10.12.2012 Views

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

Online Papers - Brian Weatherson

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

David Lewis 66<br />

of a belief is a property. To believe something then is to locate yourself within a<br />

class of possible individuals; to believe that you are one of the individuals with the<br />

property. More simply, beliefs are the self-ascriptions of properties.<br />

Within this framework, it is easy to resolve the puzzles we addressed at the top of<br />

the section. If I believe that BW is a crook, I self-ascribe the property of inhabiting<br />

a world in which BW is a crook. (On Lewis’s theory, beliefs that are not explicitly<br />

self-locating will be beliefs about which world one is in.) If I believe I am not a crook,<br />

I self-ascribe the property of not being a crook. Since there are possible individuals<br />

who are (a) not crooks but (b) in worlds where BW is a crook, this is a consistent<br />

self-ascription. Indeed, I may even have strong evidence that I have both of these<br />

properties. So there is no threat of inconsistency, or even irrationality here.<br />

Lewis’s suggestion about how to think of self-locating mental states has recently<br />

been very influential in a variety of areas. Adam Elga (2000a, 2004a) has extensively<br />

investigated the consequences of Lewis’s approach for decision theory. Andy Egan<br />

(2007a) has developed a novel form of semantic relativism using Lewis’s approach<br />

as a model. Daniel Nolan (2007) has recently argued that Lewis’s approach is less<br />

plausible for desire than for belief, and Robert Stalnaker (2008a) argues that the view<br />

makes the wrong judgments about sameness and difference of belief across agents and<br />

times.<br />

4.6 Natural Properties<br />

One classic problem for interpretationism is that our dispositions massively underdetermine<br />

contents. I believe that (healthy) grass is green. But for some interpretations<br />

of ‘grue’, ascribing to me the belief that grass is grue will fit my dispositions just as<br />

well. As Lewis points out towards the end of “New Work For a Theory of Universals”<br />

(1983c), if we are allowed to change the interpretations of my beliefs and desires<br />

at the same time, the fit can be made even better. This looks like a problem for<br />

interpretationism.<br />

The problem is of course quite familiar. In different guises it is Goodman’s<br />

grue/green problem, Kripkenstein’s plus/quus problem, Quine’s gavagai problem,<br />

and Putnam’s puzzle of the brain in a vat with true beliefs (Goodman, 1955; Wittgenstein,<br />

1953; Kripke, 1982; Quine, 1960; Putnam, 1981). One way or another it<br />

has to be solved.<br />

Lewis’s solution turns on a metaphysical posit. Some properties, he says, are<br />

more natural than others. The natural properties are those that, to use an ancient<br />

phrase, carve nature at the joints. They make for objective resemblance amongst the<br />

objects that have them, and objective dissimilarity between things that have them<br />

and those that lack them. The natural properties, but not in general the unnatural<br />

properties, are relevant to the causal powers of things. Although science is in the<br />

business of discovering which natural properties are instantiated, when Lewis talks<br />

about natural properties he doesn’t mean properties given a special role by nature. It<br />

is not a contingent matter which properties are natural, because it isn’t a contingent<br />

matter which properties make for objective similarity.<br />

Some properties are perfectly natural. Other properties are less natural, but not<br />

all unnatural properties are alike. Green things are a diverse and heterogeneous

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!