10.12.2012 Views

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

David Lewis 88<br />

7.5 Ethics<br />

Lewis is obviously not as well known for his work in ethics as for his work in other<br />

areas of philosophy. It was something of a surprise when one of the volumes of his<br />

collected papers was called <strong>Papers</strong> in Ethics and Social Philosophy (2000). On the other<br />

hand, the existence of this volume indicates that there is a large body of work that<br />

Lewis put together in moral philosophy, very broadly construed. The best guide to<br />

this work is chapter 8 of Nolan (2005), and I’ll follow Nolan very closely here.<br />

As Nolan suggests, the least inaccurate summary of Lewis’s ethical positions is<br />

that he was a virtue ethicist. Indeed, a focus on virtue, as opposed to consequences,<br />

plays a role in his defence of modal realism, as we saw in section 6.4. Nolan also<br />

notes that this position is somewhat surprising. Most philosophers who accept views<br />

related to Lewis’s about psychology and decision-making (in particular, who accept<br />

a Humean story about beliefs and desires being the basis for motivation, and who<br />

accept some or other version of expected utility maximisation as the basis for rational<br />

decision) have broadly consequentialist positions. But not Lewis.<br />

Lewis was also a value pluralist (1984a; 1989b; 1993a). Indeed, this was part of<br />

his objection to consequentialism. He rejected the idea that there was one summary<br />

judgment we could make about the moral value of a person. In “Reply to McMichael”<br />

(1978a) he complains about the utilitarian assumption that “any sort or amount of<br />

evil can be neutralized, as if it had never been, by enough countervailing good —and<br />

that the balancing evil and good may be entirely unrelated” (1978a, 85).<br />

In meta-ethics, Lewis defended a variety of subjectivism (1989b). Like many subjectivists,<br />

Lewis held that something is valuable for us iff we would value it under<br />

ideal circumstances. And he held, following Frankfurt (1971), that valuing something<br />

is simply desiring to desire it. What is distinctive about Lewis’s position is his<br />

view about what ideal circumstances are. He thinks they are circumstances of “full<br />

imaginative acquaintance”. This has some interesting consequences. In particular, it<br />

allows Lewis to say that different goods have different conditions of full imaginative<br />

acquaintance. It might, he suggests, be impossible to properly imagine instantiating<br />

several different values at once. And that in turn lets him argue that his value<br />

pluralism is consistent with this kind of subjectivism, in a way that it might not be<br />

consistent with other varieties of subjectivism.<br />

Lewis also wrote several more papers in applied ethics. In two interesting papers<br />

on tolerance (1989a; 1989c), he suggests that one reason for being tolerant, and<br />

especially of being tolerant of speech we disapprove of, comes from game-theoretic<br />

considerations. In particular, he thinks our motivation for tolerance comes from<br />

forming a ‘tacit treaty’ with those with differing views. If we agree not to press our<br />

numerical superiority to repress them when we are in the majority, they will do the<br />

same. So tolerating opposing views may be an optimal strategy for anyone who isn’t<br />

sure that they will be in the majority indefinitely. In these works it is easy to see<br />

the legacies of Lewis’s early work on philosophical lessons to be drawn from game<br />

theory, and especially from the work of Thomas Schelling.

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!