02.11.2016 Views

UNDERGRADUATE

Ycb5305N2JX

Ycb5305N2JX

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

experience of the transcendence of its thingly character<br />

one is no longer capable (or as least easily so) of working<br />

around that painting. 2 This example in Heidegger is<br />

comparable with the rule that doctors are not allowed to<br />

treat their loved ones. A doctor, to an extent, must reduce<br />

the person they are treating down to solely a thingly being.<br />

They are treating flesh and bone, not the patient’s Dasein.<br />

A doctor cannot treat their loved ones because they are<br />

not capable of experiencing solely the thingly character of<br />

their beloved’s Dasein. They cannot work around it, much<br />

like the person who boxes the paintings cannot work<br />

around the painting that moves them. There then must<br />

be something in the experience of the Dasein of one’s<br />

beloved that thrusts one into the disclosedness of beings<br />

as such insofar as one cannot work around the Dasein<br />

of one’s beloved. This is how one can understand love<br />

insofar as it is a fundamental mood through Heidegger’s<br />

discussion of the aesthetic experience of an artwork that<br />

moves oneself.<br />

Let’s recall Heidegger’s exact language “Another<br />

possibility of such revelation is concealed in our joy in the<br />

presence of the Dasein—and not simply of the person—of<br />

a human being whom we love” (Basic Writings 99). In the<br />

presence of the Dasein of the person whom we love, the<br />

beloved is no longer simply a thing, but rather something<br />

more much like in the experience of the transcendence of<br />

the thingly character of a piece of art that moves us. The<br />

transformation of the beloved’s Dasein occurs in the act<br />

of falling in love, when the equipment-like character of<br />

the fellow human falls away, when the meaning normally<br />

attached to fellow humans is traded for something more<br />

than equipment. In love, the beloved’s Dasein accrues<br />

a new meaning, the equipment like quality of Others<br />

falls away, changed to something fundamental. In love,<br />

the beloved’s thing-ly body can be transcended, and yet<br />

the Dasein remains irreducibly present. The beloved is<br />

fundamental.<br />

To conclude, in this analysis I examined three of<br />

Heidegger’s works: What is Metaphysics, Being and Time,<br />

and The Origin of the Work of Art. I argued that we cannot<br />

conceptualize the fundamental mood of love in concert<br />

with the fundamental moods of anxiety or boredom but<br />

we can conceptualize and fit in the fundamental mood<br />

of love, or the experience of the beloved’s Dasein, with<br />

Heidegger’s discussion of both the conspicuousness of<br />

broken equipment and the transcendence of the thing-ly<br />

character of a work of art.<br />

2 On a personal note, as someone employed as an art handler, this is<br />

absolutely true. One time, after two straight days of examining and<br />

cleaning framed works of art, someone asked me which one of the pieces<br />

I was working with was my favorite. I had to take a step back and actually<br />

examine them as art, I had only been considering their thingly nature.<br />

WORKS CITED<br />

Heidegger, Martin. Basic Writings: From Being and Time and The Task<br />

of Thinking. Ed. David Farrell. Krell. New York: Harper Perennial Modern<br />

Thought, 2008. Print.<br />

Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarrie. Ed. Edward S.<br />

Robinson. New<br />

York: HarperPerennial/Modern Thought, 2008. Print.<br />

116 CREATING KNOWLEDGE

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!