De Anima, as I argue thatWordsworth held the same understanding, and never intended the later more ‘Romantic’ definition <strong>of</strong>the word. Aristotle had written that:To the thinking soul images (phantasiae) serve as if they were contents <strong>of</strong> perception (andwhen it asserts or denies them to be good or bad it avoids or pursues them). That is why thesoul never thinks without an image’. (De Anima III 7. 431)<strong>The</strong> classical poetic tradition placed much emphasis on painting pictures in the mind’s eye <strong>of</strong> itsaudience/readers, and I argue that Wordsworth’s understanding <strong>of</strong> ‘imagination’ was primarilyconcerned with this function. At the same time, our phantasiae – the ‘impressions’ or ‘appearances’ inour minds which can be described also as ‘fancies’ (from the Greek term), or as ‘imaginations’ (fromthe Latin imago), are necessarily tied to sense impressions. In summarising his comments Aristotlemade two further points:No one can learn or understand anything in the absence <strong>of</strong> sense, and when the mind isactively aware <strong>of</strong> anything it is necessarily aware <strong>of</strong> it along with an image; for images arelike sensuous contents except in that they contain no matter’. (III 7. 432)Aristotle also maintained that although concepts were not images, ‘they necessarily involve them’. Histhinking on the matter was both metaphorical and literal, as he tried to account for philosophicaldistinctions as well as psychological experiences, and it is his more empirical concern with the4 Wordsworth’s more educated contemporary readers would have recognised that a description <strong>of</strong> a priestpresiding over a churchyard in the mountains could be an allusion to Rousseau’s Savoyard vicar whosecontroversial creed had earned Rousseau infamy in Europe among the established Christian orthodoxy.95

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!