10.12.2012 Views

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

David Lewis 76<br />

to there being at least one world. As (Melia, 1992, 192) points out though, the inhabitants<br />

of those worlds include all kinds of things not found in, or reducible to,<br />

fundamental physics. They include spirits, gods, trolls and every other consistent<br />

beast imaginable. So at least when it came to what there is, as opposed to what there<br />

actually is, Lewis’s ontology was rather expansionist.<br />

For all that, Lewis’s default attitude was to accept that much of our commonsense<br />

thinking about the nomic, the intentional and the normative was correct, and<br />

that this was perfectly compatible with this world containing nothing more than is<br />

found in science, indeed than is found in fundamental physics.<br />

Compatibilists should solve what Frank Jackson calls ‘the location problem’ (Jackson<br />

1998). If you think that there are, say, beliefs, and you think that having beliefs in<br />

one’s metaphysics doesn’t commit you to having anything in your ontology beyond<br />

fundamental physics, then you should, as Jackson puts it, be able to locate beliefs<br />

in the world described by fundamental physics. More generally, for whatever you<br />

accept, you should be able to locate it in the picture of the world you accept.<br />

This was certainly the methodology that Lewis accepted. And since he thought<br />

that so much of our common sense worldview was compatible with fundamental<br />

physics, he had many versions of the location problem to solve. One way to go<br />

about this would be to find exactly what the correct scientific theory is, and locate all<br />

the relevant properties in that picture. But this method has some shortcomings. For<br />

one thing, it might mean having to throw out your metaphysical work whenever the<br />

scientific theories change. For another, it means having your metaphysics caught up<br />

in debates about the best scientific theories, and about their interpretation. So Lewis<br />

took a somewhat different approach.<br />

What Lewis’s defence of Humean supervenience gives us is a recipe for locating<br />

the nomic, intentional and normative properties in a physical world. And it is a<br />

recipe that uses remarkably few ingredients; just intrinsic properties of point-sized<br />

objects, and spatio-temporal relations. It is likely that ideal physics will have more<br />

in it than that. For instance, it might have entanglement relations, as are needed<br />

to explain Bell’s inequality. But it is unlikely to have less. And the more there is<br />

in fundamental physics, the easier it is to solve the location problem, because the<br />

would-be locator has more resources to work with.<br />

The upshot of all this is that a philosophical defence of Humean supervenience,<br />

especially a defence like Lewis’s that shows us explicitly how to locate various folk<br />

properties in classical physics, is likely to show us how to locate those properties in<br />

more up-to-date physics. So Lewis’s defence of Humean supervenience then generalises<br />

into a defence of the compatibility of large swathes of folk theory with ideal<br />

physics. And the defence is consistent with the realist principle that truth supervenes<br />

on being, and with the Humean denial of necessary connections between distinct<br />

existences. And that, quite clearly, is a philosophically interesting project.<br />

6 Modal Realism<br />

This entry has been stressing Lewis’s many and diverse contributions to philosophy.<br />

But there is one thesis with which he is associated above all others: modal realism.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!