10.12.2012 Views

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

David Lewis 54<br />

that, and it is common knowledge in P that, in almost any instance of S<br />

among members of P,<br />

1. almost everyone conforms to R;<br />

2. almost everyone expects everyone else to conform to R;<br />

3. almost everyone has approximately the same preferences regarding<br />

all possible combinations of actions;<br />

4. almost everyone prefers that any one more conform to R, on condition<br />

that almost everyone conform to R;<br />

5. almost everyone would prefer that any one more conform to R ′ , on<br />

condition that almost everyone conform to R ′ ,<br />

where R ′ is some possible regularity in the behaviour of members of P in<br />

S, such that almost no one in almost any instance of S among members<br />

of P could conform to both R ′ and to R. (Lewis, 1969a, 78)<br />

This is clearly a vague definition, with many ‘almost’s scattered throughout. But<br />

Lewis, characteristically, thought this was a feature not a bug of the view. Our intuitive<br />

notion of a convention is vague, and any analysis of it should capture the vagueness.<br />

The idea that analyses of imprecise folk concepts should be imprecise recurs<br />

throughout Lewis’s career.<br />

The notion of ‘common knowledge’ that Lewis is working with here is not the<br />

standard modern notion. Lewis does not require that everyone know that everyone<br />

know etc., that all of these conditions hold. Rather, when Lewis says that it is common<br />

knowledge that p, he means that everyone has a reason to believe that p, and<br />

everyone has a reason to believe everyone has a reason to believe that p, and everyone<br />

has a reason to believe that everyone has a reason to believe everyone has a reason to<br />

believe that p, and so on. That people act on these reasons, or are known to act on<br />

these reasons, to form beliefs is unnecessary. And that the beliefs people would get if<br />

they acted on their reasons are true is also not part of the view. Hence it is necessary<br />

to specify truth as well as common belief in the definition.<br />

Lewis argues that this definition captures many of our ordinary conventions, such<br />

as the convention of driving on the right side of the road in the United States, the<br />

convention of taking certain pieces of paper as payments for debts, and, most importantly,<br />

the conventions governing the use of language.<br />

2.2 Conventions of Language<br />

In the final chapter of Convention, Lewis gives his theory of what it is for a community<br />

to speak a language (see the section on conventional theories of meaning in the<br />

entry on convention), i.e., for a community to have adopted one language as their<br />

language by convention. Lewis individuates languages largely by the truth conditions<br />

they assign to sentences. And his account of truth conditions is given in terms<br />

of possible worlds. So the truth condition of an indicative sentence is the set of possible<br />

worlds in which it is true. Somewhat more abnormally, Lewis takes the truth<br />

condition for an imperative to be the set of possible worlds in which the imperative

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!