10.12.2012 Views

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

Do Judgments Screen Evidence? 233<br />

our basis for p, and yet we have good (if misleading) grounds for believing E does not<br />

support p. Here’s his setup of the debate.<br />

Consider a person who has some evidence, E, concerning a proposition,<br />

p, and also has some evidence about whether E is good evidence for p.<br />

I will say that the person is respecting the evidence about E and p when<br />

the person’s belief concerning p corresponds to what is indicated by the<br />

person’s evidence about E’s support for p. That is, a person respects the<br />

evidence about E and p by believing p when his or her evidence indicates<br />

that this evidence supports p or by not believing p when the evidence<br />

indicates that this evidence does not support p. (Feldman 2005: 95-6)<br />

Feldman goes on to argue that we should respect the evidence. Obviously I disagree.<br />

If E is all the agent’s evidence, then the agent’s attitude towards p should be determined<br />

by how strongly E supports p. One case that strongly suggests this is when<br />

the agent has no evidence whatsoever about how E supports p, so the agent’s evidence<br />

indicates nothing about E’s support for p. If that implies that the agent can’t<br />

have any attitudes about p, then we are led quickly into an unpleasant regress.<br />

But the main point I want to make here concerns the arguments that Feldman<br />

makes for respecting the evidence. It is true that sometimes disrespecting the evidence<br />

has counterintuitive consequences. See, for example, Feldman’s example of the<br />

baseball website (Feldman 2005: 112) or, for that matter, the discussion of kitchen<br />

scales in the previous subsection. But other cases might point the other way. Is it<br />

really intuitive that the student can’t soundly infer p from ¬¬ p after hearing some<br />

lectures from a talented but mistaken intuitionistic logician? I think intuition is sufficiently<br />

confused here that we should rely on other evidence. Feldman’s primary<br />

argument concerns the oddity of the position I’m defending. In his taxonomy of<br />

views, ‘View 1’ is the view that when an agent has evidence E, which is in fact good<br />

evidence for p, and gets misleading evidence that E does not in fact support p, then<br />

she can know p, but not know that she knows p. That’s what I think happens at<br />

least some of the time, at least when the connection between E and p is basic, so his<br />

arguments are meant to tell against my position.<br />

View 1... has the implication that a person could be in a situation in<br />

which she justifiably denies or suspends judgment about whether her<br />

basis for believing a proposition is a good one, but nevertheless justifiably<br />

believes the proposition. Imagine such a person reporting her situation:<br />

“ p, but of course I have no idea whether my evidence for p is any good.”<br />

At the very least, this sounds odd. (Feldman 2005: 105)<br />

He later goes into more detail on this point.<br />

View 1 leads to the conclusion that our student can correctly believe<br />

things such as<br />

6. T , but my overall evidence does not support T .

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!