10.12.2012 Views

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

Dogmatism and Intuitionistic Probability 566<br />

We’ll just go through the argument for (a); the other cases are similar. By P6, we<br />

know that P r x (¬(Ap ∧ ¬ p)|Ap)P r x (Ap) = P r x ((Ap → p) ∧ Ap). By Theorem 3,<br />

we know that P r x (Ap) = P r x ((Ap → p) ∧ Ap), and that both sides are greater than<br />

0. (Note that the theorem is only said to hold for x > 0.) The only way both these<br />

equations can hold is if P r x (¬(Ap ∧ ¬ p)|Ap) = 1. Note also that by hypothesis,<br />

x < 1, and from this claim (a) follows. The other two cases are completely similar.<br />

Theorem 5 Let P r 1 be a regular conditional ⊢ C L -probability function,<br />

and P r 2 be a regular conditional ⊢ I L -probability function that is not a<br />

⊢ C L -probability function. And let P r 3 be defined as in the text. (That is,<br />

P r 3 (A) = xP r 1 (A) + (1 − x)P r 2 (A), and P r 3 (A|B) = P r 3 (A∧B)<br />

P r 3 (B) .) Then P r 3<br />

is a regular conditional ⊢ I L -probability function.<br />

We first prove that P r 3 satisfies the requirements of an unconditional ⊢ I L -probability<br />

function, and then show that it satisfies the requirements of a conditional ⊢ I L -probability<br />

function.<br />

If p is an ⊢ I L -antithesis, then it is also a ⊢ C L -antithesis. So P r 1 ( p) = P r 2 ( p) = 0.<br />

So P r 3 (A) = 0x + 0(1 − x) = 0, as required for (P0).<br />

If p is an ⊢ I L -thesis, then it is also a ⊢ C L -thesis. So P r 1 ( p) = P r 2 ( p) = 1. So<br />

P r 3 ( p) = x + (1 − x) = 1, as required for (P1).<br />

If p ⊢ I L q then p ⊢ C L q. So we have both P r 1 ( p) ≤ P r (q) and P r 2 ( p) ≤ P r 2 (q).<br />

Since x ≥ 0 and (1 − x) ≥ 0, these inequalities imply that xP r 1 ( p) ≤ xP r (q) and<br />

(1 − x)P r 2 ( p) ≤ (1 − x)P r 2 (q). Summing these, we get xP r 1 ( p) + (1 − x)P r 2 ( p) ≤<br />

xP r 1 (q) + (1 − x)P r 2 (q). And by the definition of P r 3 , that means that P r 3 ( p) ≤<br />

P r 3 (q), as required for (P2).<br />

Finally, we just need to show that P r 3 ( p) + P r 3 (q) = P r 3 ( p ∨ q) + P r 3 ( p ∧ q), as<br />

follows:<br />

P r 3 ( p) + P r 3 (q) = xP r 1 ( p) + (1 − x)P r 2 ( p) + xP r 1 (q) + (1 − x)P r 2 (q)<br />

= x(P r 1 ( p) + P r 1 (q)) + (1 − x)(P r 2 ( p) + P r 2 (q))<br />

= x(P r 1 ( p ∨ q) + P r 1 ( p ∧ q)) + (1 − x)(P r 2 ( p ∨ q) + P r 2 ( p ∧ q))<br />

= xP r 1 ( p ∨ q) + (1 − x)P r 2 ( p ∨ q) + xP r 1 ( p ∧ q)) + (1 − x)P r 2 ( p ∧ q)<br />

= P r 3 ( p ∨ q) + P r 3 ( p ∧ q) as required<br />

Now that we have shown P r 3 is an unconditional ⊢ I L -probability function, we need<br />

to show it is a conditional ⊢ I L -probability function, where P r 3 ( p|r ) = d f<br />

P r 3 ( p∧r )<br />

P r 3 (r ) .<br />

Remember we are assuming that both P r 1 and P r 2 are regular, from which it clearly<br />

follows that P r 3 is regular, so this definition is always in order. (That is, we’re never<br />

dividing by zero.) The longest part of showing P r 3 is a conditional ⊢ I L -probability<br />

function is showing that it satisfies (P4), which has four parts. We need to show that<br />

P r (·|r ) satisfies (P0)-(P3). Fortunately these are fairly straightforward.<br />

If p is an ⊢ I L -antithesis, then so is p ∧ r . So P r 3 ( p ∧ r ) = 0, so P r 3 ( p|r ) = 0, as<br />

required for (P0).

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!