10.06.2013 Views

vector 2_1.cdr - Universitatea de Arte "George Enescu"

vector 2_1.cdr - Universitatea de Arte "George Enescu"

vector 2_1.cdr - Universitatea de Arte "George Enescu"

SHOW MORE
SHOW LESS

Create successful ePaper yourself

Turn your PDF publications into a flip-book with our unique Google optimized e-Paper software.

critical condition: frontiers<br />

154<br />

Art and space perception<br />

Vlad MORARIU<br />

Vlad Morariu graduated the<br />

Philosophy Faculty from “Al. I.<br />

Cuza” University of Iaşi. At present,<br />

he attends the master courses at<br />

the same faculty and he is a<br />

Erasmus exchange stu<strong>de</strong>nt for<br />

Humboldt University Berlin.<br />

The rebellion against the white cube means life's coming into its own<br />

rights. A double causality un<strong>de</strong>rtakes the existential possibilities of the<br />

contemporary gallery: on the one hand, the street, as symbol of<br />

everyday life and of truly lived experiences, finds itself a place within<br />

the gallery, on the other hand, the artistic object, as every-day life's<br />

product, becomes itself an autonomous world, capable of <strong>de</strong>termining<br />

transfigurations within the society where it is being born. To<br />

experiment an artistic event nowadays supposes the approach of the<br />

choros: both from the point of view of the subject's aesthetic<br />

experience, the choros itself being able to make possible any<br />

un<strong>de</strong>rstanding, and from the point of view of what is being<br />

experienced, subsisting in the artist's and curator's concern for the<br />

right space.<br />

What does experiencing artistic situations created in an exhibition space<br />

suppose? Put it this way, the question announces a critical step, in its full-blown<br />

Kantian meaning; therefore, to answer the question, we have to search for the<br />

conditions of possibility of the artistic events' setting-frame at the level of one's<br />

experience within the exhibition space. A close analysis will have as result the<br />

revealing of the basic structure that this type of experience supposes; namely,<br />

on the one hand, the human subject, who enters the exhibition space and who is<br />

ready to have a certain aesthetic experience; on the other hand, the object of<br />

his/her own experience, the artistic object as such. On these grounds, the initial<br />

question and the searching for its answer bare a greater significance as we<br />

become aware of the diversity of the exhibition contexts of contemporary art.<br />

Museums, galleries, artistic venues, non-conventional spaces, all these,<br />

although structurally different, have a common feature: the artistic object is not<br />

exhibited at random, the artist and the curator work together to find the right<br />

place for its displaying; moreover, the contemporary art has allowed some types<br />

of work to <strong>de</strong>al exclusively with the characteristics of the exhibition space and<br />

which, as a final product, say something about their living environment.<br />

Therefore, space does not interfere within the relation between the subject and<br />

the object of an aesthetic experience as something exterior, but it is part and<br />

parcel of this. Consecutively, the exhibition space becomes a place, namely a<br />

space cognitively and emotionally experimented. Becoming a place, the space<br />

cannot be reduced to dimensionality any more, hence supposing a certain<br />

conception, a vision of the world in which both the artist and the lecturer of<br />

his/her work live. Following this, the space becomes an essential<br />

constituent of this world. But, if this thing is true, then an answer to the question<br />

about experiencing artistic situations created within an exhibition space will<br />

suppose a step towards the clarification of the ways in which we conceive the<br />

space in its generality.<br />

1. Choros and space in the Greek tradition, mo<strong>de</strong>rnity and the<br />

postmo<strong>de</strong>rn turning<br />

The concern for mapping the Earth's surface, for explaining the nature<br />

and the regions' position has always been the Geographers' main activity. But<br />

this text doesn't <strong>de</strong>al with the quantitative measure of a space or with the<br />

mathematical functions related to it. They talk about a <strong>de</strong>ad, abstract space.<br />

What we are trying to do here is to i<strong>de</strong>ntify an inhabited space, the place, for<br />

which any geography is impossible. Seen from this perspective, two other<br />

concepts come at hand: topos and choros. If the first one has easily found a place<br />

within the history of i<strong>de</strong>as, the second one had a discrete existence, sometimes<br />

unperceived. Used by the Greeks, choros disappears for almost two thousand<br />

years in or<strong>de</strong>r to be rediscovered recently, in Jacques Derrida's and Julia<br />

Kristeva's texts which place Plato's dialogue Timaeus and his discussion about<br />

chora in a new light. But what do the two concepts <strong>de</strong>signate? The ol<strong>de</strong>r one,<br />

choros, meant, even before the Plato-Aristotle period, the subjective<br />

significances attributed to a space, the emotional state <strong>de</strong>termined by<br />

someone's presence in a certain place. Opposing choros, topos took into account<br />

1<br />

the objective characteristics of the space . During Ptolemy there were already<br />

two traditions, a chorographical one and a topographical one: while the first one<br />

was <strong>de</strong>aling with the nature of regions (their qualitative <strong>de</strong>scription, which<br />

supposed an explanation given to the nature of the cultures and civilizations<br />

that were inhabiting these regions, of their relationship with the Divinity), the<br />

second one, surviving till nowadays by means of oral techniques, contemporary<br />

topography or journey diaries, initially supposed mnemonic abilities (abilities of<br />

memorizing and reproducing orally a narrative about the visited places during a<br />

trip, a narrative that usually bore a powerful infusion of symbols), eventually, the<br />

2<br />

ability of drawing becoming a necessity . For the purposes of this study, I will<br />

leave asi<strong>de</strong> any discussion about topos and topography. But, in what concerns<br />

3<br />

the choros, let us remember that in Timaeus, Plato <strong>de</strong>velops an ontology which<br />

divi<strong>de</strong>s the reality into three types: I<strong>de</strong>as or Immobile Forms (first type), their<br />

4<br />

imperfect copies (second type) and receptacle, chora (triton genos ). Plato<br />

admits it that chora is an obscure term and consi<strong>de</strong>rs that its signification can be<br />

best ren<strong>de</strong>red by analogy, associating to it a series of images, among which the<br />

5 6<br />

one of an impressive thing , of a piece of gold out of which different shapes come<br />

7<br />

into being, or of mother and father creating the offspring . All these images<br />

suggest that the receptacle is a material substratum, but nevertheless, Plato<br />

8<br />

uses the spatial concept of chora , its role being that of offering a place, a special<br />

position to the copies which, temporarily, take a certain shape. Therefore, for<br />

Plato, chora is that space which can be thought only together with the things<br />

contained in itself; it offers shape and spatio-temporal position to any placed<br />

particular, but it is also the medium where the relationships among different<br />

particular things take place. We can find the same i<strong>de</strong>a of choros, of particular,<br />

subjective space, also in Aristotle's Physics, when he argues that every thing has<br />

its own place and that every movement is a movement towards that place, where<br />

9<br />

every thing ceases . Yet, the same work produces the seed of a new conception<br />

[1] See Michael R. Curry,<br />

“Discursive Displacement and the<br />

Seminal Ambiguity of Space and<br />

Place”, in The Handbook of New<br />

Media, editors: Leah Lievrouw and<br />

Sonia Livingstone, Sage<br />

Publications, London, 2002, pp.<br />

504-505,<br />

http://www.geog.ucla.edu/~curry/<br />

Curry_Disc_Disp.pdf<br />

[2] ibi<strong>de</strong>m, p. 506.<br />

[3] Ontology is that part of<br />

philosophy which answers the<br />

questions about existence. It<br />

supposes a systematical research<br />

upon the reality's constituents and<br />

the relation-ship among them.<br />

[4] See Plato, “Timaios”, in Opere,<br />

vol.6, 48e, Editura Ştiinţifică şi<br />

Enciclopedică, Bucureşti, 1989; for<br />

the english translation see for<br />

example Bury, R. G., (ed. and tr.),<br />

1960, Plato: Timaeus, Critias,<br />

Cleitophon, Menexenus, Epistles,<br />

Cambridge, Mass.: Loeb Classical<br />

Library.<br />

[5] ibi<strong>de</strong>m, 50c, 50e- 51a.<br />

[6] ibi<strong>de</strong>m, 50a-50b.<br />

[7] ibi<strong>de</strong>m, 50d, 51a.<br />

[8] See also Zeyl, Donald, “Plato's<br />

Timaeus”, The Stanford Encyclopedia<br />

of Philosophy (Winter 2005<br />

Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.),<br />

.<br />

[9] Aristotle, Fizica, 211a, 3-5;<br />

Editura Ştiinţifica, Bucureşti, 1966;<br />

for the english translation, see for<br />

example Aristotle, “Physica”, in<br />

Richard McKeon (ed.), The Basic<br />

Works of Aristotle, trans. R.P.<br />

Hardie and R.K. Gaye, New York,<br />

Random House, 1941, pp. 218-<br />

397.<br />

155

Hooray! Your file is uploaded and ready to be published.

Saved successfully!

Ooh no, something went wrong!