01.06.2013 Views

Statistical Methods in Medical Research 4ed

Statistical Methods in Medical Research 4ed

Statistical Methods in Medical Research 4ed

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

You also want an ePaper? Increase the reach of your titles

YUMPU automatically turns print PDFs into web optimized ePapers that Google loves.

622 Cl<strong>in</strong>ical trials<br />

A somewhat different situation may arise if the <strong>in</strong>terim results for, say, two<br />

treatments are very similar, and when it can be predicted that the f<strong>in</strong>al difference<br />

would almost certa<strong>in</strong>ly be non-significant. <strong>Methods</strong> for curtail<strong>in</strong>g a trial under<br />

these circumstances have been proposed by many authors (Schneiderman &<br />

Armitage, 1962; Lan et al., 1982 (us<strong>in</strong>g the term stochastic curtailment); Ware<br />

et al., 1985 (us<strong>in</strong>g the term futility); Spiegelhalter & Freedman, 1988 (us<strong>in</strong>g<br />

Bayesian methods)). Boundaries permitt<strong>in</strong>g stochastic curtailment can be <strong>in</strong>corporated<br />

<strong>in</strong>to schemes permitt<strong>in</strong>g early stopp<strong>in</strong>g for efficacy effects and are easily<br />

implemented with EaSt or PEST.<br />

Although this approach may be useful <strong>in</strong> enabl<strong>in</strong>g research efforts to be<br />

switched to more promis<strong>in</strong>g directions, there is a danger <strong>in</strong> plac<strong>in</strong>g too much<br />

importance on the predicted results of a f<strong>in</strong>al significance test. Data show<strong>in</strong>g<br />

non-significant treatment effects may nevertheless be valuable for estimation,<br />

especially <strong>in</strong> contribut<strong>in</strong>g to meta-analyses (see §18.10). It may be unwise to<br />

term<strong>in</strong>ate such studies prematurely, particularly when there is no treatment<br />

difference to provide an ethical reason for stopp<strong>in</strong>g.<br />

Other considerations<br />

The methods described <strong>in</strong> this section have been developed ma<strong>in</strong>ly from a non-<br />

Bayesian po<strong>in</strong>t of view. As <strong>in</strong>dicated earlier, <strong>in</strong> the Bayesian approach the<br />

stopp<strong>in</strong>g rule is irrelevant to the <strong>in</strong>ferences to be made at any stage. A trial<br />

could reasonably be stopped whenever the posterior distribution suggested<br />

strong evidence of a clear advantage for one treatment. This approach to the<br />

design, analysis and monitor<strong>in</strong>g of cl<strong>in</strong>ical trials has been strongly advocated, for<br />

<strong>in</strong>stance, by Berry (1987) and Spiegelhalter et al. (1994). Grossman et al. (1994)<br />

have discussed the design of group sequential trials which preserve Type I error<br />

probabilities and yet <strong>in</strong>volve boundaries determ<strong>in</strong>ed by a Bayesian formulation,<br />

the prior distribution represent<strong>in</strong>g <strong>in</strong>itial scepticism about the possible treatment<br />

effect.<br />

We have assumed, <strong>in</strong> describ<strong>in</strong>g repeated significance tests, that the null<br />

hypothesis specifies a lack of difference <strong>in</strong> efficacy between treatments. It may<br />

be useful to base a stopp<strong>in</strong>g rule on tests of a specific non-zero difference (Meier,<br />

1975; Freedman et al., 1984; see also §4.6, p. 140, and the discussion of equivalence<br />

trials <strong>in</strong> §18.9). All the sequential methods outl<strong>in</strong>ed here can be adapted by<br />

bas<strong>in</strong>g the boundaries on tests of the required non-zero values.<br />

The rather bewilder<strong>in</strong>g variety of methods available for data monitor<strong>in</strong>g can<br />

perhaps be put <strong>in</strong>to perspective by the widely held view that all such rules should<br />

be treated flexibly, as guidel<strong>in</strong>es rather than rigid prescriptions. Many authors<br />

would argue that a DMC should def<strong>in</strong>e a stopp<strong>in</strong>g rule at the outset, even though<br />

its implementation is flexible. Others (Armitage, 1999) have favoured a more<br />

open approach, without a formal def<strong>in</strong>ition of the stopp<strong>in</strong>g rule, but with a

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!